View original document

The full text on this page is automatically extracted from the file linked above and may contain errors and inconsistencies.

Working Paper Series

Loan Guarantees for Consumer Credit
Markets

WP 11-06

Kartik Athreya
Federal Reserve Bank of Richmond
Xuan S. Tam
University of Cambridge
Eric R. Young
University of Virginia

This paper can be downloaded without charge from:
http://www.richmondfed.org/publications/

Loan Guarantees for Consumer Credit Markets∗
Kartik Athreya†

Xuan S. Tam‡

Eric R. Young§

Research Department

CFAP

Department of Economics

FRB-Richmond

University of Cambridge

University of Virginia

September 30, 2011
Working Paper No. 11-06

Abstract
Loan guarantees are arguably the most widely used policy intervention in credit markets,
especially for consumers. This may be natural, as they have several features that, a priori,
suggest that they might be particularly effective in improving allocations. However, despite
this, little is actually known about the size of their effects on prices, allocations, and welfare.
In this paper, we provide a quantitative assessment of loan guarantees, in the context of
unsecured consumption loans. Our work is novel as it studies loan guarantees in a rich dynamic
model where credit allocation is allowed to be affected by both limited commitment frictions
and private information.
Our findings suggest that consumer loan guarantees may be a powerful tool to alter allocations that, if carefully arranged, can improve welfare, sometimes significantly. Specifically, our
key findings are that (i) under both symmetric and asymmetric information, guaranteeing small
consumer loans nontrivially alters allocations, and strikingly, yields welfare improvements even
after a key form of uncertainty–one’s human capital level–has been realized, (ii) larger guarantees change allocations very significantly, but lower welfare, sometimes for all household-types,
and (iii) substantial further gains are available when guarantees are restricted to households hit
by large expenditure shocks.

∗

We thank Larry Ausubel, Dean Corbae, Martin Gervais, Kevin Reffett, and participants in seminars at Arizona
State, Georgia, Iowa, and the Consumer Credit and Bankruptcy Conference at the University of Cambridge for helpful
comments and discussions. We also thank Brian Gaines and Jon Lecznar for assistance. The opinions expressed
here are not necessarily those of the Federal Reserve Bank of Richmond or the Federal Reserve System. Keywords:
Bankruptcy, Unsecured Credit, Loan Guarantees JEL Codes: H81, D82, D91, E21.
†

E-mail: kartik.athreya@rich.frb.org.
E-mail: xst20@cam.ac.uk.
§
E-mail: ey2d@virginia.edu.
‡

1. Introduction
In the US and many other developed nations, arguably the most important class of interventions in
household credit markets are publicly-funded guarantees issued to private lenders to defray losses
from default. In the U.S., the most obvious of these are the loan guarantee programs for home
loans. Currently, for example, the FHA and the Veterans Administration both offer loan guarantees
to private lenders that are explicitly backed by the “full faith and credit” of the Federal government
to qualified home buyers, and in both 2009 and 2010, the FHA alone originated over $300 billion
in new guaranteed loans. Similarly, the US Student Loan Administration (Sallie Mae) is active in
arranging guaranteed loans, with recent flows on the order of $100 billion annually, and a stock of
approximately $500 billion. Loan-guarantees also play a role in credit aimed at the self-employed,
with the U.S. Small Business Administration’s (SBA) 7a loan program guaranteeing roughly $100
billion in credit per decade since 1990.12
Beyond their sheer size, the scope of activities receiving guarantees is noteworthy. Endeavors ranging from nuclear and solar power plant construction, trade credit, micro-enterprises, and
support for female-entrepreneurs are all ones that have received, or currently receive, guaranteed
loans. In some instances, the guarantees are motivated by the premise of externalities. Others,
such as the guarantees on student loans, are motivated by additional considerations, especially a
quantitative presumption over the strength of limited commitment problems (such as those arising
from the private sector’s statutory inability to attach human capital, in the case of student loans),
as well as the desire to alleviate “rationing” induced by private information.
The goal of this paper is to provide a quantitative assessment of the price-, allocation-, and
welfare-related consequences of guaranteeing loans for household credit. Our focus will be on the
ability of loan guarantees to productively alter allocations when credit markets are affected by
limited commitment, and sometimes asymmetric information as well; we will not presuppose the
presence of any externalities.
Our results can be summarized as follows. First, under symmetric information we find that
loan guarantees can, strikingly, generate improvements for households even after all uncertainty
1

See Weinberg and Walter (2002) and Li (2002) for more details. Both show that the overall contingent-liabilities
of the US government have grown substantially over time.
2
In addition to these officially-guaranteed loan programs, there is one that dwarfs them all, and this is the one
operated by the two main government-sponsored enterprises (GSEs), Fannie Mae, Freddie Mac. These entities issue
securities to investors that come with a guarantee against default risk. The ultimate originators of mortgage credit to
home buyers thereby receive, in essence, a loan guarantee. While historically not explicitly backed by the Treasury–
but now clearly so–MBS investors receive Fannie and Freddie guarantees on loans with face value of approximately
$5 trillion, nearly half of the value all household mortgage debt.

2

over their final human capital level – which fully pins down their expected lifetime income – has
resolved itself. However, this is true only as long as they are not too generous (whereby only small
loans qualify). This welfare gain is disproportionately experienced by low-skilled households who
face flat average income paths and relatively-large shocks. Higher-skilled types rapidly begin to
experience welfare losses as loan guarantees are made more generous. These results arise because
loan guarantees induce a transfer from skilled to unskilled, which can be substantial, while the gains
to the skilled from improved loan pricing as a result of guarantees are relatively small. Second, we
find that allocations are quite sensitive to the size of qualifying loans whereby even modest limits on
qualifying loan size invite very large borrowing — as perhaps intended by proponents. However, these
same limits also bring very large increases in default rates relative to a world without guarantees,
and as a result, transfer resources in significant amounts from the ex post lucky to the ex post
unlucky, in addition to transferring wealth across education types.
Under asymmetric information, we find that guarantees can, once again, yield ex-ante improvements for households of all human capital levels. Moreover, the welfare gains are larger than under
symmetric information because the loan guarantee to some extent mitigates the information asymmetry problem. This is because the reduction in the sensitivity of loan interest rates to default
risk that accompanies loan guarantees also reduces relatively high-risk borrower-types’ incentives
to reduce their borrowing inefficiently simply to mimic those with lower risk. This incentive effect
contributes positively to the welfare impact. Finally, targeted guarantees that focus entirely on
households hit by large expenditure shocks dominate unrestricted programs.
Taken as a whole, our results suggest that loan guarantees can be quite powerful, but that
care must be taken if policymakers intervene in credit markets through them. They can improve
outcomes and do so in ways that are robust to the informational frictions present, but they can
also rather quickly alter private incentives to borrow and default, which in turn can redistribute
resources in ways that leave most worse off. This finding is particularly important from a policy
perspective, as it does not matter for our model whether the loan guarantees received by lenders
are explicitly part of a program, or simply arise from implicit promises to creditors. As long as
lenders act as competitors, the effects on household budget sets and default behavior will be the
same, as the latter will receive cheaper, less-sensitive loan terms.3
Our paper is novel along two dimensions. We are the first, to our knowledge, to analyze loanguarantees in the presence of both voluntary default (default when it is feasible to repay debt)
3

Notice also that loan-guarantees may well be politically feasible – obtaining the support of all newly-entering
households, of all human capital levels, requires no complex forms of ex-post compensation of losers by winners.

3

and asymmetric information. Second, we are the first to assess these effects quantitatively. Our
work enables us to measure, for the first time, the ability of loan guarantees to alleviate credit
constraints when the latter arise from the presence of both asymmetric information and the force
that makes such a friction relevant at all: limited commitment to loan repayment. Moreover, the
extent of asymmetric information in our model will be endogenous as well; it depends on how
heterogeneous borrowers are, not only in terms of both exogenous shocks, but also in terms of
endogenously determined and unobservable, net asset positions. Loan guarantees therefore alter
the importance of asymmetric information not just directly, but also indirectly via their influence
on asset accumulation.
Our work contributes to the understanding of how credit markets are altered by the predominant
form of intervention aimed at them in modern economies, through a model that explicitly accommodates the two central frictions–limited commitment and asymmetric information–routinely
deemed most culpable in these markets’ dysfunction. At a more specific level, our work contributes
by evaluating the likely outcome of the introduction of loan guarantees in a specific market that,
for several a priori reasons, makes them a good candidate for improving outcomes (to be detailed
below), but where they currently are not employed. The complete absence of loan guarantees on
unsecured consumer credit is striking: the young and poor have long been identified as facing
both borrowing constraints and income risk (see Jappelli (1990) and Hubbard, Skinner, and Zeldes
(1994), respectively, for important early references), and they generally lack any meaningful form
of collateral. Therefore, to the extent that the unsecured market is the one most relevant for improving the consumption smoothing efforts of a nontrivial group of US households, the provision
of guaranteed loans to this sector appears, a priori, likely to be consequential.4
While we focus our quantitative analysis on consumer credit markets where only intangible collateral arising from the perception of reputational costs or changes in future credit terms is “posted,”
our approach applies to credit markets where more tangible forms of collateral are pledged. This
is because even when a loan guarantee program is nominally targeted at a secured form of lending,
such as mortgage loan guarantees, they can only alter allocations because there is a positive probability of the loan becoming at least partially unsecured, ex-post. That is, the value of the guarantee
4
Relatedly, although beyond the scope of our inquiry, it should be noted that loan guarantees are often seen as
a viable and essential part of macroeconomic/financial public policy remedies to get credit markets “unstuck” in
crises. Prominent efforts include the Emergency Loan Guarantee Act of 1971, and more recently the guarantees
offerred by Federal Reserve System to member banks to allow the latter continued access to relatively inexpensive
wholesale funding. An extremely recent examples relates to the suggestion that loan guarantees be used to alleviate
fallout from Greek sovereign default. (http://www.nytimes.com/2011/09/24/business/us-pressures-europe-to-actwith-force-on-debt-crisis.html?\_r=1).

4

necessarily emerges from the existence of states of nature in which ex post, repayment becomes
less attractive than paying the costs of default. Sometimes, these costs are primarily those arising
from the surrender of tangible collateral that, ex-post, becomes less valuable than reneging on the
repayment obligation. In other cases, default implies the destruction of intangible collateral, as
described above. Thus, in either case, loan guarantees fundamentally concern unsecured lending.
There are at least three a priori reasons to study the potential for consumer loan guarantees.
First, loan guarantees decouple loan pricing from credit risk. This is relevant in light of a growing
body of work showing that in the absence of complete insurance markets, risk averse households
can benefit from the state-contingency introduced by the option to default, particularly in bad
states of the world (these papers include Zame (1993), Dubey, Geanakoplos, and Shubik (2005),
Livshits, MacGee, and Tertilt (2007), and Chatterjee et al. (2007)). Moreover, in existing work,
consumers have been shown to benefit despite the presence of loan pricing that moves “against”
the riskiest borrowers. However, these gains are not necessarily accessible in all a priori plausible
environments. In recent quantitative work on the value of defaultable consumer debt, a variety
of authors (such as Athreya, Tam, and Young (2009)) have found that in many cases, the ability
of lenders to reprice loans at the same frequency as the arrival of new information on income risk
undoes insurance benefits altogether. In other words, every time a consumer is hit by a persistent
(but not permanent) bad shock, they find their ability to commit to loan repayment eroded and
any borrowing they might attempt will become expensive. From the perspective of borrowers, if
competitive lenders are made partially whole, they cannot “risk-adjust” interest rates as much,
meaning that unsecured debt markets will be better able to assist households in consumption
smoothing. Thus, policies which allow for default, but break the link between credit risk and credit
pricing, are promising candidates to improve allocations–at least to borrowers.
A second reason to develop an assessment of loan guarantees is that the power of unsecured
lenders to frequently re-price consumer debt has already led to policy changes. Most noticeably, the
“CARD” Act of 2009 has responded by essentially requiring longer-term commitments from lenders
in an attempt to deter frequent repricing. However, as studied by Tam (2009), such policies may
carry serious side effects. In particular, average interest rates are predicted to rise substantially to
offset the ability of a borrower to “dilute” their debt (much as in the sovereign debt literature). In
contrast, loan guarantees will decouple risk and pricing, while at the same time reducing average
interest rates. This channel may be important: Calem, Gordy and Mester (2006) show that many
US households appear to use credit cards for relatively long-term financing, making the roughly
ten-percentage-point cost differential between secured and unsecured interest rates quantitatively
5

important.5
Lastly, loan guarantees may mitigate the consequences of asymmetric information at the individual level. This is because they lessen the incentive for a borrower to misrepresent and pretend
to be a lower-risk individual. This is precisely the mechanism operative in Smith and Stutzer
(1989). The costs of asymmetric information are inextricably linked to the strength of the limited
commitment problem; if agents are unable to repudiate debt the asymmetric information problem
is completely irrelevant for allocations. This link is an important feature of loan guarantees given
that asymmetric information may be an important part of why credit constraints do affect many
households. In particular, the larger the equilibrium amount of adverse selection, the more valuable
loan guarantees are likely to be for households.
Despite these likely benefits, it should be clear that loan guarantees will create costs, particularly
in two places. First, default rates are likely to rise, generating more deadweight loss (whether
pecuniary or nonpecuniary in nature). The rise in default rates occurs for the very reason that
loan-guarantees “work”: they lead to the systematic underpricing of loans by lenders, given their
risk. Relatively larger loans will now attract the attention of relatively high-risk borrowers. As
a result, the more effective any loan-guarantee scheme is in spurring borrowing and consumption,
the more prevalent will be default and deadweight losses on the equilibrium path. In the context of
loan-guarantees for entrepreneurial ventures, the work of Lelarge et al. (2008) documents precisely
this type of response in a near-natural French experiment. As they note, “it [loan guarantees]
significantly increases their probability of default, suggesting that risk-shifting may be a serious
drawback for such loan guarantee programs.” This inevitable tradeoff means that the real questions
are: “By how much?” and “Does risk-shifting happen, and if so, is it welfare-enhancing?”
Second, tax revenue must be raised to finance transfers to lenders ex post. Under incomplete
markets, the taxes used to finance these transfers have two opposing effects on welfare. First, if,
as was the case in the in study of Lelarge et al. (2008), a relatively large fraction faces a tax
that a relatively small proportion benefit most significantly from, the introduction of a publiclyfunded loan guarantee program will reduce the mean level of income for many households. In
particular, if it is a relatively small measure of households who run up substantial debts that,
absent the guarantee, would demand high interest rates, they then receive a transfer from all other
households. Second, non-regressive taxes reduce the variance of after-tax income, especially when
5
Andolfatto (2002) develops a simple model to illustrate how government policies may induce changes in behavior
that generate calls to change that policy. Athreya, Tam, and Young (2010b) discuss a similar issue with respect to
bankruptcy costs.

6

one’s expected lifetime income (as captured by ex ante uncertainty over one’s eventual educational
attainment) is uncertain. The second term, being second order, is necessarily dominated by the
first, so the net effect is a welfare loss due to taxation. Thus, the choice of introducing a loan
guarantee system boils down to the choice of whether or not to replace a world of relatively high
average interest rates that, moreover, are highest in those states where a household’s marginal
valuation of wealth is highest, with one of low average interest rates that are relatively insensitive
to personal circumstances, but where average after-tax income for most is lower and smoother.
Our paper is linked to three strands of research in public interventions in credit markets. First,
our work is tied to an earlier, relatively stylized, class of papers that focused on the role of interventions, including loan guarantees, on outcomes for a general problem of risky-investment problem
in static or near-static settings under asymmetric information. Key landmarks in this category are
Chaney and Thakor (1985), Smith and Stutzer (1989), Innes (1990), Gale (1990), and Williamson
(1994).6 Most of this work abstracts from the financing of their programs as well while, as noted
above, these costs will feature prominently in our analysis.
Second, our work is clearly connected to more recent work on quantitative analysis of the
allocational consequences of loan guarantees. This work began, to our knowledge, with the work
of Gale (1991), and was followed by the rich, fully dynamic, and relatively tractable incompletemarket models developed in Li (1998), and Jeske, Krueger, and Mitman (2010).7 The last paper
is the first to focus centrally on credit markets in a consumption smoothing context. However,
with respect to modeling default, in all the preceding work, default is involuntary; it is forced to
occur due to an extreme event. In Jeske, Krueger, and Mitman (2010), for example, default occurs
whenever the value of the loan exceeds the value of the collateral initially pledged as the result of
an exogenous change in asset prices; that is, loan guarantees alter allocations only because loans
can become partially unsecured ex-post.8
Third, our focus on consumer credit under default risk in the latter kind of incomplete-market
setting connects this paper closely to recent work of Chatterjee et al. (2007), Livshits et al (2007),
and Athreya, Tam, Young(2010, 2011). In this line of work, guarantees are not studied, but both
6
In related work, Lacker (1994) investigates whether adverse selection problems necessarily justify government
intervention in credit markets. When cross-subsidization between private contracts is not feasible, intervention is
generally welfare-improving.
7
See also recent work of Jia (2010), who studies loan guarantees as a form of insurance for small businesses in a
setting similar to that of Li (1998).
8
In future work, we aim to analyze the role of guarantees for mortgage lending. However, the central role of
aggregate risk in driving home-loan default makes a full quantitative analysis that satisfactorily incorporates the forces
we do allow for here—partially endogenously asymmetric information and limited commitment—currently infeasible.
But that model would have the same fundamental structure as that developed here.

7

voluntary default and asymmetric information have been shown to matter for the allocation of
consumer credit in the absence of guarantees, see e.g., Athreya, Tam, Young (2011) and Sanchez
(2009).

2. Illustrative Model
In this section we discuss why loan guarantees are likely to be of particular interest, as opposed
to any of the other myriad of interventions that governments could choose, using a simple twoperiod model for illustration. Smith and Stutzer (1989) provide a simple argument for the use of
loan guarantees in unsecured commercial credit markets — compared to direct government loans or
equity purchases, loan guarantees are the only option that does not worsen the private information
problem.

The interest rate reductions apply to all risk-types, so high-risk types do not find

any particular advantage, beyond what they already have, for pretending to be low-risk. Other
programs, such as direct loans to those unable to obtain credit (who are low-risk in their model),
will lead to additional incentives by high-risk borrowers to claim the contracts intended for low-risk
ones, a situation which is harmful to efficiency.
There are two important distinctions between our work and theirs — the nature of the commitment problem and the issue of government revenue balance. In Smith and Stutzer (1989), limited
commitment is a trivial consideration: default occurs when the borrower receives zero income and
is costless (in terms of direct costs).

In contrast, US bankruptcy procedures are voluntary and

clearly not costless: there is a filing fee in addition to substantial time costs and some form of
stigma/nonpecuniary costs appear relevant as well (see Fay, Hurst, and White (1998) or Gross and
Souleles (2002)). Two questions then emerge. First, do loan guarantees still have desirable welfare
properties when commitment is not trivial and default is costly? Second, do these properties hinge
on the presence of information asymmetries with costly signalling? The second aspect that casts
some doubt about the efficacy of loan guarantees in more general environments is that they can be
expensive. Smith and Stutzer (1989) do not consider the financing of such payments; any welfare
gains from the guarantee could easily be wiped out by the cost of taxation. In contrast, a central
aspect of our analysis is the requirement that transfers required to implement loan guarantees be
paid for via taxes.
Before turning to the quantitative setting in the next section, we use a two-period variant of our
model to identify the types of individuals who are harmed by risk-based pricing (and the nonwaivable right of default that makes it necessary) and who may therefore gain from loan guarantees.

8

Households have standard expected utility preferences
max

c1 ,{c2 (e2 ),d2 (e2 )}

{u (c1 ) + βEe2 [u (c2 (e2 )) − d2 (e2 ) λ]} .

Endowments are probabilistic, and structured as follows: e1 is constant and e2 is drawn from a
two-point distribution {eL , eH } with probabilities π and 1 − π.
Let ci denote consumption in period i, ei denote the endowment of the agent in period i, and
d2 ∈ {0, 1} the default decision in period 2. Defaulting incurs a nonpecuniary cost λ. The presence
of default risk on loan size leads to the need for loan prices to depend on loan size. Households
are modeled as borrowing through the issuance of debt b. This debt, by virtue of being risky, will
be discounted by lenders. The term q (b) is the discount factor applied to a debt issuance of facevalue b, and is determined by competitive markets and therefore equals the expected repayment
probability 1 − p (b) divided by the exogenous risk-free rate 1 + r:
q (b) =

1 − p (b)
.
1+r

Households face period budget constraints given by
c1 + q (b1 ) b1 ≤ e1
c2 (e2 ) ≤ b1 (1 − d2 (e2 )) + e2 .
We can represent two kinds of households in this model. Let one type be those whose endowments have (relatively) large mean and (relatively) small variance of e2 , so that income in the future
is expected to be high and relatively safe; this group roughly corresponds to educated types. The
second type we are interested in has small mean and large variance of e2 ; one can think roughly of
this group as being uneducated.
We can parameterize the endowments of the first group of agents such that three conditions
hold: (i) the amount that can be feasibly repaid in the bad state is large (that is, eL is relatively big);
(ii) the household will default in both states under risk-free pricing (λ is small and eL and eH are
close together); and (iii) the household would borrow if asset markets were complete (β (1 + r) < 1
and mean e2 significantly larger than e1 ).

This group is (weakly) harmed by the intertemporal

disruptions that default options create; because the two states tomorrow are very similar, the
household would either default in both states and thus be unable to borrow at all (q = 0), or she
would not default in either state and thus care not at all about default options. As a result, the
9

outcome may be worse than if bankruptcy were banned, since in the absence of a default option
feasibility would permit borrowing against the (relatively high) value of eL .
We can then parameterize the second type’s endowments such that three conditions hold: (i)
the amount of debt that can feasibly be repaid in all states is small (that is, eL is very low); (ii)
the household will default only in the low state (λ intermediate and eL and eH far apart); and (iii)
the household would borrow if asset markets were complete (β (1 + r) < 1 and mean e2 equal to
e1 ). A member of this group can gain from the default option because she actually can borrow
more with a bankruptcy option, as she does not intend to repay in the low state; thus, feasibility
is limited only by the amount that can be repaid in the high state and additional consumption
smoothing is feasible. This is a manifestation of what might be referred to as a “supernatural”
debt limit, as opposed to the “natural” debt limit: feasibility involves what can be repaid in the
best state instead of the worst.
Figure 1 shows a typical equilibrium. The indifference curves are monotone (over the range of
interest at least), and reflect the fact that a household can receive additional consumption today in
two ways: raise q or lower b, holding the other fixed. As a result, if the household borrows a little
more, indifference requires that q fall. Although not shown in the figure, the typical indifference
curve turns upward at very low levels of b, but these lie well outside the budget set. At the optimum
the household is constrained, in the sense that additional borrowing is desired but not feasible due
to the increase in the probability of default; this situation will be typical in the quantitative model
as well. Thus, local to that optimal b there are welfare improvements available if q can be held
fixed while b is increased.
2.1. Loan Guarantees
We now introduce a loan guarantee into this model economy. Loan guarantees will be defined by
two parameters: (i) a “replacement rate” θ that determines the fraction of defaulted obligations the
lender receives as a transfer from the government, and (ii) a “coverage limit” ϑ that determines the
largest (riskiest) loan that the government will insure. Only loans smaller than ϑ qualify for any
compensation; lenders making loans larger than the ceiling receive nothing in the event of default.9
This structure for loan guarantees will also be used in the remainder of the paper.
Given that the loan guarantee covers θ percent of the repayments lost to default for the portion
9

This program assumes that the household cannot obtain a qualifying loan of size greater than ϑ by visiting
multiple lenders; that is, we attach the qualification criterion to the borrower, not the lender.

10

of any loan less than ϑ, competitive pricing of loans must obey
q (b) =

1 − p (b)
p (b)
+
θ.
1+r
1+r

In the absence of taxes needed to compensate lenders for default under any guarantee program,
it is clear that both types of households would gain from their introduction. Assuming default
probabilities don’t change, the guarantee increases the bond price for the first group from 0 to
θ
1+r

and for the second group from

1−π
1+r

to

1−π+πθ
1+r .

This increase expands the set of feasible

consumption paths and raises welfare; default probabilities will not increase if θ is small enough
due to the discreteness of the income process. To illustrate how a loan guarantee works, Figure
2 shows how the pricing function shifts weakly upward, which clearly raises utility because the
household is currently constrained and the deadweight loss from default is the same.
The welfare effects of the tax component are negative — a proportional tax on e2 will reduce
both the mean and variance of second-period income, but the second component is second-order
and therefore dominated by the reduced mean (if tax rates are uniform). Whether agents gain or
lose is then a quantitative question, and hinges on two things. First, how much does the default
rate change, and how much deadweight loss does this change generate? Second, how much does
a particular type of household receive in transfers (the reduction in interest rate times the amount
of debt borrowed) relative to the amount they pay in taxes?
2.2. Asymmetric Information
The current size of the U.S. unsecured credit market is large ($1.5 trillion in balances as of September 2011), and widespread in terms of the fraction of households using it (see, e.g., Bertaut and
Starr-McCluer(2002), and Han and Li (2011)). It is also a market that features information storage,
data sharing, and credit-risk modeling that all suggest, a priori, that private information frictions
are not a central determinant of outcomes, relative especially to purely limited-commitment-related
problems. This is reflected in the now-large array of models of unsecured credit, almost none of
which feature asymmetric information.
Recent work of Sanchez (2010), and Athreya, Tam, Young (2011) suggests, however, that asymmetric information may have played a substantial role in stunting unsecured credit access in earlier
periods. The latter in particular argues that asymmetries in terms of knowledge of factors that
collectively govern individual-level costs of default may have once played a nontrivial role in limiting
unsecured credit access to households. The implication is that in settings lacking the informational

11

infrastructure seen in the U.S. currently, such as developing countries, unsecured credit markets
may well be substantially limited. Our analysis under asymmetric information will, therefore, help
inform us on the potential for guarantees under these more challenging circumstances.10
To adapt the model to deal with asymmetric information, suppose now that default risk, π,
varies according to some characteristic that is not observable to the lender; for concreteness, let
there be two such types. Private information forces (barring a rich menu of screening contracts)
the lender to offer a uniform pricing function to both types of households based on the invariant
measure of each type (let δ ∈ (0, 1) be the measure of the first type); the function is contingent on
the costly signal b sent by the household.11 The pricing function without the guarantee would be
q (b) = δ

p (b|1)
p (b|2)
+ (1 − δ)
,
1+r
1+r

where the conditional probabilities reflect the fact that each type will not default with the same
probability at any given level of debt.
The “bad” type of borrower — that is, the borrower with the high value of π — will want to
reduce b in order to look more like the good borrower, all things being equal. As discussed more
completely in Athreya, Tam, and Young (2011), pooling is potentially an equilibrium if the pricing
function is relatively flat just to the right of the equilibrium choice; in that case, the indifference
curves of both types lie above the break-even curve for the lenders so deviations to lower debt levels
do not occur. Separating equilibria occur when pricing functions are steep (relative to indifference
curves), because then the good type would be better off reducing b while the bad type would
not. Loan guarantees reduce the desire of bad types to pool with good types because they break
the link between pricing and type; this disincentive is welfare-improving because it improves the
allocation of consumption, and so under asymmetric information loan guarantees will have even
better welfare properties. But as before, we must consider whether the costs outweigh the gains,
and under asymmetric information the costs will increase more than under symmetric information
because default is initially lower. Whether the costs or benefits are larger is the main focus of our
quantitative model, which we describe in the next section.
10
Our results, of course, will still reflect the statistical properties of U.S. household income, which we assume
throughout. A detailed quantitative cross-country analysis of unsecured credit markets under country-specific earnings
and expenditure processes would certainly be useful, but is well beyond the scope of this paper. It has not, to
our knowledge, been attempted even in the case of full (non-asymmetric) information, let alone under asymmetric
information.
11
We assume that no costless and credible signals are available, and that some additional hidden characteristic,
such as initial wealth, thwarts the lender’s attempts to infer from b the exact value of π.

12

3. Quantitative Model
The general framework is, under symmetric information, an entirely standard life-cycle model of
consumer debt with default. It is closely related to the models of Athreya, Tam, and Young (2009),
Livshits, MacGee, and Tertilt (2007) and Chatterjee et al. (2007), though the last uses an infinite
horizon. Under asymmetric information, the models builds on Athreya, Tam, and Young (2011).
We assume that the economy is small and open, so that the risk-free rate is exogenous, while the
wage rate is determined by a first-order condition on factor usage.
3.1. Preferences
Households in the model economy live for a maximum of J < ∞ periods, supply labor inelastically,
and face stochastic labor productivity and mortality risk. Households differ along several dimensions
over their life-cycles according to an index of type, denoted “y” and defined in what follows. Each
household of age j and type y has a conditional probability ψ j,y of surviving to age j + 1. Let nj
denote the number of “effective” members in a household.
Households are risk-averse and value consumption per effective household member

cj
nj .

To

smooth consumption, all households have access to risk-free savings, and also debt that they may
discharge fully in bankruptcy subject to some costs. These costs reflect the variety of consequences
that bankruptcy imposes on households. A first set of costs are represented by a nonpecuniary cost
of filing for bankruptcy, denoted by λj,y , which we also permit to depend on household type y. This
will motivated below. In addition to this non-pecuniary cost, there is an out-of-pocket pecuniary
resource cost Λ that represents all formal legal costs and other procedural costs of bankruptcy.
Lastly, households are not allowed to borrow or save in the same period as a bankruptcy filing.
This is to reflect provisions guarding against fraud that are routinely applied in court. There are
no other costs of bankruptcy in the model.
The existence of nonpecuniary costs of bankruptcy is strongly suggested by the calculations and
evidence in Fay, Hurst, and White (1998) and Gross and Souleles (2002). The first paper shows
that a large measure of households would have “financially benefited” from filing for bankruptcy
but did not, while both papers document significant unexplained variability in the probability of
default across households after controlling for a large number of observables. These results suggest
the presence of implicit unobserved collateral that is heterogeneous across households, including
(but not limited to) any “stigma” associated with bankruptcy (as in Athreya 2004).
A household with a relatively low value of λj,y will obtain low value from any given expenditure

13

on consumption (cj ) in a period in which they file for bankruptcy. This is meant to reflect the
increased transactions cost associated with obtaining utility via consumption expenditures in the
period of a bankruptcy. Examples include increased “shopping time” arising from difficulty in
obtaining short-term credit and payments services, locating rental housing and car services, as
well as any stigma/psychological consequences. For convenience, we will sometimes refer to λj,y
as stigma in what follows, we intend it to be more encompassing.12 Because of the breadth of
costs that λ represents, we will allow it to vary stochastically over time, and across individuals as
a function of their type y.
At the time of obtaining a loan, a household that expects to have a relatively low value of λ
next period will know that filing for bankruptcy will result in a relatively high cost of obtaining
any given level of marginal utility, in the next period. Given the current marginal utility of consumption, consumption smoothing (i.e., keeping marginal utility in accordance with the standard
euler equation) under bankruptcy will therefore be costlier, all else equal, than for a household
with a high value of λ. This is further amplified by the fact that households are not allowed to
borrow in the same period as when they file for bankruptcy. For convenience, we will therefore
refer to those whose value of λj,y is relatively low as “low-risk” borrowers, and vice versa. Lastly,
household preferences are represented by a time-additively-separable utility function with common
discount factor β and an isoelastic felicity function with parameter σ. The result is that preferences
are represented by

U

ý

cj
nj

¾J !
j=1

⎡
⎤
õ
¶1−σ !
J
X
cj
1
⎦
E⎣
β j−1 ψ j,y
=
[λj,y dj + (1 − dj )]
1−σ
nj

(3.1)

j=1

where dj is the indicator function that equal unity when the household chose to default in the
current period (in which case dj = 1). We assume that households retire exogenously at age j ∗ < J.
3.2. Endowments
Our focus on consumer credit makes it critical to allow for both uninsurable idiosyncratic risk.
Consumer default, and hence the value of loan guarantees, is by all accounts strongly tied to
individual -level uninsurable risk (see, e.g. Sullivan et al. (1989, 2000), Chatterjee et al. (2007)).13
12
Another possibility is that these households gain the benefits from bankruptcy without filing, as suggested by
Dawsey and Ausubel (2004). Athreya et al. (2011) extends the benchmark model to include a delinquency state in
which households do not formally file for bankruptcy but also do not service their debt.
13
In mortgage lending, loan guarantees protect lenders against house price fluctuations, which in turn are strongly
tied to aggregate risk (or at least city-level risk). The full incorporation of the aggregate risk, private information,

14

There are two sources of such risk in our model. First, households face shocks to their labor
productivity, and because they are modeled as supplying labor inelastically, face shocks to their
labor earnings. Second, households are susceptible to shocks to their net worth. The former
represent shocks arising in the labor market more generally, and the latter represent sudden required
expenditures arising from the need to deal with unplanned events such as sickness, divorce, and
legal expenses.
In addition to the use of credit to deal with stochastic fluctuations in income and expenditures,
consumer credit also likely serves, as noted earlier, as a tool for longer-term, more purely intertemporal smoothing in response to predictable, low-frequency changes in labor income, such as those
coming with increased age and labor market experience. This leads us to specify, in addition to
transitory and persistent shocks to income, a deterministic evolution in average labor productivity over the life-cycle. This component of earnings will reflect most obviously, one’s final level of
educational attainment, which is represented in the model as part of an agent’s type, y.
Specifically, log labor income will be determined as the sum of five terms: the aggregate wage
index W , a permanent shock y realized prior to entry into the labor market, a deterministic age
term ω j,y , a persistent shock e that evolves as an AR(1) process. The log of income at age-j for
type−y is therefore given by:

log W + log ωj,y + log y + log e + log ν
where
¡ ¢
log e0 = ς log (e) + ²0 ,

(3.2)

and a purely transitory shock log (ν). Both ² and log (ν) are independent mean zero normal random
variables with variances that are y-dependent.
As for the risk of stochastic expenditures, we follow the literature (e.g. Livshits, MacGee and
Tertilt (2007) and Chatterjee et al. (2007)), and specify a process xj to denote the expense shock
to net worth that takes on three possible values {0, x1 , x2 } from a probability distribution π x (·)
with i.i.d. probabilities {1 − π x1 − π x2 , π x1 , π x2 }.
We will take agents’ permanent type y to reflects differences between households with permanent
differences in human capital. Specifically, we will consider agents with three types of human capital:
those who did not graduate high school, those who graduated high school, and those who graduated
and limited commitment needed to analyze this specific class of guarantees remains an important topic for future
work.

15

college.14 This partition of households follows Hubbard, Skinner, and Zeldes (1994). The central
reason for allowing this heterogeneity is that the observed differences in mean life cycle productivity
for each of these types of agents makes gives them different incentives to borrow over the life cycle.
In particular, college workers will have higher survival rates and a steeper hump in earnings; the
second is critically important as it generates a strong desire to borrow early in the life cycle. They
also face smaller shocks than the other two education groups. The life cycle aspect of our model
is key; in the data, defaults are heavily skewed toward young households.15
3.3. Market Arrangement
As stated earlier, to smooth consumption and save for retirement, households have access to both
risk-free savings as well as one-period defaultable debt. The issuance and pricing of debt is modeled
as a two stage game in which households at any age j first announce their desired asset position bj ,
after which a continuum of lenders simultaneously announces a loan price q. As a result, a household
issuing bj units of face value receives qbj units of the consumption good today. A household who
issues debt with face value bj at age-j is agreeing to pay bj in the event that they fully repay the
loan, and pay zero otherwise (i.e., when they file for bankruptcy). The fact that non-repayment
can occur with positive probability in equilibrium means that lenders will not be willing to pay the
full face value, even after adjusting for one-period discounting. Therefore, given any gross cost of
b we must have q ≤ 1/R.
b
funds R,

As we will allow for both symmetric and asymmetric information, we introduce the following

notation. Let I denote the information set for a lender and π
b : b×I → [0, 1] denote the function that

assigns a probability of default to a loan of size bj given information I. Clearly, since default risk
assessed by lenders will depend in general on both their information and the size of the loan taken
by a household, so will loan prices. Therefore, let loan pricing be given by the function q(bj , I).
Under asymmetric information, we allow lenders to use the information revealed by the size of the
loan request, and lenders’ knowledge of the distribution of household net worth in the economy to
update their assessment of all current unobservables. Thus, lenders use their knowledge of both (i)
optimal household decision making (i.e., their decision rules as a function of their state), and (ii)
the endogenous distribution of households over the state vector.We will describe the determination
of this function in detail below.
14

We say primarily because mortality rates also differ by education, although this heterogeneity is of no consequence
for our questions.
15
See Sullivan, Warren, and Westbrook (2000).

16

The household budget constraint during working life, as viewed immediately after the decision
to repay or default on debt has been made, is given by
cj + q (bj , I) bj + Λdj ≤ aj + (1 − τ 1 − τ 2 ) W ω j,y yeν.

(3.3)

aj is net worth after the current-period default decision dj . Therefore, aj = bj−1 − xj if dj = 0 and
0 if dj = 1. Households default decisions also determine their available resources beyond removing
debt, because default consumes real resources Λ, arising from court costs and legal fees. The last
term, (1 − τ 1 − τ 2 ) W ω j,y yeν, is the after-tax level of current labor income, where τ 1 is the flat-tax
rate used to fund pensions and τ 2 is the rate used to finance the loan guarantee program.
The budget constraint during retirement is
cj + q (bj , I) bj + Λdj ≤ aj + υW ω j ∗ −1,y yej ∗ −1 ν j ∗ −1 + ΥW,

(3.4)

where for simplicity we assume that pension benefits are composed of a fraction υ ∈ (0, 1) of
income in the last period of working life plus a fraction Υ ∈ (0, 1) of average income W (we
normalize average individual labor earnings to 1).
3.4. Consumer’s Problem
The timing is as follows. In each period, all uncertainty is first realized. Thus, income shocks e and
v, the default cost λ, and the current expense shock x, are all known before any decisions within
the period are made. Following this, households must decide, if they have debt that is due in the
current period, to repay or default. This decision, along with the realized shocks, then determines
the resources the household has available in the current period. Given this, the household chooses
current consumption and debt or asset holding with which to enter the next period, and the period
ends.
Prior to making the current-period bankruptcy decision, a household can be fully described by
bj−1 , the debt, if any, that is due in the current period, their type y, the pair of currently realized
income shocks e and v, their cost of default λ, the current realization of the shock to expenses, xj ,
and their age j.16
Letting V (·) denote the household’s value function prior to the decision to default or repay, with
primed variables denoting objects one-period ahead, we have the following recursive description. If
16

To avoid repetition, we display only the value functions during working life; retirement is entirely analogous.

17

the household chooses to repay its debt bj−1 , and therefore sets dj = 0, then the value they derive
from state (bj−1 , y, e, ν, λ, x, j) is:

v d=0 (bj−1 , y, e, ν, λ, x, j) = max
c,bj

⎧
⎨

⎩ βψ
j,y

³

cj
nj

⎫
⎬

´1−σ

+
¢´ ⎭
¡ 0 ¢ ¡
0
0
0
0 , ν 0 , λ0 , x0 , j + 1
b,
y,
e
0 0 π x (x )π e (e |e) π ν (ν ) π λ λ |λ V
0
0
e ,ν ,λ ,x
(3.5)

³P

subject to the budget constraint:

cj + q (bj , I) bj + xj ≤ bj−1 + (1 − τ 1 − τ 2 ) W ωj,y yeν.

(3.6)

If the household has chosen bankruptcy for the current period (dj = 1), since we disallow
credit-market activity in the period of bankruptcy, which implies bj = 0, we obtain:

⎧
⎨

⎫
´
³
cj 1−σ
⎬
λ
+
j,y
nj
³P
´
v d=1 (bj−1 , y, e, ν, λ, x, j) =
¢ ⎭
¡ 0 ¢ ¡
⎩ βψ
0
0
0
0 0 0 0
j,y
e0 ,ν 0 ,λ0 ,x0 π x (x )π e (e |e) π ν (ν ) π λ λ |λ V 0, y, e , ν , λ , x , j + 1
subject to the budget constraint:

cj + Λ ≤ (1 − τ 1 − τ 2 ) W ω j,y yeν.

(3.7)

Notice that both debt due in the current period, bj−1 , and the current expenditure shock realization xj get removed by bankruptcy, and hence disappear, when comparing the budget constraint
under bankruptcy to one under non-bankruptcy. By contrast, the resource- and non-pecuniary
costs, Λ, and λj,y , respectively, both appear.
Given this, prior to the bankruptcy decision, the current-period value function is:

V (bj−1 , y, e, ν, λ, x, j) = max{v d=1 (bj−1 , y, e, ν, λ, x, j), v d=0 (bj−1 , y, e, ν, λ, x, j)}.
3.5. Loan Pricing and Loan Guarantees
Loan guarantee regimes are defined by two parameters: the “replacement rate” θ and the “coverage
limit” ϑ. Only loans smaller than ϑ qualify for any compensation; lenders making loans larger than

18

the ceiling receive nothing in the event of default.17 Conditional on default occurring, the lender,
having made a loan of qualifying size, will receive partial compensation whereby the fraction θ will
be paid to the lender for each dollar of face value.18
We focus throughout on competitive lending whereby intermediaries utilize all available information to offer one-period debt contracts with individualized credit pricing that is subject to
meeting a zero profit condition. The definitions of I and π
b (b, I) have been given above. Also,
π
b (b, I) is identically zero for positive levels of net worth and is equal to 1 for some sufficiently large
debt level. Denote by r the exogenous risk-free saving rate and φ a transaction cost for lending, so

that r + φ is the risk-free borrowing rate.
Given the preceding and the loan guarantee program parameters (θ, ϑ), the break-even pricing
function on loans (b < 0) will depend on the size of the loan relative to the guarantee limit ϑ as
follows. First, since only loans smaller than the guarantee ceiling entitle lenders to compensation,
qualifying loans (those with b ∈ (−ϑ, 0)) are priced as follows:
q (b, I) = ψ j+1|j

∙

π
b (b, I) θ
(1 − π
b (b, I))
+
1+r+φ
1+r+φ

¸

if 0 > b ≥ −ϑ.

(3.8)

The first term, ψ j+1|j reflects the fact that repayment occurs, if at all, only if the borrower survives.
Conditional on survival, the payoff to a loan of face value b will be complete in the event of no
default, which occurs with probability 1− π
b (b, I), and partial, according to the guarantee, if default

occurs. These payoffs are then discounted according the cost of funds, inclusive of transactions costs,
1+r +φ. For any loans exceeding the guarantee qualification threshold, lenders will receive nothing

in the event of default. As a result, the preceding zero-profit loan price collapses (the second term
goes to zero), yielding the simpler expression
q (b, I) = ψ j+1|j

∙

(1 − π
b (b, I))
1+r+φ

¸

if 0 > −ϑ > b.

(3.9)

Lastly, savings are trivial to price, as they carry no transactions costs or default risk. Therefore,
for b ≥ 0, we have
q (b, I) =

1
if b ≥ 0.
1+r

For the full information setting we assume I contains the entire state vector for the household:
17

This restriction seems to be standard practice in markets where some form of loan guarantee program exists. For
example, FNMA (Fannie Mae) will not issue guarantees on loans which do not conform to their pre-set standards,
which include a restriction on the loan-to-value ratio.
18
As we noted earlier, qualification actually applies to the total debt of the borrower, not the total loan emanating
from any one lender. An implicit assumption is therefore that this debt burden is observable.

19

I = (y, e, ν, x, λ, j).

Abusing notation slightly, let d(·) now denote the decision rule governing

default. As described earlier, this function drives the decision to repay a given debt or not, and
hence depends on the full household state vector. Letting non-primed objects represent current
period decisions, and using primed variables for objects dated one-period ahead, we have the
following zero profit condition for the intermediary. Simply put, it requires that the probability
of default used to price debt must be consistent with that observed in the stationary equilibrium,
implying that
π
bf i (b, y, e, ν, x, λ, j) =

X

e0 ,ν 0 ,λ0 ,x0

¢ ¡ ¢
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¡
d(b, e0 , ν 0 , x0 , λ0 , j + 1)π e e0 |e π ν ν 0 π λ λ0 |λ π x x0 . (3.10)

¡
¢
¡
¢
Since d b, e0 , ν 0 , x0 , λ0 , j + 1 specifies whether or not the agent will default in state e0 , ν 0 , x0 , λ0

tomorrow at debt level b, integrating over all such events one-period hence produces the relevant
default risk π
bf i . This expression also makes clear that knowledge of the persistent components

(e, λ) is relevant for predicting default probabilities, and the more persistent these characteristics

are, the more useful they become in assessing default risk.
3.5.1. Asymmetric Information
As we noted at the outset, in earlier work, Sanchez (2010), and Athreya, Tam, Young (2011)
both find that in past decades, unsecured credit market outcomes may well have been affected
by asymmetric information. In the latter, asymmetric information governing individual-level costs
of bankruptcy were shown to be consistent with a variety of features of the data from the 1980s
and earlier. Thus, to evaluate the implications of loan guarantees under asymmetric information,
we assume that nonpecuniary default costs, λj,y , is unobservable. With the exception of current
household net worth following the bankruptcy decision in a period (which we denoted by “a”) all
other household attributes, including educational attainment, age, and the current realization of
the persistent component of income are assumed observable. To be clear, the use of household
decisions rules and the distribution of households over the state space to infer a borrower’s current
net worth, a, is not because the latter is relevant to forecasting income, default risk, or anything
else; it is not. Rather, it is because lenders want to draw a more precise inference on the current
values of the persistent aspects of a household’s state. In this case the inference is about the
current realization of a household’s λ, something that is clearly relevant to assessing default risk.
Let π ∗ (λ|b, y, e, ν, x, j) denote the conditional probability of a household having a realized value
of λ, given that they have observable characteristics y, e, ν, x, j, and that they have issued bonds of

20

b units of face value. To construct π ∗ (·), lenders use their knowledge of household decision making
and the joint (conditional) distribution of households over the state-space to arrive at a probability
distribution for the current value a household’s non-pecuniary default cost.19 The best estimate of
default risk is then given by:
π
bpi (b, y, e, ν, x, j) =

X

λ

π ∗ (λ|b, y, e, ν, x, j) π
bf i (b, y, e, ν, x, λ, j)

3.6. Equilibrium in the Credit Market

Here, we follow Athreya, Tam, Young (2011), and employ the Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium (PBE)
concept to define equilibrium in the game between borrowers and lenders.20 Denote the state space
for households by Ω = B × Y × E × V × L × J × {0, 1} ⊂ R4 × Z++ × {0, 1} and space of information
as I ⊂ Y × E × V × L × J × {0, 1}. Let the stationary joint distribution of households over the state
be given by Γ(Ω). Let the stationary equilibrium joint distribution of households over the state
space Ω and loan requests b0 be derived from the decision rules {b0∗ (·), d∗ (·)} and Γ(Ω), and be
denoted by Ψ∗ (Ω, b0 ). Given Ψ∗ (Ω, b0 ), let μ∗ (b0 ) be the fraction of households (i.e., the marginal
distribution of b0 ) requesting a loan of size b0 . Lastly, let the common beliefs of lenders on the
household’s state, Ω, given b0 , be denoted by Υ∗ (Ω|b0 ).21
Definition 1. A PBE for the credit market game of incomplete information consists of (i) household strategies for borrowing b0∗ : Ω → R and default d∗ : Ω × λ × E × V → {0, 1}, (ii) lenders’
i
h
1
such that q ∗ is weakly decreasing in b0 , and (iii)
strategies for loan pricing q ∗ : R × I → 0, 1+r
lenders’ common beliefs about the borrower’s state Ω given a loan request of size b0 , Υ∗ (Ω|b0 ), that

satisfy the following:
1. Households optimize: Given lenders’ strategies, as summarized in the locus of prices
q∗ (b0 , I), decision rules {b0∗ (·), d∗ (·)} solve the household problem.
2. Lenders optimize given their beliefs: Given common beliefs Υ∗ (Ω|b0 ), q 0∗ is the purestrategy Nash equilibrium under one-shot simultaneous-offer loan-price competition.
3. Beliefs are consistent with Bayes’ rule wherever possible: Υ∗ (Ω|b0 ), is derived from
Ψ∗ (Ω, b0 ) and household decision rules using Bayes rule whenever b is such that μ∗ (b0 ) > 0.
19

See Athreya, Tam, and Young (2011) for details.
See, e.g., Mas-Colell, Whinston, Green, Definition 9.C.3, p. 285, and the additional requirement given on p. 452).
21
Recall that the stationary distribution of households over the state space alone is given by Γ(·).
20

21

Equilibria are located through an iterative procedure. The interested reader is directed to
Athreya, Tam, and Young (2011) where we discuss the computational procedure used to solve
for equilibria. As a quick summary, we define an iterative procedure that maps a set of pricing
functions back into themselves, and then show three things. First, fixed points of this map are
Perfect Bayesian Nash equilibria of the game between lenders and borrowers; second, that this
procedure converges to a fixed point; and third, that this fixed point is maximal (in the sense of
the size of the budget set for households).22
3.7. Government
The purpose of government in this model is to fund pension payments to retirees and to finance
the loan guarantee system. The government budget constraint for pensions is
τ 1W

Z

∗

(yωj,y eν) dΓ (a, y, e, ν, x, λ, j < j ) = W

Z

(υω j ∗ −1,y yej ∗ −1 ν j ∗ −1 + Υ) dΓ (a, y, e, ν, x, λ, j ≥ j ∗ ) ,
(3.11)

where Γ (a, y, e, ν, x, λ, j) is the invariant cumulative distribution function of households over the
states. For the loan guarantee program, the budget constraint is
Z
(3.12)
τ 2 W yω j,y eνdΓ (a, y, e, ν, x, λ, j < j ∗ )
Z
θb (a, y, e, ν, x, λ, j)
π
b (b (a, y, e, ν, x, λ, j) , I)
max(0, b (a, y, e, ν, x, λ, j) − ϑ)
dΓ (a, y, e, ν, x, λ, j) .
= ψ j+1|j
1+r+φ
b (a, y, e, ν, x, λ, j) − ϑ
3.8. Wage Determination
For both simplicity and substantive reasons, we assume constant and exogenous factor prices in
our welfare calculations. In each case, the imposition of the loan guarantee program leads to
more borrowing and lower aggregate wealth. In particular, we assume that the risk-free rate r
is exogenous and determined by the world market for credit. Given r, profit maximization by
domestic production firms implies that
W = (1 − α)

³r´

α
α−1

α

(3.13)

where α is capital’s share of income in a Cobb-Douglas aggregate production technology.
22

Uniqueness cannot be ensured, since q = 0 is a fixed point of our mapping. However, simple sufficient conditions
exist to rule out q = 0 as the maximal fixed point; again, see Athreya, Tam, and Young (2011) for details. Also,
under symmetric information, the largest budget set yields the equilibrium with the highest welfare for households,
but strictly speaking, this need not hold under asymmetric information.

22

4. Stationary Equilibrium
We have already given the definition of equilibrium for the game between borrowers and lenders.
The outcomes of that interaction were, of course, part of a larger fixed point problem that included,
among other things, the joint distribution of households over the state space, Γ(·), and the tax rates
τ 1 and τ 2 needed to fund transfers and loan-guarantees, respectively. But this joint distribution
depended on household borrowing behavior, which in turn influenced the construction of Γ(·).
Given this feedback, we will focus on throughout on stationary equilibria in which all aggregate
objects including, critically, the joint distribution Γ(·) remain constant over time under the decision
rules that arise from household and creditor optimization.
Computing stationary equilibria requires two layers of iteration. We first specify the wage
rate, interest rate, tax rates, and public sector transfer- and loan-guarantee policy. This allows
us to solve the household’s decision problem and locate the associated stationary distribution of
households over the state space—all for a given guess of the equilibrium loan-pricing locus q(·).
Our use of a risk-free rate-taking open economy allows us to iterate on the function q(·) without
having to deal any additional feedback from loan pricing to risk-free interest rates and wages. Once
we have located a price function that is a fixed point under the stationary distribution induced
by optimal household decision making, which we can denote by q ∗ (·), we need to check if the
government budget constraint holds. Here, we must iterate again, this time on transfers and taxes.
We proceed by guessing the size of old-age and loan-guarantee transfers and tax rates, and iterate
(re-solving for the fixed-point loan pricing function q ∗ (·) each time, of course) until the associated
stationary equilibrium generates allocations that, given the tax rates, satisfy the government budget
constraint.

5. Parametrization
To assign values to model parameters, we proceed first by imposing standard values from the
literature for measures of income risk, out-of-pocket expenses, risk aversion, and demographics.
We then calibrate the remaining model parameters, which are those governing bankruptcy costs
and the discount factor. The goal is to match as well as possible, key facts about bankruptcy
and unsecured credit markets in the US, given income risk, risk aversion and demographics. As
discussed earlier, we follow the literature by calibrating to recent data and assuming symmetric
information between borrowers and lenders.
The parametrization is relatively parsimonious and largely standard. First, as mentioned above
23

we directly assign values to household level income risk and risk aversion at values standard in the
literature. The model period is taken to be one year. The income process is taken from Hubbard,
Skinner, and Zeldes (1994), who estimate separate processes for non-high school (NHS), high school
(HS), and college-educated (Coll) workers for the period 1982-1986.23 Figure 3 displays the path
for ω j,y for each type; the large hump present in the profile for college-educated workers implies
that they will want to borrow early in life to a greater degree than the other types will (despite
their effective discount factor being somewhat higher because of higher survival probabilities). The
process is discretized with 15 points for e and 3 points for ν. The resulting processes are
¡ ¢
log e0 = 0.95 log (e) + ²0
² ∼ N (0, 0.033)

log (ν) ∼ N (0, 0.04)
for non-high school agents,
¡ ¢
log e0 = 0.95 log (e) + ²0
² ∼ N (0, 0.025)

log (ν) ∼ N (0, 0.021)
for high school agents, and
¡ ¢
log e0 = 0.95 log (e) + ²0
² ∼ N (0, 0.016)

log (ν) ∼ N (0, 0.014)
for college agents. We normalize average income to 1 in model units, and in the data one unit
roughly corresponds to $40,000 in income. When we construct the invariant distribution of the
model, we assume households are born with zero assets and draw their first shocks from the stationary distributions.
To assign values for the idiosyncratic risk of out-of-pocket expenses, we choose the parameters
23

In Athreya, Tam, and Young (2009) we study the effect of the rise in the volatility of labor income in the US
and find the effect on the unsecured credit market to be quantitatively small; the key parameter for default is the
persistence of the shocks. We would find similar numbers if we adjusted the variance of the shocks upward to conform
to more recent data.

24

for the expenditure shock xj to be the annualized equivalent of those used in Livshits, MacGee,
and Tertilt (2007). For pensions, we set υ = 0.35 and Υ = 0.2, yielding an average replacement
rate of 55 percent, and assume an exogenous retirement age of j ∗ = 45. Relative risk aversion is set
to σ = 2, as is standard, and a value that also avoids overstating the insurance problem faced by
households. Lastly, with respect to demographics, we set the measures of the college (Coll), high
school (HS), and non-high school (NHS) to 20, 58, and 22 percent, respectively, and the maximum
lifespan to J = 65, corresponding to a calendar age of 85 years.
Table 1 displays the targeted moments and the implied ones from the model.24 Table 2 displays
the parameters associated with this calibration, along with the other parameters of the model (such
as the cost of default Λ, which is set to match the observed $1200 filing cost). First, the default
rates, measured as filings for Chapter 7 bankruptcy, are very close to the data. Second, the model
does fairly well at matching the debt/income ratios in the data, measured as credit card debt divided
by income (from the Survey of Consumer Finances 2004), although it gets the order backward: we
understate debt for college types and overstate it for non-high-school types. Lastly, the model
overstates the fraction of borrowers and understates the discharged debt to income ratio.25
To parameterize the non-pecuniary costs of bankruptcy while limiting free parameters, we
represent λ by a two-state Markov chain with realizations {λL,y , λH,y } that are independent across
households, but serially dependent with a symmetric transition matrix Πλ :
⎡

Πλ = ⎣

πλ

1 − πλ

1 − πλ

πλ

⎤

⎦.

The calibrated process suggests that non-pecuniary costs of bankruptcy are largely in the nature
of a “type” for any given household. This interpretation arises because the benchmark calibration reveals λ to be very persistent, and therefore very unlikely to change during the part of life
where unsecured credit is useful. This persistence is also what makes the model consistent with
the observed ability of households to borrow substantial amounts but still default at a nontrivial
rate. Despite this “implicit collateral,” debts discharged in bankruptcy are still higher in the data;
however, the discharge ratio from the data (obtained as the median debts discharged in bankruptcy
divided by the median income of filers taken from the survey data of Sullivan, Warren, and West24
The calibrated parameters are obtained by minimizing the (equally-weighted) sum of squared deviations between
the data and moments from the invariant distribution of the model. Since the model is not linear, we cannot
guarantee that there exists a set of parameters that makes this criterion zero; indeed, we find that such a vector does
not exist.
25
If we had data on discharge by education type, we could permit the persistence of λ to vary by type and possibly
match the aggregates more closely.

25

brook (2000)) is likely an overestimate, as it includes small business defaults that are generally
large and not present in the model. The size of the values for λ are relatively large, implying that
even the low cost types view default as equivalent to a loss of nearly 10 percent of consumption;
thus, the primary source of implicit collateral in this model is stigma rather than pecuniary costs.
Table 3 presents a decomposition of defaults according to the various combinations of expense
shock and stigma. The median shock for x and the high value of λ constitute only 3.55 percent of
the population but are responsible for 58.11 percent of the defaults under symmetric information,
while the high shock for x and high value for λ are 0.23 percent of the population and 6.66 percent of
the defaults. Thus, defaults are clearly skewed toward households that experience an expenditure
shock, consistent with the model of Livshits, MacGee, and Tertilt (2007). We will return to this
table when we discuss the asymmetric information case, where expenditure shocks are essentially
the only source of defaults.
Lastly, while omitted from the tables for brevity, the other relevant probability is that of the
likelihood of default given the receipt of an expenditure shock. This distribution yields two pieces
of information about the model. First, getting an expenditure shock, particularly the largest one,
greatly increases the likelihood of default, all else equal. Second, the vast majority of households
who receive such a shock still do not default. The reason for this is that the power of such shcoks
to drive default, while non-trivial, is still naturally limited by the wealth positions households take
on as they move through the life-cycle. Default is most likely to happen when one has substantial
debts at the same time that one receives such a shock. This rules out relatively older households
from being very susceptible; as seen in Figure 6, they have, in the main, already begun saving for
retirement.26

6. Results
We will study four types of allocations.

First, we examine our benchmark setting, where infor-

mation is symmetric and there is no loan guarantee program. Second, we introduce various loan
guarantee programs and examine how credit market aggregates, default rates, and welfare are al26

For the high risk households (high λ in the model):
High expense shock: 26%
Median expense shock: 15%
Low expense shock (a value of zero)=1%
For the low risk households (low λ in the model):
High expense shock: 17%
Median expense shock: 2%
Low expense shock (a value of zero)=0%
The numbers are very similar under asymmetric information.

26

tered.

Third, we relax the assumption of symmetric information and study allocations without

loan guarantees; in this setting we permit lenders to use all observable characteristics to infer as
much as they can about borrowers. Finally, we examine the introduction of loan guarantees into
this asymmetric information environment. We will refer to these four allocations as FI, FI-LG, PI,
and PI-LG, respectively.
To preview the results, we find that introducing a small loan guarantee program into a symmetric
information economy (comparing FI with FI-LG) can benefit all newborns, independent of type, but
that increasing generosity quickly eliminates the gains for skilled types. In the environments with
asymmetric information (comparing PI to PI-LG), welfare gains are larger for any given generosity,
but the same pattern emerges.

Thus, a general lesson to be gleaned from these experiments is

that loan guarantees are welfare-improving, and in fact can be welfare-improving for all newborns,
provided they are not too generous.
6.1. Symmetric Information
As we noted at the outset, unsecured credit markets are most vital for the consumption smoothing
needs of the least wealthy members of any society. This is obvious for any household with liquid
wealth, but even those whose wealth is illiquid will, in general, be able to pledge at least a portion
of that wealth to obtain credit. Moreover, as we noted, existing work suggests that information
asymmetries may not be central, relative to the limited-commitment problem, in explaining current
U.S. unsecured credit market activity. We therefore first isolate the role that loan-guarantees play
to deal with the effects of such a friction by studying the model under symmetric information.
Moreover, since loan-guarantee programs require two parameters for their specification, we simplify
the results by focusing throughout the analysis — and unless otherwise stated — on the case where
the replacement rate is set to cover 50 percent of lender losses, i.e., θ = 0.5.
6.1.1. Allocations and Pricing
Our first main result is that loan guarantees are powerful tools in altering the use of unsecured
credit. In Table 4, we see that as we move away from the case with no loan guarantees (ϑ = 0),
equilibrium borrowing rises for all households, and the increase in debt is non-linear. In particular
for small qualifying loan sizes (e.g. ϑ = 0.1, or $4,000), allocations are fairly similar to a setting
with no guarantees. In large part, this similarity reflects the presence of bankruptcy costs which
serve as a form of implicit collateral. In particular, the fixed cost component of bankruptcy (Λ)
will ensure the existence of a region of risk-free debt. Therefore, under a small qualifying loan
27

size, few individuals will see their access to credit substantially altered; in fact, setting ϑ < −Λ
would have no effect on credit, since those loans are always risk-free. Once the qualifying loan size
grows large enough to make large loans “cheap” relative to default risk, matters are different. The
compensation to lenders for default disproportionately subsidizes large loans, and thereby generates
the significant additional default seen in Table 4.
The differential distortion to loan pricing is displayed in Figure 4, and our model suggests
that this feature helps account for the striking distributional consequences seen in Table 4. In
particular, borrowing behavior changes in different ways across the education groups. Relative to
income, debt rises by far the most for NHS households. The differential increase in debt relative
to income for the lowest skilled is also reflected in the disproportionate rise in bankruptcy rates
within this group. While remaining modest under small qualifying loan ceilings, more generous
ceilings create greatly increased default rates. The preceding suggests in part that the pricing
of debt is a meaningful barrier to nearly all households, but especially the least skilled (NHS)
households. An additional force at work is that high-skilled households have less reason to use
unsecured credit beyond early life. As a result, any distortion in the pricing of debt will affect
them less than their NHS counterparts. In particular, all NHS households that have income below
their age-specific mean will find “artificially” cheap credit useful, while the well-educated, many
of whom wish to save less for precautionary reasons and more for life-cycle reasons (arising from
the more pronounced hump in their average earnings shown in Figure 3), will be far less sensitive.
Lastly, under high ceilings for qualifying loan guarantees, the high tax rate will also meaningfully
compress the intertemporal profile of earnings, and therefore attenuate the incentives of the skilled
to borrow for pure lifecycle smoothing. This will make loan guarantees even less valuable than
otherwise.
6.1.2. Welfare
Having shown results suggesting that loan guarantees will likely have sizeable and non-linear effects
on credit use and default, we now turn to the issue that motivated us at the outset: can loan
guarantees, by breaking the link between credit risk and loan pricing, improve welfare? And if so,
for whom? Our metric for measuring welfare is standard: it is the increment to consumption at
all dates and states needed to make the household indifferent, in terms of ex ante expected utility,
between the benchmark economy and the one with loan guarantees.
A fact that will be important for welfare is that households in our economy that borrow are
always constrained.

Figure 5 plots indifference curves in (b, q) space along with the zero-profit
28

pricing function; the optimal amount of borrowing and the resulting price lies where the highest
indifference curve intersects this zero-profit curve.

At this point the slope of the indifference

curve is strictly smaller than the slope of the pricing function (which is infinite). This implies that
borrowing more is desirable at the current interest rate, but the increase in the default rate that a
marginal increase in b would generate means that lenders must charge a higher rate. As a result, by
reducing the slope of the pricing function at the optimal point, loan guarantees can improve utility
at the margin. What we are contemplating, however, are not marginal changes; thus, whether a
discrete change is welfare-improving is a quantitative question.
We see first, from Table 4, that more generous loan guarantees come with higher taxes, and
that the taxes also naturally reflect the non-linearity in household borrowing and default behavior
(that is, taxes are a convex function of ϑ). However, not all households pay the same amount in
taxes, and, as we noted, proportional taxes — which are used here — will by themselves provide some
risk-sharing benefits. Moreover, the loan guarantee may allow for an effective form of insurance for
some households, especially the low-skilled. The transfers from loan guarantees come “at the right
time” for households, but require households to pay a cost akin to a deductible. Therefore, while
households pay more in taxes under a generous loan guarantee scheme, they receive transfers in a
manner that is effective in providing insurance. Turning to welfare in Table 5, we see that this is
precisely what is at work. In this table a positive value indicates a gain to welfare from moving to
loan guarantees, and vice versa. In particular, we see that generous loan guarantee schemes mainly
represent transfers to the very unskilled. These are, in turn, the groups with the most to gain
from improved credit access. As a result, the most skilled households lose in welfare terms from
any qualifying loan sizes in excess of approximately $4000 (ϑ = 0.1). Conversely, HS households
continue to gain, and gain substantially in welfare terms, from loan guarantees of up to $16,000
(ϑ = 0.4). Most strikingly, NHS households gain for very large loan guarantee levels, even to levels
exceeding their mean income level. In summary, our results suggest that modest loan guarantee
programs can improve welfare for all households, even those households who likely will pay the
bulk of the taxes needed to finance them. However, our model also suggests that qualifying loan
size is likely to be quite important in determining whether a particular guarantee program serves
all households or instead functions as a very significant redistributive mechanism. In the absence
of definitive means for detecting the sensitivity of aggregate credit use and default to the size of
qualifying loans, instituting a program that is too generous will lead to significant welfare losses

29

for some groups.27
Where do the welfare gains come from? Table 6 shows mean consumption and decomposes the
variance of consumption into two moments: the variance of mean consumption by age, a measure
of intertemporal consumption smoothing, and the mean of consumption variance by age, a measure
of intratemporal consumption smoothing.28
Loan guarantees reduce mean consumption due to the combination of higher taxes, more borrowing, and more frequent default. The gain comes through a better distribution of consumption
over the life cycle. We see here that this gain is driven entirely by a reduction in the intertemporal
dimension as intratemporal consumption volatility actually increases.
We note here that our welfare results differ significantly from those in Athreya, Tam, and Young
(2010), where the role of the out-of-pocket costs of default, Λ, in restricting access to bankruptcy is
explored. High values of Λ restrict access to bankruptcy to high income types (who typically do not
want to default), and in a wide range of models the optimal value (from an ex ante perspective)
is infinite for all types; that is, from the perspective of a newborn household, permitting any
bankruptcy in equilibrium is suboptimal.29 The largest gains are experienced by the college types,
because they have the strongest demand for purely intertemporal borrowing and this demand is
thwarted by risk-based pricing. There are a number of reasons to view that result as impractical
from a policy perspective. Loan guarantees, in contrast, are clearly policy-feasible and benefit the
least-skilled more than the more-skilled.30
6.1.3. Decomposing the Effect of Taxes on Welfare
In this section we decompose the net effect of the loan guarantee program. We consider two
experiments, presented in Table 7, where we ask how welfare changes if we confront an individual
with the pricing emerging from the presence of a loan guarantee, with and without the taxes needed
to finance the program. Starting in the top row of Table 7 we display the effect of a move from the
benchmark setting to one in which a tax-free loan guarantee is provided. Welfare increases quite
substantially, again by least for the skilled and by most for the unskilled. Since their income profile
27
The analytical work of Jia (2011) is relevant here: he shows that as a qualititative matter, barring eligibility
requirements, loan guarantees will lower welfare.
28
Specifically, we use the decomposition: var (log (c)) = var (E [log (c) |j]) + E [var (log (c) |j)]
29
If consumption sets can become empty, eliminating bankruptcy cannot be optimal. Athreya, Tam, and Young
(2011) abstracts from expenditure shocks.
30
Davila et al. (2007) shows that utilitarian constrained efficient allocations in a model with uninsurable idiosyncratic shocks are skewed toward improving the welfare of “consumption-poor” households (since they have higher
marginal utility). While we do not attempt to characterize constrained efficient allocations here, it seems clear that
this intuition would apply — thus, policies which raise the utility of the least-skilled would seem to be preferable from
a social welfare perspective.

30

is flat, the NHS households experience the largest gain because they use unsecured debt over most
of their life cycle. By contrast, the more-skilled types decrease unsecured borrowing as they age
(see Figure 6).
Turning next to the bottom row of Table 7, we present the welfare implications of a move from a
setting with a tax-free loan guarantee to one where the taxes must now break the program even. As
seen from Table 5, once taxes are imposed only the unskilled benefit from a program this generous,
and they lose proportionally more from taxes than do the college types. Why are the costs of a
small tax so large in this model? With taxes, permanent income is reduced, leaving households
more exposed to the expenditure shock. As a result, they “involuntarily” default more frequently,
leading to more deadweight loss and a much larger welfare loss than one would expect from a tax
of less than 4 percent. Due to the accumulation pattern of net worth, on average NHS households
are more exposed to this risk (again, see Figure 6).
Table 8 decomposes the costs of the program by type. The loan guarantee program transfers
resources along two dimensions. First, loan guarantees transfer resources from skilled households
to less-skilled; college types pay into the program, via taxes, significantly more than they collect
in terms of lower interest rates. Second, loan guarantees transfer resources from individuals who
pose little default risk (those with low λ) to those with a high value for λ, as the latter pose more
default risk, all else equal. This transfer occurs because the high risk types would pay substantially
higher interest rates without intervention and therefore gain a lot from the program.
6.2. Asymmetric Information
Returning to the problem noted at the outset of the previous section, recall that the cost of limited
access to unsecured credit is likely largest for the least wealthy. This is particularly likely to
be true in a society that lacks the information storage, sharing, and data-analysis available in
developed nations to effectively identify credit risk at the time of loan origination (and then update
it regularly). As a first step in getting a sense of the quantitative potential of loan guarantees to
alter outcomes in such settings, we now study stationary equilibria of our model under asymmetric
information.
To remind the reader, in our economy, asymmetric information will mean that the borrower will
have characteristics that are not observable to the lender; specifically, we assume neither current
stigma, λ, nor current net worth, a, can be directly observed.

However, any information about

these variables that can be inferred from the observable components of the state vector, as well as

31

from the desired borrowing level, b, is available to the lender.31

We focus on two representative

examples: one that represents a relatively modest loan guarantee program and results in welfare
gains for all types under symmetric information (θ = 0.1 and ϑ = 0.1), and one that is more generous
and reduces the welfare of college-educated types (θ = 0.5 and ϑ = 0.4). Our key finding is that
the presence of asymmetric information will increase the gains available from loan guarantees, no
matter how generous.
6.2.1. Allocations and Pricing
We first compare outcomes in the FI and PI economies. Table 9 shows that a move from symmetric
to asymmetric information has the following effects. First, default falls for all types, and default
skews more strongly toward the high λ type; these individuals are treated relatively better under
asymmetric information, since they get terms that reflect the average default risk instead of their
own, and therefore end up borrowing amounts that induce relatively high default rates. Second,
overall the credit market shrinks, in the sense that we observe fewer borrowers (of each type) and
lower discharged debt aggregates.
Figure 7 shows that pricing is significantly worse for the high λ (low bankruptcy cost) borrower
and better for the low λ borrower. Under asymmetric information, the two types will be pooled
together, so that the default premium at a given debt level reflects the average default risk. The
result is that good borrowers face significantly tighter credit limits and higher interest rates, while
bad borrowers face the same credit limit but lower interest rates. The shift in pricing accounts for
the smaller credit market size.
Third, expenditure shocks take on a larger role in defaults under asymmetric information (see
Table 3). With tighter credit limits, big expenditure shocks that hit when the household is young
are hard to smooth, since income is relatively low. The result is that essentially all defaults are
done by households that have received an expenditure shock, despite this group being only 7.56
percent of the population.

Information has less of an impact on these defaults, since they are

defaults on debt that has been acquired involuntarily.
We now turn to the effects of loan guarantees under asymmetric information. Table 9 shows
that the change induced by the introduction of the particular program is larger for all credit market
aggregates under asymmetric information, with the exception of the debt-to-income ratio for college
31

We assume that credit markets are anonymous, so that past borrowing is also not observable to the current
lender. In Athreya, Tam, and Young (2011) we introduce a flag that tracks whether a household is likely to have
recently defaulted. Due to computational considerations we do not examine this case here.

32

educated households (in which case it is of only slightly smaller magnitude). Figure 8 shows the
increased access to credit that guarantees provide in these two cases. Note that the increase in the
default rate is smaller under asymmetric information for every education group. As a result, the
taxes required to finance the program are lower than under symmetric information.
6.2.2. Welfare
Table 10 displays the welfare effects of two different loan guarantee programs. Relative to the
symmetric information case, loan guarantees are uniformly better when information is asymmetric;
this result holds for every case we have computed. The larger gain is partly due to the lower tax
burden required in the asymmetric information cases and partly due to the severe pricing distortion
caused by asymmetric information evident in Figure 7.
To more directly describe the transfers between agents induced by loan guarantees, Table 8
collects the proportion of costs paid by each group. Now, the loan guarantee program subsidizes
the high λ (low stigma cost) types much more than under symmetric information. This result is
exactly what we would expect, given that this type is receiving better credit terms under asymmetric
information.
6.3. Targeted Loan Guarantees
Our results suggest that loan guarantees have the potential to become primarily a means of transferring resources from the rich to the poor. Moreover, our findings suggest that they may also
lower welfare, often of all types of agents, unless their generosity is modest. Moreover, in our
results, default is disproportionately driven by those who have received an expenditure shock. A
natural question therefore is whether the benefits of loan guarantees discussed at the outset can
be preserved by limiting compensation to lenders only when a borrower has suffered such a shock.
Expenditure shocks represent large increases in debts that are rare and involuntarily acquired.
As a result, a policy of guaranteeing loans only under these conditions is unlikely to alter loan
pricing substantially (since these states are rare) but may substantially aid households that find
themselves in those rare states. Moreover, targeted guarantees are unlikely to induce significant
additional deadweight loss because the default decision is more frequently heavily influenced by
expenditure shocks, which again, are rare.
To investigate this question, we study a case where ϑ = 0.50 and θ = 0.50, but where lenders
only receive compensation in the event that a bankruptcy coincides with a positive expenditure
shock (x > 0). Table 11 shows that all groups gain from the introduction of a loan guarantee
33

program restricted in this manner. As before, the NHS households gain most and the highly skilled
gain the least. Nonetheless, the ability of the conditionality of the program to overturn what was
initially a very large welfare loss to the skilled into a gain is striking.32
To see the effect on aggregates more generally, we turn to Table 12. It is immediately clear
that the tax rate needed to sustain the restricted loan guarantee program is very small relative to
the unrestricted case, even though the debt discharged in bankruptcy is similar to the unrestricted
guarantee case. Nonetheless, the overall level of debt responds to the restricted guarantee far more
modestly than the unrestricted case. For example, under restricted guarantees, the mean debtto-income ratio among high-school educated borrowers is less than half that under unrestricted
guarantees (0.2256 vs. 0.4707). The central reason for the low tax rate is that the default rate
responds by far less than with an unrestricted program, even though borrowing does increase
nontrivially, relative to the benchmark case. Under restricted guarantees, the bankruptcy rate
roughly doubles, while the unrestricted program implies a nearly ten-fold increase.

7. Discussion
We have made a few assumptions in our model that require some additional discussion. First, we
have assumed that factor prices are fixed. General equilibrium calculations would imply higher
r and lower W would prevail under loan guarantee systems, since they produce more borrowing
and less aggregate wealth (as well as increasing the amount of transactions costs that works like a
reduction in aggregate supply of goods). Factor price movements of this sort are likely to make the
welfare costs larger (gains smaller), since the higher risk-free interest rate would make borrowing
more costly and the lower wages would reduce mean consumption. Despite these effects, we choose
to abstract from equilibrium pricing because it is well known that income processes representative of
the vast majority of households will, in environments such as ours, produce less wealth concentration
than observed (see Castañeda, Díaz-Jiménez, and Ríos-Rull 2003), meaning that the mean wealth
position will be too similar to the median. That is, the mean agent will care “too much” about
changes in the debt market, implying larger factor price changes than would occur if the distribution
of wealth were matched. Given the immense computational burden that matching the US Gini
coefficient of wealth would impose on our OLG setup, and given that the factor price adjustments
32
We are implicitly assuming that expenditure shocks are likely to be easy to observe; we doubt that agents could
easily hide one from the government, given the size and nature of these shocks. Our calibration, as noted above,
equates x to a combination of medical and legal bills plus unplanned family costs; these expenses should be relatively
easy to monitor in practice.

34

should be small, we feel justified in ignoring them.33
Second, we have financed the program using proportional labor income taxes. An obvious
alternative would be to finance the program using progressive income taxes, where high income
(college) types would pay higher marginal tax rates. This approach would increase the gains to
the NHS types, who already gain substantially, and reduce (or even eliminate) any gains to college
types. We expect a similar result from capital income taxation as well, since it will tend to tax the
wealthier college types more heavily. In contrast, a regressive income tax would imply the types
who benefit the most, the NHS, would pay a higher marginal tax rate. Regressive tax systems
seem unlikely to be implemented on equity grounds, even if they are welfare-improving within a
specific model. We could also introduce separate programs for each education group, so that the
cross-subsidization that makes the program so attractive to NHS types would be eliminated; we
conjecture that this case would result in larger gains for college types and smaller for NHS.
Third, there is a conceptual issue of the right benchmark allocation. The US corporate income
tax rate is 35% and banks are permitted to deduct losses due to nonperforming loans from their
taxable income. As a result, it may be that the appropriate benchmark is a case where the loan
guarantee program is not zero, but rather has a large value of ϑ and θ = 0.35. We can of course
easily express the welfare gains relative to this benchmark instead; a more detailed investigation of
this issue is part of ongoing work.
There are some natural extensions of our model that seem useful to pursue. Given our results regarding the effect of loan guarantees to redistribute towards the unskilled from the skilled, it would
be productive to know if the least-skilled, for example, would benefit from a loan guarantee program
that was required to be self-financing via taxes on only the unskilled. Such an extension would be
along the lines explored in Gale (1991), who studies targeted loan guarantees designed to facilitate
credit access for certain identifiable subpopulations (such as minority borrowers). Targeted programs would be related to the regulations we mentioned earlier that require certain characteristics
not be reflected in credit terms; exactly how the dual goals of encouraging access to these groups
without allowing their characteristics to alter credit terms would affect welfare is unknown and
worth studying. It would also be straightforward to investigate loans targeted to individual borrowers who are deemed constrained by competitive lenders.34 In our model, since borrowers are at
a “cliff” in the pricing function they would benefit from government loans at their existing interest
33
In Chatterjee et al. (2007), the model is calibrated to the US distribution of wealth; the resulting effects of an
endogenous risk-free rate are quantitatively unimportant.
34
A stylized approach to this is taken in Smith and Stutzer (1989).

35

rate, provided the tax costs are not “too high.”
Also, our work is a step in the direction that, in the future, will allow us to analyze the role
of guarantees for mortgage lending. However, the central role of aggregate risk in driving homeloan default makes a full quantitative analysis that satisfactorily incorporates the forces we do allow
for–asymmetric information and limited commitment–currently infeasible. But we note that such
model would have the same fundamental structure as that developed here.

8. Concluding Remarks
As stated at the outset, loan guarantees are almost certainly the largest form of intervention in
household-level credit markets. Our paper is the first to quantify their likely impact in a model
that incorporates both a meaningful private information and limited commitment problem into a
rich life-cycle model of consumption and savings. Our quantitative analysis focused on evaluating
the impact of introducing loan guarantees into unsecured consumer credit markets. These markets
have large consequences for household welfare, because they influence the limits on smoothing faced
by some of the least-equipped subgroups in society, particularly the young and the unlucky.
Our results suggest first, that under symmetric information, loan guarantees can actually improve the ex-ante welfare of all household-types (by human capital) if they are not too generous.
This welfare gain is disproportionately experienced by low-skilled households that face flat average
income paths and relatively-large shocks. Indeed, such households gain from very generous programs, but higher-skilled types rapidly begin to experience welfare losses as loan guarantees are
made more generous. These results arise because loan guarantees induce a transfer from skilled
to unskilled, and this transfer can be substantial, while the gains to the skilled from seeing loan
pricing terms improve as a result of guarantees is relatively small. Second, we find that allocations
are quite sensitive to the size of qualifying loans: even modest limits on qualifying loan size invite
very large borrowing — as perhaps intended by proponents — but also spur very large increases in
default rates. As a result, loan guarantee programs transfer resources in significant amounts from
all households to the lifetime poor. Under asymmetric information, the welfare gains are larger for
all households, as the taxes required to finance the programs are smaller.
One interpretation of our work is that it provides an answer for why, despite the potential
for welfare gains from expanding guarantees to consumer credit and thereby alleviating credit
constraints for a marginalized population otherwise lacking collateral, they are rarely observed.
The value of the program depends on how elastically credit demand and supply respond to default

36

risk, which may be hard to estimate, and the programs are quite costly if too generous. As a
practical matter, the forces at work in our model may well be part of explaining why student loan
default rates hit 25 percent in early 1990’s, at which point the government increased monitoring and
enforcement (recall also the similar findings of Lelarge et al (2008) in the French entrepreneurship
context). Nonetheless, the fact that consumer loan guarantees have the potential for generating
widespread ex-ante welfare improvements while requiring no ex-ante promises to compensate losers
is striking, and seems worth keeping in mind.
As noted at the outset, we studied the explicitly-unsecured credit market as a way to learn
about consumer loan-guarantees, with the view that the insight gained would likely to carry over
to markets where loans are more implicitly unsecured. The two main areas that fit this description,
and have seen some form of loan guarantee, are (i) federal student loans and (ii) home loans. Our
results suggest that loans of the size guaranteed by federal student loan program would have been
likely to default at high rates, even under a relatively “partial” nature of the guarantee. Similarly,
the FHA/VA and others have historically provided loan guarantees for seemingly large mortgage
loans. The calibrated costs of default measured in our model suggest strongly that larger loans,
especially if covered more fully by a loan guarantee program, would lead to even greater debt and
default than that predicted for the consumer credit market. Therefore, unless such loans are vetted
carefully, one should expect both a high take-up rate, a high subsequent failure rate, and nontrivial
transfers from better-off households. To this point, both the FHA and VA loan guarantee programs
impose strict underwriting standards with respect to loan-to-value ratios, perhaps because these
agencies are cognizant of the possibility of high ex post default rates.
Lastly, because loan guarantees may well be a powerful tool for altering aggregate consumption
decisions, our work should be of help in future examinations of the extent to which consumer
spending can be amplified to spur current activity in business-cycle contexts. While currently
intractable, we hope to address that question in future work.

37

References
[1] Andolfatto, David (2002), “A Theory of Inalienable Property Rights,” Journal of Political
Economy 110(2), pp. 382-93.
[2] Athreya, Kartik (2004), “Shame As It Ever Was: Stigma and Personal Bankruptcy,” Federal
Reserve Bank of Richmond Economic Quarterly 90(2), pp. 1-19.
[3] Athreya, Kartik, Juan M. Sánchez, Xuan S. Tam, and Eric R. Young (2011), “Default, Bankruptcy, and Delinquency,” manuscript.
[4] Athreya, Kartik, Xuan S. Tam, and Eric R. Young (2009), “Unsecured Credit Markets Are
Not Insurance Markets,” Journal of Monetary Economics 56(1), pp. 83-103.
[5] Athreya, Kartik, Xuan S. Tam, and Eric R. Young (2010), “Personal Bankruptcy and the
Insurance of Labor Income Risk,” manuscript.
[6] Athreya, Kartik, Xuan S. Tam, and Eric R. Young (2011), “A Quantitative Theory of Information and Unsecured Credit,” WP-08-06R, Federal Reserve Bank of Richmond.
[7] Bertaut, Carol, and Martha Starr-McCluer (2002), “Household Portfolios in the United
States,” in Guiso, Luigi, Haliassos, Michael and Tullio Jappelli, eds. Household Portfolios,
MIT Press.
[8] Calem, Paul S., Michael B. Gordy, and Loretta J. Mester (2006), “Switching Costs and Adverse
Selection in the Market for Credit Cards: New Evidence,” Journal of Banking and Finance
30(6), pp. 1653-85.
[9] Castañeda, Ana, Javier Díaz-Giménez, and José-Víctor Ríos-Rull (2003), “Accounting for
Earnings and Wealth Inequality,” Journal of Political Economy 111(4), pp. 818-57.
[10] Chaney, Paul, and Anjan Thakor, (1985), “Incentive Effects of Benevolent Intervention: The
Case of Government Loan Guarantees” Journal of Public Economics, 26(2), 169-189
[11] Chatterjee, Satyajit, P. Dean Corbae, Makoto Nakajima, and José-Víctor Ríos-Rull (2007),
“A Quantitative Theory of Unsecured Consumer Credit with Risk of Default,” Econometrica
75(6), pp. 1525-90.
[12] Dawsey, Amanda E. and Lawrence M. Ausubel (2004), “Informal Bankruptcy,” manuscript.

38

[13] Davila, Julio, Jay H. Hong, Per Krusell, and José-Víctor Ríos-Rull (2007), ”Constrained Efficiency in the Neoclassical Growth Model with Uninsurable Idiosyncratic Shocks,” manuscript.
[14] Dubey, Pradeep, John Geanakoplos, and Martin Shubik (2005), “Default and Punishment in
General Equilibrium,” Econometrica 73(1), pp. 1-37.
[15] Fay, Scott A., Erik Hurst, and Michelle J. White (1998), “The Bankruptcy Decision: Does
Stigma Matter?” University of Michigan Working Paper 98-01.
[16] Gale, William G. (1990), “Federal Lending and the market for credit”, Journal of Public
Economics, 42, pp. 177-193.
[17] Gale, William G. (1991), “Economic Effects of Federal Credit Programs,” American Economic
Review 81(1), pp. 133-152.
[18] Gross, David B. and Nicholas S. Souleles (2002), “An Empirical Analysis of Personal Bankruptcy and Delinquency,” Review of Financial Studies 15(1), pp. 319-47.
[19] Han, S., and Geng Li, (2011), “Household Borrowing after Personal Bankruptcy”, Journal of
Money, Credit, and Banking, (43) 491-517.
[20] Hubbard, R. Glenn, Jonathan Skinner, and Stephen P. Zeldes (1994), “The Importance of
Precautionary Motives for Explaining Individual and Aggregate Saving,” Carnegie-Rochester
Conference Series on Public Policy 40, pp. 59-126.
[21] Innes,R., (1990), “Investment and Government Intervention in Credit Markets when there is
Asymmetric Information”, Journal of Public Economics, 46(3), 347-381.
[22] Jappelli, Tullio (1990), “Who is Credit Constrained in the U.S. Economy?” Quarterly Journal
of Economics 105(1), pp. 219-234.
[23] Jeske, Karsten, Dirk Krueger, and Kurt Mitman (2010), “Housing and the Macroeconomy:
The Role of Implicit Guarantees for Government Sponsored Enterprises,” manuscript.
[24] Jia, Ye (George), (2011), “Small Business Loan Guarantees as Insurance Against Aggregate
Risks,” mimeo, UPEI
[25] Lacker, Jeffrey M. (1994), “Does Adverse Selection Justify Government Intervention in Loan
Markets?” Federal Reserve Bank of Richmond Economic Quarterly 80(1), pp. 61-95.

39

[26] Li, Wenli (1998), “Government Loan Guarantee and Grant Programs: An Evaluation,” Federal
Reserve Bank of Richmond, Economic Quarterly, 84(4), pp. 25-51.
[27] Li, Wenli (2002), “Entrepreneurship and Government Subsidies:

A General Equilibrium

Analysis,” Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control 26(11), pp. 1815-44.
[28] Livshits, Igor, James MacGee, and Michèle Tertilt (2007), “Consumer Bankruptcy: A Fresh
Start,” American Economic Review 97(1), pp. 402-18.
[29] Sanchez, Juan, (2009), The Role of Information in the Rise of Consumer Bankruptcy, Federal
Reserve Bank of Richmond Working paper, WP 09-4.
[30] Smith, Bruce D. and Michael J. Stutzer (1989), “Credit Rationing and Government Loan
Programs: A Welfare Analysis,” AREUEA Journal 17(2), pp. 177-193.
[31] Sullivan, Teresa A., Elizabeth Warren, and Jay Lawrence Westbrook (2000), The Fragile Middle Class: Americans in Debt, Yale University Press.
[32] Tam, Xuan S. (2009), “Long Term Contracts in Unsecured Credit Markets,” manuscript.
[33] Weinberg, John A. and John R. Walter (2002), “How Large is the Federal Financial Safety
Net?” CATO Journal 21(3), pp. 369-94.
[34] Williamson, Stephen (1994), “Do Informational Frictions Justify Federal Credit Market Programs?” Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 26(3).
[35] Zame, William R. (1993), “Efficiency and the Role of Default when Security Markets are
Incomplete,” American Economic Review 83(5), pp. 1142-1164.

40

Table 1
Calibration
Calibration

Model

Target/Data

Discharge/Income Ratio

0.2662

0.5600

Fraction of Borrowers

0.1720

0.1250

Debt/Income Ratio | NHS

0.1432

0.08

Debt/Income Ratio | HS

0.1229

0.11

Debt/Income Ratio | COLL

0.0966

0.15

Default Rate | NHS

1.237%

1.228%

Default Rate | HS

1.301%

1.314%

Default Rate | COLL

0.769%

0.819%

41

Table 2
Calibration
Parameter

Value

Parameter

Value

xlow

0.0000

Prob(xlow )

0.9244

xmedian

0.0888

Prob(xmedian )

0.0710

xhigh

0.2740

Prob(xhigh )

0.0046

λNHS
low

0.7675

λNHS
high

0.9087

λHS
low

0.7309

λHS
high

0.9320

λColl
low

0.7830

λColl
high

0.9017

π λHH = π λLL

0.9636

J

65

j∗

45

Λ

0.0300

σ

2.0000

φ

0.0300

α

0.3000

r

0.0100

42

Table 3
Default by State
FI

PI

High λ

Low λ

High λ

Low λ

Low x

0.2315

0.0092

0.0089

0.0000

Median x

0.5811

0.0670

0.8033

0.0399

High x

0.0666

0.0446

0.0890

0.0588

43

Table 4
Aggregate Effects of Loan Guarantee Program
θ = 0.50
ϑ

0.00

0.10

0.30

0.60

0.70

τ2

0.0000

0.0005

0.0174

0.0531

0.0664

Discharge/Income Ratio

0.2662

0.2691

0.5430

0.9907

1.1172

Fraction of Borrowers

0.1720

0.2039

0.2400

0.4023

0.4466

Debt/Income Ratio | NHS

0.1432

0.1648

0.4765

0.6562

0.7118

Debt/Income Ratio | HS

0.1229

0.1372

0.3707

0.5369

0.5934

Debt/Income Ratio | COLL

0.0966

0.1140

0.2532

0.3858

0.4124

Default Rate | NHS

1.237%

1.768%

11.651%

19.691%

20.877%

Default Rate | HS

1.301%

1.751%

11.658%

16.609%

17.836%

Default Rate | COLL

0.769%

0.987%

5.668%

11.569%

13.100%

44

Table 5
Optimal Generosity of Loan Guarantee Program
θ = 0.50
COLL

HS

NHS

ϑ = 0.00 → ϑ = 0.10

0.02%

0.08%

0.13%

ϑ = 0.00 → ϑ = 0.20

−0.24%

0.20%

0.22%

ϑ = 0.00 → ϑ = 0.30

−1.41%

0.27%

0.39%

ϑ = 0.00 → ϑ = 0.40

−1.60%

0.19%

0.78%

ϑ = 0.00 → ϑ = 0.50

−2.24%

−0.11%

1.06%

ϑ = 0.00 → ϑ = 0.60

−2.84%

−0.35%

1.26%

ϑ = 0.00 → ϑ = 0.70

−3.60%

−0.44%

1.02%

45

Table 6
Distribution of Consumption
E (c)

var (log (c))

E (var (log (c) |age))

var (E (log (c) |age))

Aggregate
NO LG

0.8455

0.1894

0.1671

0.0223

LG ϑ = 0.5, θ = 0.5

0.8016

0.1977

0.1755

0.0222

College
NO LG

1.0918

0.1776

0.1293

0.0481

LG ϑ = 0.5, θ = 0.5

1.0521

0.3874

0.3354

0.0520

High School
NO LG

0.7767

0.2279

0.1907

0.0372

LG ϑ = 0.5, θ = 0.5

0.7575

0.3926

0.3749

0.0180

Non-High School
NO LG

0.6579

0.2807

0.2582

0.0225

LG ϑ = 0.5, θ = 0.5

0.6514

0.3932

0.3849

0.0083

46

Table 7
Welfare Decomposition, Symmetric Information
ϑ = 0.5, θ = 0.50
¢
¡
¢
¡ NLG
, τ 2 = 0.0 → q LG , τ 2 = 0.0
q
¡ LG
¢
¡
¢
q , τ 2 = 0.0 → q LG , τ 2 = 0.0386

47

COLL

HS

NHS

4.86%

8.30%

10.69%

−6.74%

−7.76%

−8.69%

Table 8
Net Costs Paid by Type
ϑ = 0.50, θ = 0.50, FI
High λ

Low λ

Taxes

Transfer

Taxes

Transfer

Coll

0.1366

0.1050

0.1366

0.0384

HS

0.2995

0.5082

0.2995

0.1512

NHS

0.0639

0.1333

0.0639

0.0639

ϑ = 0.50, θ = 0.50, PI
High λ

Low λ

Taxes

Transfer

Taxes

Transfer

Coll

0.1366

0.1155

0.1366

0.0341

HS

0.2995

0.4971

0.2995

0.1239

NHS

0.0639

0.1711

0.0639

0.0583

48

Table 9
Aggregate Effects of Loan Guarantees and Asymmetric Information
ϑ = 0.40
FI

PI

θ=

0.0000

0.5000

0.0000

0.5000

τ2

0.0000

0.0245

0.0000

0.0196

Discharge/Income Ratio

0.2662

0.6965

0.2021

0.6497

Fraction of Borrowers

0.1720

0.3109

0.1614

0.3036

Debt/Income Ratio | NHS

0.1432

0.4880

0.1209

0.4762

Debt/Income Ratio | HS

0.1229

0.3897

0.0909

0.3755

Debt/Income Ratio | COLL

0.0966

0.2691

0.0801

0.2389

Default Rate | NHS

1.237%

13.170%

0.956%

12.704%

Default Rate | HS

1.301%

12.310%

0.957%

11.407%

Default Rate | COLL

0.769%

6.304%

0.658%

5.412%

49

Table 10
Welfare Effects of Loan Guarantees
COLL

HS

NHS

NO LG→ θ = 0.50, ϑ = 0.40, FI

−1.60%

0.19%

0.78%

NO LG→ θ = 0.50, ϑ = 0.40, PI

−1.02%

0.98%

1.59%

NO LG→ θ = 0.10, ϑ = 0.10, FI

0.01%

0.02%

0.03%

NO LG→ θ = 0.10, ϑ = 0.10, PI

0.04%

0.08%

0.11%

50

Table 11
Welfare Effects of Restricted Loan Guarantees
ϑ = 0.5, θ = 0.50

NO LG→Restricted LG
Restricted LG→Unrestricted LG

51

COLL

HS

NHS

0.40%

0.77%

0.99%

−2.66%

-0.88%

−0.07%

Table 12
Aggregate Effects of Restricted Loan Guarantees
ϑ = 0.50
θ=

0.00

0.50

0.50

No LG

Restricted LG

Unrestricted LG

τ LG

0.0000

0.0004

0.0386

Discharge/Income Ratio

0.2662

0.7208

0.8657

Fraction of Borrowers

0.1720

0.2408

0.3527

Debt/Income Ratio | NHS

0.1432

0.2649

0.5738

Debt/Income Ratio | HS

0.1229

0.2256

0.4707

Debt/Income Ratio | COLL

0.0966

0.1681

0.3285

Default Rate | NHS

1.237%

2.755%

16.797%

Default Rate | HS

1.301%

2.586%

14.619%

Default Rate | COLL

0.769%

1.643%

9.072%

52

Figure 1: Equilibrium in Two-Period Model

Preferences over (b,q)
0.9

0.85

Direction of Increasing Utility
0.8

0.75

q

0.7

0.65

0.6

Indifference Curves

0.55

Zero Profit

0.5

0.45

0.4
-0.25

-0.2

-0.15

-0.1

b

53

-0.05

0

Figure 2: Loan Guarantee Equilibrium in Two-Period Model

Preferences over (b,q), Loan Guarantee
Direction of Increasing Utility
0.7

0.6

LG Utility
Zero Profit w/o Guarantee
Zero Profit with Guarantee

q

0.5

No LG Utility
0.4

0.3

0.2

-0.3

-0.25

-0.2

-0.15

b

54

-0.1

-0.05

0

Figure 3: Efficiency Units of Labor

2
NHS
HS
Coll

1.8

Efficiency Units of Labor

1.6
1.4
1.2
1
0.8
0.6
0.4
20

25

30

35

40

45
age

55

50

55

60

65

Figure 4: Pricing Functions with and without Loan Guarantees

age=29, low , median e
LG,  = 0.5,  = 0.5, HS, FI
0.95

LG,  = 0.5,  = 0.5, Coll, FI

0.9

q

0.85

No LG, HS, FI

No LG, NHS, FI

0.8

LG,  = 0.5,  = 0.5, NHS, FI

0.75

No LG, Coll, FI

0.7
-0.25

-0.2

-0.15

b

56

-0.1

-0.05

Figure 5: Optimal Choice of Borrowing
age=29, coll, low , median e

Zero Profit

0.9

Direction of Increasing Utility
0.8

q

0.7

0.6

Indifference Curve
0.5

0.4
-0.4

-0.35

-0.3

-0.25

-0.2

b

57

-0.15

-0.1

-0.05

Figure 6: Net Worth over the Life Cycle
mean(a | age, edu)
5
4.5
4

Coll
3.5

a

3
2.5

HS

2
1.5

NHS

1
0.5
0
25

30

35

40

45
age

58

50

55

60

Figure 7: Pricing with Symmetric and Asymmetric Information

age=29, coll, median e
0.95

0.9

FI, high 

FI, low 
0.85

Unobserved 
0.8

q

0.75

0.7

0.65

0.6

0.55

0.5

-0.25

-0.2

-0.15

-0.1

b

59

-0.05

Figure 8: Pricing with Loan Guarantee, Symmetric vs Asymmetric Information
age=29, low , median e, Coll
0.95

LG,  = 0.5,  = 0.5, FI

0.9

No LG, PI
No LG, FI

q

0.85

LG,  = 0.5,  = 0.5
0.8

0.75

-0.25

-0.2

-0.15

-0.1

b

60

-0.05