View original document

The full text on this page is automatically extracted from the file linked above and may contain errors and inconsistencies.

Working Paper Series

Bank Runs and Institutions: The Perils of
Intervention

WP 07-02

Huberto M. Ennis
Federal Reserve Bank of Richmond
Todd Keister
Federal Reserve Bank of New York

This paper can be downloaded without charge from:
http://www.richmondfed.org/publications/

Bank Runs and Institutions: The Perils of Intervention
Huberto M. Ennis
Research Department
Federal Reserve Bank of Richmond
Huberto.Ennis@rich.frb.org

Todd Keister
Research and Statistics Group
Federal Reserve Bank of New York
Todd.Keister@ny.frb.org

Federal Reserve Bank of Richmond Working Paper No. 07-02
March 30, 2007

Abstract
Governments typically respond to a run on the banking system by temporarily
freezing deposits and by rescheduling payments to depositors. Depositors may
even be required to demonstrate an urgent need for funds before being allowed
to withdraw. We study ex post efficient policy responses to a bank run and the ex
ante incentives these responses create. Given that a run is underway, the efficient
response is typically not to freeze all remaining deposits, since this would
impose heavy costs on individuals with urgent withdrawal needs. Instead,
(benevolent) government institutions would allow additional withdrawals,
creating further strain on the banking system. We show that when depositors
anticipate these extra withdrawals, their incentives to participate in the run
actually increase. In fact, ex post efficient interventions can generate the
conditions necessary for a self-fulfilling run to occur.

____________________________________
We thank Roberto Chang and seminar participants at Rutgers University, the Federal Reserve Bank of
Richmond, Universidad de Alicante, Universidad de San Andrés, the Society for Economic Dynamics
meetings, the Midwest Macro meetings, the North American Meeting of the Econometric Society, the
Cornell-Penn State macroeconomics workshop, and the SAET conference in Vigo, Spain, for helpful
comments. The views expressed herein are those of the authors and do not necessarily reflect the position
of the Federal Reserve Bank of New York, the Federal Reserve Bank of Richmond, or the Federal Reserve
System.

1 Introduction
System-wide banking crises are complex phenomena that typically occur in conjunction with a
variety of unfavorable nancial and macroeconomic factors. One feature that often plays a prominent role in such crises is a run by depositors. While the general crisis may develop slowly, over
the course of weeks or months, the run is a sudden event in which withdrawals quickly spiral out
of control. In Argentina, for example, deposits fell steadily throughout most of 2001, but the rate
of withdrawals accelerated dramatically in the last two days of November. Total deposits in the
banking system fell by more than 2 billion (U.S.) dollars, or nearly 3%, on November 30 alone.1
Such a run almost invariably provokes a policy response from the government and/or central
bank. A wide range of responses are possible and, in practice, the details of the response vary
across episodes. However, two key elements are typically present. First, at some point deposits
are frozen, meaning that further withdrawals are strictly limited. Deposit freezes were a regular
feature in U.S. banking history, with the last (and largest) occurring in March 1933, and have been
used in recent years in several developing countries.2 Second, a rescheduling of payments occurs.
Some demand deposits, for example, might be converted to time deposits with a penalty for early
withdrawal. In addition, depositors may nd that their access to funds is made contingent on
their ability to demonstrate an urgent need to withdraw; the court system in Argentina was heavily
involved in verifying individual depositors' circumstances in 2001-2.
In this paper, we study ex post ef cient policy responses to a run on the banking system and
the ex ante incentives these responses give to depositors. In focusing on responses that are ex
post ef cient, we intend to capture institutional features that prevent policymakers from being
able to pre-commit to follow a particular course of action in response to a crisis. Instead, the
authorities will intervene once the crisis is underway and attempt to bring about the most ef cient
allocation of resources given the situation. We show how the anticipation of such an intervention
can generate the conditions necessary for a self-ful lling run to occur. In other words, when
depositors anticipate that a run will be followed by an (ex post ef cient) intervention, this fact may
These gures include time deposits with penalties for early withdrawal. Demandable deposits (essentially checking
and savings accounts) fell by more than 6% on that day.
2
Friedman and Schwartz [18] provide an extensive discussion of the nationwide banking holiday of March 1933, as
well as of the numerous earlier episodes. Deposits in Argentina were frozen, with some exceptions, for a period
of 90 days on December 1, 2001; this freeze was extended in various ways until early 2003. We discuss some
details of the intervention in Argentina in Sections 3 and 4 below.
1

1

give them ex ante incentives to participate in the run. In this sense, such interventions can have a
destabilizing effect on the banking system.
Deposit freezes (sometimes called suspensions of convertibility) have been studied before, but
the focus has been almost exclusively on policies that are ex ante ef cient. The classic paper of
Diamond and Dybvig [10], for example, presented a model in which a self-ful lling bank run could
occur in equilibrium but then showed how an appropriate deposit freeze policy would remove all
incentives for depositors to run. In their setting with no aggregate uncertainty, freezing deposits
quickly enough in the event of a run guarantees that the banking system will be able to meet all
of its future obligations. Given this guarantee, depositors without an urgent need for their funds
have no incentive to withdraw and, therefore, a run will never start. Importantly, deposits are never
frozen in equilibrium; the threat of a freeze is suf cient to convince depositors not to run. Gorton
[21], Chari and Jagannathan [7], and Engineer [13] have also studied deposit freezes, but in each
case the focus was again on the policy response that would be chosen ex ante, before a crisis were
to start.
We show that the deposit freeze studied by Diamond and Dybvig [10] is typically not ex post
ef cient. In other words, if a run started and reached the point where deposits are to be frozen, a
benevolent banking authority would not want to follow through with the freeze. The intuition is
easy to see. Some of the depositors who have not yet withdrawn truly need access to their funds;
freezing deposits imposes heavy costs on these individuals. In most cases, a better policy would
be to delay the freeze or reschedule payments in a way that gives at least some funds to these
depositors. A banking authority that is unable to pre-commit to follow the complete-freeze policy,
therefore, would not choose to do so once a run is underway.
We provide the rst analysis of ex post ef cient policy interventions in the classic DiamondDybvig framework. We focus on the types of interventions observed in reality: deposit freezes,
payment reschedulings, and court interventions. We show that, compared to the Diamond-Dybvig
policy of immediately freezing deposits, the ex post ef cient policy is more lenient and allows
more funds to be withdrawn. Such withdrawals place additional strain on the banking system and
decrease the assets available to meet future obligations. This fact, in turn, increases the incentive
for a depositor to participate in the run and attempt to withdraw right away. We show that when
policy responses are ex post ef cient, self-ful lling bank runs can arise in the canonical DiamondDybvig model. This result obtains even if the authorities, by means of freezing deposits, are able

2

to halt the run and implement the rst-best continuation allocation.
Our results identify an important time-inconsistency problem in banking policy. The banking
authorities would like to claim that they will be “tough” in response to a run; this threat, if believed
by depositors, would never be tested. However, if a run were to actually start, the authorities would
not want to follow through on this threat. Instead, they would choose a more lenient policy that
ends up justifying the original decision of depositors to run. This type of time inconsistency was
informally discussed by Kydland and Prescott [27, p. 477] in the context of government investment
in ood control. As in the Kydland-Prescott example, we show that an inferior equilibrium exists
if the government cannot pre-commit to a “tough” course of action.3
Our results also contribute to the debate on the underlying causes of observed bank runs. While
there are clearly many factors at work in any speci c crisis, two distinct views have emerged regarding the basic forces driving these runs. In one view, some fundamental shock(s) cause banks
to become insolvent; depositors eventually realize the situation and then rush to withdraw their
funds. In this view, a run is always a symptom of the underlying problems in the banking sector.4
The second view, in contrast, holds that runs can also be caused by the self-ful lling beliefs of depositors. Individuals may rush to withdraw because they believe the withdrawals of others threaten
the solvency of the banking system; the resulting run is a form of coordination failure. In this view,
the run is a major contributing factor to the overall crisis, not a mere symptom.
The complexity of real-world banking crises makes it extremely dif cult to determine the “true”
underlying cause of an observed episode (see Calomiris and Mason [5] and Ennis [14]). One useful
research agenda, therefore, is to ask whether or not self-ful lling runs are plausible, in the sense of
being equilibrium outcomes of a reasonable economic model. This agenda began with the seminal
work of Bryant [3] and Diamond and Dybvig [10]. As described above, however, self-ful lling
runs can be ruled out in the basic Diamond-Dybvig framework if policymakers can pre-commit to
immediately freeze deposits when faced with a run.5 We show that when the intervention is instead
chosen ex post, a self-ful lling run equilibrium can exist. Our approach thus provides one possible
answer to the question of “what's missing?” in the Diamond-Dybvig model posed by Green and
Lin [23].
See also the discussion in King [25]. Similar implications of a government's inability to commit are discussed
in Glomm and Ravikumar [19], Albanesi, et al. [1], and King and Wolman [26].
4
See, for example, Gorton [21], Saunders and Wilson [29], Calomiris and Mason [4], and Allen and Gale [2].
5
For this reason, the recent literature has focused on more complex environments where aggregate liquidity demand
is random (see, for example, Green and Lin [22] and Peck and Shell [28]).
3

3

The remainder of the paper is organized as follows. In Section 2 we present the basic model,
including banking with demand deposit contracts and deposit freezes. In Section 3 we study the
decision of when to freeze deposits in response to a bank run, and we derive conditions under
which a self-ful lling run cannot be ruled out when this decision is made ex post, once the run is
underway. The focus of Section 4 is on interventions in which the court system determines which
depositors have an urgent need to withdraw. We show that such interventions can actually make
it more dif cult for the banking authorities to rule out self-ful lling runs. We also show that such
runs can occur even when the courts are able to implement the rst-best continuation allocation ex
post. Finally, in Section 5 we offer some concluding remarks.

2 The Basic Model
Our basic framework is the now-standard model of Cooper and Ross [8], which generalizes the
Diamond and Dybvig [10] environment by introducing costly liquidation and a non-trivial portfolio
choice.
2.1

The environment

There are three time periods, indexed by t = 0, 1, 2. There is a continuum of ex ante identical
depositors with measure one. Each depositor has preferences given by
(c1 + c2 )1
u (c1 ; c2 ; ) =
1

;

where ct is consumption in period t; is a binomial random variable with support f0; 1g; and

>0

holds. If the realized value of is zero, the depositor is impatient and only cares about consumption
in period 1: A depositor's type (patient or impatient) is private information and is revealed to her at
the beginning of period 1: Let

denote the probability with which each individual depositor will

be impatient. By a law of large numbers,
will be impatient. Note that

is also the fraction of depositors in the population who

is non-stochastic; there is no aggregate uncertainty in this model.

The economy is endowed with one unit of the consumption good per capita in period 0. There
are two constant-returns-to-scale technologies for transforming this endowment into consumption
in the later periods. A unit of the good placed into storage in period 0 yields one unit of the good in
either period 1 or period 2. A unit placed into investment in period 0 yields either R > 1 in period

4

2 or 1

in period 1; where

2 (0; 1) represents a liquidation cost. In other words, investment

offers a higher long-term return than storage but is relatively illiquid in the short term.

Depositors can pool resources to form a bank,6 which allows them to insure against individual
liquidity risk and minimize costly liquidation. There is also a benevolent banking authority (BA),
which has the power to freeze deposits in period 1 if it deems that doing so would increase the
welfare of depositors. In Section 4, we introduce a court system that can, once a deposit freeze has
been declared, verify depositors' types and, potentially, reschedule payments.
The timing of events is as follows. We begin our analysis with all endowments deposited in the
bank.7 In period 0; the bank divides these resources between storage and investment. In period
1, depositors are isolated from each other and no trade can occur (as described in Wallace [31]).
However, each depositor has the ability to contact the bank and, hence, the bank can make payments to depositors from the pooled resources after types have been realized. Depositors choose
between contacting the bank in period 1 and waiting until period 2. Those who choose to contact
the bank in period 1 do so in a randomly-assigned order; they do not know this order when they
decide whether or not to contact the bank.8 The payment made by the bank to a particular depositor during period 1 can only be contingent on the number of previous withdrawals and not on
the actions of depositors who have yet to withdraw. This sequential-service constraint captures an
essential feature of banking: the banking system pays depositors as they arrive and cannot condition current payments to depositors on future information. We assume that the BA and the courts
are also subject to the sequential-service constraint. Hence, for example, a deposit freeze can only
apply to funds that have not yet been withdrawn; it cannot be made retroactive.
2.2

The rst-best allocation

In this subsection we provide a benchmark against which the ef ciency of the alternative scenarios
can be evaluated. Suppose a planner could observe each depositor's type and assign an allocation
based on these types. We call the allocation the planner would assign the rst-best allocation. This
As is standard in the literature, this representative bank can be interpreted as the outcome of competition for
deposits (with free entry) in period 0:
7
For simplicity, we do not examine explicitly the deposit decision of agents (the “pre-deposit game” of Peck and
Shell [28]); our approach is the same as that in Diamond and Dybvig [10]. As will become clear later in the
paper, our results can be extended to include the pre-deposit game in the usual way.
8
This assumption, which is standard in the literature, simpli es matters by ensuring that all depositors face the same
decision problem, rather than potentially facing different problems depending on their order of arrival at the bank. Most
of the results below would also hold if this order were known in advance (see Ennis and Keister [17] for such
an analysis).
6

5

allocation would clearly give consumption to impatient depositors only in period 1 and to patient
depositors only in period 2: Let cE denote the amount given to impatient depositors (who consume
“early”) and cL the amount given to patient depositors (who consume “late”). Let i denote the
fraction of the total endowment placed into investment; the remaining 1

i would go into storage.

Then the planner would choose cE , cL , and i to solve
1

max

(cE )1

1

subject to

+ (1

)

cE = 1
(1
cE

1
1

(cL )1
(1)

i;

)cL = Ri;
0; and 0

0; cL

i

1:

The solution to this problem is
cE =

1
+ (1

)R

;

1

cL =

and
i =

R

(1

)R

+ (1

+ (1

1

)R

1

;

(2)

1

)R

1

:

Notice that cL > cE necessarily holds, meaning that patient depositors consume more than impatient ones.
In order for the possibility of bank runs to arise, the following condition on parameter values
must hold.
Assumption 1. (1

)R(1

)=

< 1.

This assumption implies that cE > 1

i , or that the amount of consumption given to an im-

patient depositor in the rst-best allocation is greater than the per-capita liquidation value of all
assets in period 1. The planner's allocation thus provides liquidity insurance by cross-subsidizing
those depositors who turn out to be impatient. Notice that this assumption will hold if
(liquidation costs are signi cant) and/or

is large

is large (depositors are suf ciently risk averse). We

maintain Assumption 1 throughout.

6

For the remainder of this section and the next, we restrict attention to the case of

< 1 so that

u(0; 0; ) = 0 holds. This assumption is used primarily to simplify the exposition. Our results can
be generalized to the case of

> 1 in a straightforward way by changing the utility function to
u(c1 ; c2 ; ) =

(c1 + c2 + b)1
1

b1

(3)

where b is an arbitrarily small scalar.
2.3

Banking with demand deposits

Diamond and Dybvig [10] showed how a bank offering demand-deposit contracts can generate
the rst-best allocation described above as an equilibrium outcome, even though depositors' types
are private information. Suppose the bank allows each depositor to choose whether to withdraw
her funds in period 1 or in period 2. It offers depositors withdrawing in period 1 a pre-speci ed
payment cE (as long as the bank has funds), while depositors withdrawing in period 2 receive a
pro-rata share of the matured assets. In effect, the demand-deposit contract generates a game in
which each depositor observes her own type and then chooses in which period to withdraw. Note
that this arrangement clearly respects the sequential service constraint.
If the bank invests a fraction i of its assets and sets the early payment equal to cE , then there
is an equilibrium of this game in which the rst-best allocation obtains. To see why, rst note
that an impatient depositor will always choose to withdraw in period 1: A patient depositor, on the
other hand, may base her decision on what she expects others to do. If she expects all other patient
depositors to wait until period 2 to withdraw, then she anticipates receiving cE if she withdraws
early and cL if she waits. Since cL > cE holds (see (2)), her best response is to wait. Hence, there
is an equilibrium where all patient depositors wait until period 2 to withdraw and the rst-best
allocation obtains.
Diamond and Dybvig also pointed out, however, that under this simple deposit contract – absent
any intervention – there exists another equilibrium in which all depositors attempt to withdraw in
period 1. Suppose an individual patient depositor expects all others (both impatient and patient) to
withdraw in period 1. Under Assumption 1 she knows that the bank will not be able to satisfy all
of these withdrawal requests. Depositors who contact the bank early enough will receive cE ; but a
depositor who arrives late in period 1 or waits until period 2 will receive nothing. Her best response
in this situation is to also attempt to withdraw in period 1 and, thus, there is an equilibrium where

7

all depositors try to withdraw at once. This equilibrium resembles a run on the banking system.9
We say that the banking system is fragile if this run equilibrium exists when the period-1 payment on demand deposits is set at cE . Note that fragility does not imply that a run would necessarily
occur. If the bank anticipates a run, for example, it might offer depositors a payment different from
cE in period 1 in an attempt to prevent the run. The important point is that whenever the banking
system is fragile, the possibility of a run will generate costly distortions in the economy. These
costs can come through an ex ante distortion of the banking contract away from the rst-best allocation, the ex post inef ciency caused by the occurrence of a run, or both. We discuss these
issues in more detail in Section 3.3. Here, it suf ces to say that only when the banking system is
not fragile can the potential problems associated with self-ful lling bank runs be safely ignored.
Our interest, therefore, is in whether or not (and under what conditions) deposit freeze policies can
eliminate this fragility and ensure that the rst-best allocation of resources is achieved.
2.4

Bank runs and deposit freezes

After pointing out the fragility of the simple demand-deposit contract, Diamond and Dybvig
showed how a particular deposit freeze policy could make the rst-best allocation the unique equilibrium outcome. In practice, a deposit freeze is the most common policy response to a banking
panic. As mentioned above, such freezes (often called “banking holidays”) were a regular occurrence in the U.S. prior to 1933. More recently, Brazil (1990), Ecuador (1999), and Argentina
(2001) have declared widespread deposit freezes to stop the out ow of deposits from the banking
system (see IMF [24]).
In the model, “normal times” are associated with
than

withdrawals occurring in period 1. If more

withdrawals take place in period 1; the BA realizes that a run must be underway and reacts

to this information. Suppose it is known that the BA will completely freeze deposits whenever
more than

depositors attempt to withdraw in period 1. In other words, after paying the speci ed

amount cE to a fraction

of depositors in period 1, the BA will direct the bank to suspend further

payments to depositors until period 2. Diamond and Dybvig [10] showed that this policy rules out
the bank run equilibrium and renders the rst-best allocation the unique equilibrium outcome in
We follow the literature based on the Diamond-Dybvig model in studying deposits that are denominated in real
terms. In such case, a sudden increase in withdrawal demand cannot be met by simply printing additional currency, as
could be done if contracts were nominal. This assumption matches the situation in many emerging market economies,
where a large fraction of deposits are denominated in foreign currencies. (See the discussion in Diamond and Rajan
[11].) In Argentina, for example, over 60% of deposits were denominated in U.S. dollars in early 2001.

9

8

this economy.
Proposition 1 (Diamond and Dybvig [10]) If deposits are frozen after
the banking system is not fragile.

withdrawals in period 1,

The intuition behind this result is simple. If a patient depositor believes the BA will freeze
deposits after a fraction

of depositors has withdrawn in period 1, then she is certain that the

bank will have enough resources to pay at least cL in period 2: Since cL > cE holds, waiting to
withdraw is a strictly dominant strategy for her, and the only equilibrium has all patient depositors
withdrawing in period 2. Note that deposits will never actually be frozen in equilibrium, because a
run never takes place. In this way, the BA can costlessly eliminate the possibility of a bank run by
means of a temporary deposit freeze.
2.5

Discussion

The deposit freezes observed in reality often differ in at least two important ways from the one
studied by Diamond and Dybvig [10] and described in our Proposition 1. First, the freeze is
usually declared relatively late in the course of the overall crisis. Figure 1 presents the evolution of
total bank deposits in Argentina during the crisis of 2001-2. From their peak on February 28, 2001,
total deposits had fallen 21.8% by the time the freeze was declared on December 1, 2001.10 If the
deposit freeze in the model is delayed and more than

withdrawals take place in period 1, the

payments the bank is able to make in period 2 will decrease. If the freeze is delayed long enough,
patient depositors might prefer to participate in the run and the result in Proposition 1 could be
overturned.
Second, deposits are often not frozen completely; some types of withdrawals may still be allowed. In Argentina, for example, during the freeze announced on December 1, 2001, depositors
were allowed to withdraw up to 1,000 pesos per month from each account. A similar policy was
used in Brazil during the freeze implemented in March 1990. In addition, the court system in
Argentina ordered banks to make payments to a large number of depositors after the freeze was
The large upward jump in January 2002 corresponds to the abandonment of the currency board and devaluation
of the peso. Dollar-denominated deposits, which were approximately 70% of the total, were converted into pesos
at the of cial exchange rate of 1.4 pesos/dollar. This conversion increased total deposits, measured in pesos, by
approximately 28%, as depicted in the gure. It is also interesting to note that several run-like events in the summer of
2001 and again in October 2001 did not lead to deposit freezes. In each of these cases, the authorities were able
to halt the decline in deposits through various announcements aimed at restoring con dence, such as scal adjustment
measures and an increase in IMF standy-by credit. See Dominguez and Tesar [12] for details.

10

9

in place. Figure 1 shows how total deposits in the banking system in Argentina continued to fall
dramatically after the freeze was declared. Such additional payments from the banking system also
tend to undermine the incentives for patient depositors to wait and could potentially overturn the
result in Proposition 1.
Figure 1: Evolution of Deposits During the Crisis in Argentina 2001-2
90,000
Total Deposits (Million of Pesos)
85,000

80,000

75,000

70,000
Deposit Freeze
Devaluation
65,000

001

001

2
:200
June
002
May:2
002
Mar:2
002
Feb:2
002
Jan:2
001
Dec:2
001
Nov:2
001
Oct:2
2001
Sept:
001
Aug:2
001
July:2
1
:200
June
001
May:2
001

Apr:2

Mar:2

001
Jan:2

Feb:2

Source: Ministry of the Economy and Production of Argentina.

In the remainder of the paper, we investigate why the authorities might choose to allow additional withdrawals when a run is underway, even though these withdrawals place further strain on
the banking system. In light of Proposition 1, the BA would clearly like to pre-commit to freezing
deposits after

early withdrawals. The experience from crises in Argentina and other countries

indicates that institutional factors may limit the ability of the banking authorities to pre-commit
to future actions. For this reason, we proceed by assuming that the BA decides interventions only
as the crisis develops. To isolate the implications of lack of commitment from other governmentinduced distortions, we assume the BA reacts optimally, given that a crisis is underway. In other
words, we focus on policy responses that are ex post ef cient, and we describe the implications of
such policy responses for the fragility of the banking system. We begin by examining the decision
of when to declare a deposit freeze.

10

3 Choosing When to Freeze
In this section, we investigate the incentives a benevolent banking authority faces in deciding
when to declare a deposit freeze and how this ex post decision, in turn, affects the ex ante incentives
of depositors to participate in a run. Consider a situation where the bank has already paid out cE
to a fraction

of depositors. If additional depositors attempt to withdraw in period 1; the BA

recognizes that something abnormal is occurring. In our simple model, if more than

depositors

attempt to withdraw, a run must be underway. The BA then recognizes that some of the funds
already paid out were given to depositors who are actually patient. Furthermore, it knows that
some impatient depositors have not yet been served and will be attempting to withdraw. Freezing
deposits immediately after

withdrawals implies giving nothing to these impatient depositors,

which may be very costly from a social point of view.
3.1

Ex post ef cient deposit freezes

When would a benevolent banking authority choose to freeze deposits? Let

s

denote the “freeze

point,” that is, the fraction of depositors the BA would choose to serve when faced with a run
before freezing deposits. Then the BA would seek to maximize depositor welfare by solving the
following problem:
1

max W ( s )
f

s

sg

(cE )1

1

+ (1

s )(1

)

1
1

[cL ( s )]1

(4)

subject to
R

cL ( s ) =

The objective (4) states that a fraction
period 2. The remaining fraction

(1
(1

i
)(1

s cE )
s)

and

(5)

:

s

receive cE : Of the remaining 1

1

s

s

of depositors will be served in period 1 and each will

depositors, only a fraction 1

will be patient and return in

will be impatient and will receive nothing, leaving them with

a utility level of zero. The function cL ( s ) in (5) represents the consumption of patient depositors
who are forced by the freeze to return in period 2; the numerator equals the total resources of the
bank in period 2 while the denominator is the mass of patient depositors who were not served in

11

period 1.11 The second constraint re ects sequential service: the BA only discovers that a run is
underway after
Let

M
s

withdrawals have been made and, thus,

is the earliest possible freeze point.

denote the solution to this problem, which is implicitly de ned by
W0

M
s

0;

and = 0 if

M
s

> :

In making their withdrawal decisions, depositors recognize that the BA lacks the ability to precommit to a speci c plan of action and that it will, therefore, react to a run by freezing deposits
only after

M
s

withdrawals have been made. Our interest is in whether or not a self-ful lling run

can arise when depositors anticipate this policy response.
3.2

Equilibrium under the ef cient policy

The ef cient freeze point

M
s

may be equal to ; in which case Proposition 1 applies and the

banking system will not be fragile. In fact, the BA does not need to freeze deposits right at

in

order for this result to obtain; it is suf cient for the BA to suspend at any point where it can still
afford to give more than cE to depositors who are paid in period 2: Since the function cL ( s ) is
strictly decreasing, there is an interval of such values as shown in the following lemma. A proof of
this result is given in the Appendix.
Lemma 1 There exists a value T > such that if deposits are frozen after
any s 2 [ ; T ); the banking system is not fragile.

s

withdrawals for

This lemma shows that the effectiveness of a deposit freeze policy in preventing a self-ful lling
run depends crucially on whether the credible freeze point
old value

T

M
s

is smaller or larger than the thresh-

. (See Figure 2.) If it is smaller, the BA will be expected to impose the freeze relatively

quickly and cL

M
s

> cE would hold. In such case, a patient depositor – anticipating the “early”

freeze – is better off waiting than participating in the run and, hence, a run will never start. However, if

M
s

is greater than

T

; the BA is expected to impose a deposit freeze relatively late and

depositors who wait to withdraw during a run will receive less than cE : A patient depositor who
expects others to run will, therefore, choose to run as well and a self-ful lling bank run can arise.
We assume that impatient depositors who are not served in period 1 do not come back to the bank in period
2 since they have no desire to consume. The results would be qualitatively similar if these depositors did contact the BA
and receive a share of the remaining funds.

11

12

Figure 2: Period 2 Payoff after a Deposit Freeze at

s

The next proposition is the main result of this section. It shows that for some parameter values,
the ef cient deposit freeze occurs too late to rule out the possibility of a self-ful lling run. A proof
of the proposition is given in the Appendix.
Proposition 2 The banking system is fragile under the (ex post) ef cient deposit freeze if and only
if
1
R
1 :
(6)
1
Condition (6) shows that the banking system will tend to not be fragile if

is small. When rel-

atively few depositors have a real need to consume early, the cost of temporarily freezing deposits
and leaving these depositors with nothing is relatively small. In addition, a large proportion of
any additional payments made in period 1 during the run would go to depositors who are actually
patient. The optimal response to a run in this case is to freeze deposits relatively early and preserve
a high payment for the large number of patient depositors expected to come back and withdraw
in period 2:12 Notice that the condition will necessarily be violated if the right-hand side of the
inequality is greater than one, or if we have
1

<1

R

:

(7)

It is worth noting that if is small enough, W 0 ( ) 0 will hold and the ex post ef cient policy will set M
s = : In
this case, and only in this case, the BA would choose to follow the policy proposed by Diamond and Dybvig [10]
of freezing deposits immediately after identifying a run.

12

13

In this case, the ef cient deposit freeze occurs early enough to rule out a self-ful lling run for any
value of . Depositors must exhibit a minimal amount of risk aversion for bank runs to be an issue
in this framework.
On the other hand, notice that for any given values of ; R; and ; condition (6) will hold if

is

close enough to unity. In other words, xing all other parameter values, the ef cient deposit freeze
occurs too late to rule out a self-ful lling run equilibrium if depositors are suf ciently risk averse.
We state this result in the following corollary.
Corollary 1 If depositors are suf ciently risk averse, the banking system will be fragile.

3.3

Discussion

The results above give conditions under which the banking system is fragile and conditions under
which it is not. When it is not fragile (that is, when the equilibrium is unique), this is clearly the
end of the story – no bank run will occur and the rst-best allocation will obtain. What happens
in the fragile case, where the equilibrium is not unique? Would a bank run and the subsequent
deposit freeze actually occur? These questions raise the dif cult issue of equilibrium selection, a
formal analysis of which is beyond the scope of the present paper. However, it is relatively easy to
see how the standard approach in the existing literature can be applied to our model and why our
results above capture the essential elements at play.
The most common approach to equilibrium selection in this type of model is to assume that
depositors condition their actions on the realization of an extrinsic “sunspot” variable; the run
equilibrium is played if spots appear on the sun and the no-run equilibrium is played if no spots
appear. The probability of a run is then equal to the (exogenous) probability of sunspots. The
payment offered by the bank in period 1 may depend on this probability but not on the realization
of the sunspot variable, because the latter is not observed by the banking authorities. This approach
was suggested in Diamond and Dybvig [10, p. 410] and explicitly taken in Cooper and Ross [8],
Peck and Shell [28], and others.
Whether or not a run occurs in equilibrium under this approach depends on both the ex ante
probability of sunspots and the realization of this variable. If the probability is high, for example,
banks may choose to offer a payment much smaller than cE in order to convince depositors not to
run. Cooper and Ross [8] labelled such a deposit contract “run proof.” Run-proof contracts imply

14

that depositors receive low levels of liquidity insurance and, hence, generate substantially lower
welfare than the rst-best allocation. For this reason, if the probability of sunspots is low enough
then choosing a run-proof deposit contract will not be optimal.13
Two main conclusions emerge from this type of analysis. First, whenever the banking system is
fragile, an equilibrium can be constructed in which a run occurs with positive probability and all
contracting and deposit decisions take this probability into account (see Peck and Shell [28]). In
our model, this equilibrium will include a deposit freeze in states where a run occurs.14 Second,
the ex ante possibility of a run will lead banks to choose a period-1 payment different from cE ; so
that the rst-best allocation does not obtain even in states where a run/freeze does not occur (see
Cooper and Ross [8] and Ennis and Keister [16]).
An alternative approach would be to attempt to use the global-games techniques developed by
Carlsson and van Damme [6] and others to eliminate the potential multiplicity of equilibrium.
Goldstein and Pauzner [20] show how the Diamond-Dybvig model can be modi ed for this purpose.15 However, as is clear from their analysis, using the global-games approach in this setting
requires many additional assumptions that would complicate the analysis and distract the focus
away from the effects we intend to highlight here. Furthermore, the ex post interventions in our
framework seem likely to have important effects on the structure of beliefs and, hence, may tend
to undermine the uniqueness of equilibrium. Nevertheless, we conjecture that such an exercise,
if successful, would lead to the same conclusion as the sunspots-based approach described above:
under the conditions we identify in this paper, the possibility of self-ful lling bank runs distorts
the allocation of resources away from the rst-best.
The bottom line, therefore, is that whenever the banking system is fragile, the possibility of
self-ful lling runs will create costly distortions in the economy. Our results above characterize
the conditions under which this happens if the authorities choose when to freeze deposits in order
to maximize (ex post) depositor welfare. In the next section we examine what happens when the
court system can intervene and verify depositors' types.
Ennis and Keister [17] explicitly formulate this argument in a related model. See Ennis and Keister [15] for
a general discussion of policy choices and equilibrium selection in environments with strategic complementarities.
14
In other words, a deposit freeze occurs along the equilibrium path of play in our model. This result contrasts sharply
with Diamond and Dybvig [10], where the threat of a deposit freeze eliminates the possibility of a run.
15
In Goldstein and Pauzner [20], pre-commitment is implicitly assumed and the set of possible contracts is exogenously restricted to generate the potential for multiplicity. In our environment, in contrast, multiplicity arises naturally as a result of ex post ef cient government intervention.
13

15

4 Court Intervention
After the authorities declare a deposit freeze, the court system may become involved in the
resolution of the crisis. For example, in Argentina in 2001, depositors claiming to have urgent
nancial needs (due to, for example, illness or hospitalization) could le a legal recourse requesting
withdrawal of some or all of their funds from the banking system while the freeze was in place.
Nearly 200,000 such cases were led between December 2001 and June 2003, and the courts
awarded payments to depositors totaling over 14 billion pesos (see Table 1). Of the value of
total deposits in the system as of March 2002 (around 65 billion pesos) more than 21% were
paid out to depositors via legal recourse. This process of legal mediation was based, in part, on
the presumption that the courts had at least some ability to differentiate between depositors who
needed funds urgently and those who did not. In this section, we investigate how such court
interventions can affect the (ex ante) fragility of the banking system.

Table 1: Legal Recourses during Deposit Freeze in Argentina 2001-2003

Period

Number

Total

Total Drop in

Average Size

of

Payment

Banks' Liabilities

of Payment

Court Cases

(Mill. Pesos)

(Mill. Pesos)

(Pesos)

Dec., 2001 - April, 2002

28,430

2,346

1,312

82,518

May - June, 2002

28,285

2,124

1,026

75,093

Dec., 2001 - June, 2002

56,715

4,470

2,338

78,815

July - Dec., 2002

92,926

7,109

3,834

76,502

Jan. - June, 2003

42,249

2,437

1,643

57,682

Total (Dec. 2001 - June 2003)

191,890

14,016

7,815

73,042

Source: Central Bank of Argentina. Note: The term “Court Cases” (Recursos de Amparo) stands for court-ordered repayments of individuals' frozen deposits. Banks' deposit liabilities were accounted in pesos after converting dollar deposits
into pesos at the of cial post-devaluation exchange rate of 1.4 pesos per dollar (the liability also includes the indexation
called CER). However, some payments to depositors (second column) were made for the dollar amount of the deposits
(according to court rule). Hence, total payments (in pesos) tends to be larger than the accounting value (third column).16

16

We are grateful to Fernando Navajas for sharing this data with us.

16

In the context of our model, suppose that once the BA declares a deposit freeze, the court system
intervenes and veri es the true type of each remaining depositor.17 In principle, one would expect
verifying types to involve some administrative costs. To keep the analysis as simple as possible,
we abstract from such costs: we assume that type veri cation occurs costlessly, but only after
depositors have already withdrawn and the BA has declared a deposit freeze. This assumption
prevents the system from using the courts to completely overcome the private information problem.
With a positive veri cation cost, it would be optimal not to screen the types of the rst individuals
to withdraw if the likelihood of facing a run is relatively small. On the other hand, if the cost is not
too high, using the veri cation technology will be desirable ex post, after the deposit freeze has
been declared.
We consider two cases. First, we assume that the courts insist on giving the promised period-1
payment cE to all impatient depositors. Originally, depositors entered into a contract with the bank
stating that they would receive cE if they needed to withdraw early. After the run is discovered,
the courts may consider it their duty to maintain this promised value of the early payment. We call
this the no-rescheduling case.
Once a run is underway and a deposit freeze has been declared, however, it would be socially
optimal to reschedule payments. In particular, it would be optimal to pay the remaining impatient
depositors less than cE in order to economize on costly asset liquidation and preserve resources for
the patient depositors. In the second case we consider, the courts make this adjustment and thereby
are able to implement the rst-best continuation allocation for the remaining 1

depositors. We

call this the case of intervention with payment rescheduling.
The basic logic is similar for the two cases. The courts, by verifying types, ensure that all
additional period-1 payments go to agents who truly need to consume early. As a result, the
authorities give away more resources in period 1 than they would under a simple deposit-freeze
policy, which, in turn, reduces the amount of resources available in period 2. This fact makes
waiting to withdraw (i.e., not participating in the run) less attractive to a patient depositor. In other
words, by improving the allocation of resources ex post, a court intervention can increase the ex
ante incentive for patient depositors to run and, hence, increase the fragility of the banking system.
Gorton [21] offers a related interpretation of the role of a suspension of payments. He studies an environment
where the value of the bank's assets is random and imperfectly observed by depositors. If a suspension of payments
triggers a costly state-veri cation of the value of the assets, then Gorton shows that, in some cases, the suspension
can actually be Pareto improving (speci cally, in those cases when depositors are more pessimistic than is warranted by
the true state of the assets, which is assumed to be known by the entity declaring the suspension).

17

17

4.1

No rescheduling of payments

Suppose that once deposits are frozen the courts are expected to intervene, verify which depositors
are truly impatient, and honor the original commitment of the bank by awarding cE to each impatient depositor. It is clear that under this expectation, a benevolent BA would declare a deposit
freeze immediately after discovering that a run is underway, that is, after
Once the courts have intervened and veri ed types, the remaining

(1

withdrawals in period 1.
) impatient depositors

)2 patient depositors will be paid in period 2;

will each have received cE : The remaining (1
each will receive
cLC

R
2

(1

)

(1
(1

i

)
c
:
) E

Our interest is in whether or not the conditions necessary for a self-ful lling run can arise when
depositors anticipate this type of court intervention. What action would a patient depositor take at
the beginning of period 1 if she expects other patient depositors to run? If cLC > cE holds, she
would wait until period 2 to withdraw and the run equilibrium would not exist. In this case, the
banking system would not be fragile; the combination of a deposit freeze with court intervention
would make the rst-best allocation the unique equilibrium. Note that in such a case the courts
would never intervene in equilibrium; the fact that depositors anticipate this intervention would
prevent a run from ever starting. However, if the reversed inequality holds, that is cLC

cE , then a

patient depositor expecting a run would choose to withdraw and, hence, the run equilibrium cannot
be ruled out. The following proposition characterizes the set of parameter values for which each
case applies.
Proposition 3 The banking system is fragile under a deposit freeze with court intervention and
no rescheduling if and only if we have
(1
R

)
(1

)

R

1

1 :

(8)

Once again, we see that the banking system will be fragile if there are suf ciently many impatient depositors. It is interesting to compare condition (8) with condition (6) in Proposition
3. Recall that (6) is the necessary and suf cient condition for fragility under an ef cient deposit
freeze without court intervention. Straightforward algebra shows that when liquidation costs are
high, condition (6) is stronger than condition (8). In such cases, there exist intermediate values

18

of

such that (i) without court intervention the (ex post) ef cient deposit freeze prevents banking

system fragility, but (ii) with court intervention the banking system is fragile. We formalize this
result in the following proposition. The proof is straightforward and thus omitted.
Proposition 4 Given all other parameter values, there exists ^ 2 [0; 1) such that for all
condition (8) holds but condition (6) is violated for an interval of values for .

^;

In other words, court intervention can undermine the BA's ability to ensure, by freezing deposits,
that the most desirable allocation is the unique equilibrium. The logic is simple. When the BA
anticipates a court intervention, it declares a deposit freeze quickly (immediately after discovering
the run) but the courts still mandate payments to impatient depositors in period 1. If liquidation
costs are high, making these payments is very costly and the funds available for period 2 payments
are highly depleted. Instead, if court intervention is not possible, while the BA may delay the
freeze of deposits, after the freeze is declared no further payments are made in period 1. This
complete halt in payments reduces the total payout (and early liquidation) in period 1 and thus
allows a relatively high payment to those depositors withdrawing in period 2. The anticipation of
high payments in period 2 makes running no longer an equilibrium strategy.
We can go a step further and ask whether or not the (benevolent) BA would actually want the
courts to intervene. Proposition 4 shows that, at least for some parameter values, in period 0 the
BA would like to obtain a prior commitment from the courts that they would not intervene in the
event of a freeze. However, it is not dif cult to show that for some of these same parameter values,
once a run is discovered in period 1 the BA would prefer to have the courts intervene because
such intervention leads to a better allocation of resources. In this sense, the possibility of court
intervention introduces a new kind of time-inconsistency problem. Even in cases where a credible
deposit freeze would be able to eliminate the possibility of a bank run, the inability to credibly rule
out a court intervention in the event of a run could render the banking system vulnerable to a run.
4.2

Payment rescheduling

The intervention policy studied above involves a somewhat arti cial restriction: the courts insist
on repaying the amount cE originally promised to depositors withdrawing in period 1. We now
relax this restriction and allow the courts to reschedule payments if they conclude that doing so
can improve depositor welfare.

19

As before, the bank pays cE to the rst

depositors who withdraw in period 1. If more than

depositors attempt to withdraw in period 1; the BA realizes that a run is underway and will choose
to immediately declare a deposit freeze. Once the freeze is in place, the courts intervene and verify
which depositors are truly impatient. The only difference from the earlier case is that we now allow
the courts to decide how much each of the remaining impatient depositors should be paid in period
1. This payment is chosen to solve the following problem:18
max (1

)

cE ;cL ;i

1
1

(cE )1

+ (1

(1

)i ;
(1

)

1
1

(cL )1

subject to
(1
(1

) cE

)2 cL = R i
cE

Of the 1

0 and cL

remaining depositors, a fraction

while a fraction 1

) cE
;
(1
)
0:

are impatient and will be served in period 1

are patient and will be told to come bank in period 2: The rst constraint

in the problem re ects the fact that all of the resources in storage have already been paid out to
the rst

depositors who withdrew; additional period-1 payments can only come from liquidat-

ing investment. The second constraint is the standard pro-rata share of remaining resources that
determines the payment in period 2. The solution to this problem is given by
cER =
where

1
+ (1

(1
b (1
)R

Note that cLR > cER holds.19

)i
)

and

cLR =

b = [R=(1
R

)](1

R
1

)=

b
R

+ (1

(1
b (1
)R

)i
)

(9)

:

At the beginning of period 1; depositors anticipate that the BA will respond to a run by declaring
a freeze, triggering a court intervention and resulting in the continuation payments (cER ; cLR ).
Note that the solution to this problem is the rst-best allocation for the continuation economy after agents
have each received cE from the banking system.
19
Note that in the analysis that follows, there are no circumstances in which some depositors receive zero consumption and, therefore, we can study the case where the coef cient of relative risk aversion is greater than one without changing the form of the utility function to (3).
18

20

Given these payments, would a patient depositor choose to run at the beginning of period 1 if she
believes that all other depositors will? A patient depositor who believes that all other depositors
are running will have an expected payoff of
1

(cE )1

1

+ (1

)

1
1

(cLR )1

if she also runs, but will receive cLR for certain if she does not run. Using (2) and (9), it is
straightforward to show that

1 implies that cLR

cL > cE holds and, therefore, the depositor

would prefer not to run. In other words, the run equilibrium cannot exist when

is less than unity.

We summarize this discussion in the following proposition.
Proposition 5 For 2 (0; 1]; under a deposit freeze with court intervention and payment rescheduling the banking system is not fragile.
Proposition 5 shows that if the coef cient of relative risk aversion is less than unity then, regardless of the size of the liquidation cost, the possibility of a deposit freeze followed by a court
intervention that reschedules payments will allow the economy to achieve the rst-best allocation
without raising the possibility of a self-ful lling run. In addition, it is straightforward to show that
< 1 implies (1

) cER

) i . In other words, even if the courts would assign cER in

(1

period 1 to all remaining depositors, there would be enough liquidity in the system to cover those
payments. This fact, in turn, implies that even if the courts were not to verify types after the intervention, only impatient depositors would appeal to the courts to obtain the early payment cER . In
a sense, veri cation of types is redundant in this case.20
Things are different when

> 1. In this case, it is possible for cLR

cE to hold and, hence,

for a patient depositor to choose to run when she expects others to do so. Straightforward algebra
shows that this condition is equivalent to the following:

R

1

R

1

1

+ (1

)

R

1

1:

(10)

1

We can now state the main result of this section.
The payments (cER ; cLR ) constitute a run-proof contract (Cooper and Ross [8]). Even if agents expect the courts
to be lenient in their veri cation of types (i.e., in determining who has urgent needs and who does not), the payoff
cER is low enough that there is no danger of a “run” to the courts.

20

21

Proposition 6 The banking system is fragile under a deposit freeze with court intervention and
payment rescheduling if and only if (10) holds.
Notice that (10) will necessarily be violated if

is close to zero, which is reminiscent of Propo-

sition 2 in the previous section. When there are relatively few impatient depositors, the additional
early payments ordered by the courts amount to a relatively moderate sum and, hence, there will be
suf cient assets left to offer a relatively high payment to depositors in period 2. Also notice that,
consistent with Proposition 5, condition (10) cannot hold if

is less than unity. However, if

is

greater than unity then, given all other parameter values, for high enough values of the liquidation
cost

the condition will hold. In other words, if the coef cient of relative risk aversion is greater

than one, whenever liquidation costs are large the banking system will be fragile.
Corollary 2 For any > 1; there exists a < 1 such that
implies that the banking system
is fragile under a deposit freeze with court intervention and payment rescheduling.
Villamil [30] suggests that a way to commit to a full suspension of payments is by making investments that cannot, under any circumstances, be liquidated (and shows how the optimal lending
contract can have this property in some settings). This idea can be captured in our notation by
setting

= 1; in which case suspending payments after all liquid assets have been depleted is

clearly ex post ef cient. However, Corollary 2 points out the knife-edge nature of this argument.
If liquidation is costly but not impossible (i.e.,

is close to but not equal to 1), the courts will

still mandate the liquidation of some investment after a deposit freeze and the possibility of a run
cannot be ruled out.
Given a value of the liquidation cost (and all other parameter values), condition (10) will also
hold if

is large enough. The result in Proposition 6 can, therefore, be stated another way: the

rst-best allocation cannot be obtained without introducing the possibility of a run if depositors
are suf ciently risk averse.
Corollary 3 There exists < 0 such that
implies that the banking system is fragile under
a deposit freeze with court intervention and payment rescheduling.

22

5 Concluding Remarks
The previous literature on bank runs has concluded that self-ful lling runs can typically be
prevented if there is enough exibility in the scheme for setting payments to depositors.21 In light
of this nding, it seems natural to conjecture that any viable explanation of self-ful lling runs
will require taking into consideration institutional restrictions that might limit such exibility. Our
focus has been on a set of realistic, ex post ef cient interventions that can be regarded as providing
microfoundations for such limitations. The results presented in the previous literature rely on the
ability of the banking authorities to pre-commit to a speci c payment arrangement. In this paper,
we argue that to better understand many of the relevant situations, it is more appropriate to proceed
under the premise that pre-commitment is not possible and, hence, that interventions and actual
payments are decided as events unfold. In this case, many of the previously proposed schemes are
no longer feasible and self-ful lling runs become a real possibility.
The behavior of individuals during a banking crisis depends crucially on how they expect the
authorities to respond to events. If it were known that the authorities would respond to a run by
immediately freezing all remaining deposits then, in a wide range of model environments, selfful lling runs would not happen. However, this type of response is likely to be highly inef cient
ex post, in the event that a run actually occurs. Taking into account these ex post concerns can
dramatically change the analysis. We illustrated this fact by deriving the ex post ef cient policy
responses to a run in the classic framework of Diamond and Dybvig [10] and showing how these
interventions can actually generate the ex ante incentives that induce depositors to participate in a
run.
Banking crises are often associated with periods of signi cant political turmoil and weak institutions, which makes any sort of commitment by government agencies dif cult to achieve. Such
was certainly the case in Argentina, with the President of the country resigning in December 2001
and his successor resigning after only a week in of ce. Political stability was also present in the
U.S. during the banking crisis of 1932-33, when a change in administration made commitment
to a coherent policy very dif cult (see Friedman and Schwartz [18] pp. 327-331). In addition,
a suspension of payments from the banking system effectively requires commitment from multiple branches of government, which is especially dif cult to achieve. The executive branch in
21

See, for example, de Nicolò [9] and Green and Lin [22].

23

Argentina, for example, could not prevent the court system from allowing additional withdrawals
after the deposit freeze was declared.
These institutional features that undermine the ability of a government to pre-commit to a given
course of action correspond to precisely the type of problems we aim to draw attention to with our
analysis. We have shown that when depositors anticipate the government's ex post reaction, they
often have an ex ante incentive to run on the banking system if they expect others to do so as well.
Our general conclusion from this novel approach is that, to the extent that lack of commitment
is a realistic feature of economies in crisis, the possibility of self-ful lling runs cannot be safely
ignored from the standpoint of modern banking theory.

24

Appendix A. Proofs
Lemma 1: There exists a value
any

s

2[ ;

T

T

such that if deposits are frozen after

>

s

withdrawals for

); the banking system is not fragile.

Proof: De ne the function cL ( s ) as in (5). This function gives the payoff to a patient depositor
who waits until period 2 to withdraw when (i) all other patient depositors attempt to withdraw
in period 1 and (ii) the BA declares a deposit freeze after a proportion

s

of depositors have

withdrawn. Note that we have
cL ( ) =

cL
(1

It is straightforward to show that dcL ( s )=d
such that cL (
T

such that

U
s)
s

)

s

= 0; this value is given by

<

T

> cL > cE :

< 0 holds. In addition, there exists a value
U
s
s

>

<1

i =cE : Hence, there is a unique value

1

implies cL ( s ) > cE , while

U
s

T

implies cL ( s ) < cE : (See Figure 2.)

Therefore, waiting is a strictly dominant strategy for patient depositors if and only if

s

2[ ;

T

).

Proposition 2: The banking system is fragile under the (ex post) ef cient deposit freeze if and
only if (6) holds.
Proof: De ne
cL ( s )
:
cE

A ( s)

(11)

Using (1) and (5), this expression can be written as
A ( s) =

(1

)R
(1

1

( s
s ) (1

) 1R
)

(12)

:

Using (11), the BA's objective function (4) can be rewritten as
W ( s) =

(cE )1
1

s

+ (1

)A( s )1

s )(1

:

It is straightforward to show that W is strictly concave. Using (12), its derivative can be written
as

(cE )1
W ( s) =
1
0

1

(1

) A ( s )1

25

(1

)

R
1

A ( s)

:

(13)

The banking system is fragile under the (ex post) ef cient deposit freeze if and only if

M
s

holds, or (by the concavity of W ) if and only if we have
W0
Using (13) and the fact that A

T

1

T

0:

= 1 holds (see (11) and Figure 2), this condition becomes
(1

)

(1

)

Straightforward manipulations then yield condition (6).

26

R
1

0:

T

References
[1] Albanesi, Stefania, V.V. Chari, and Lawrence J. Christiano, “Expectation traps and monetary
policy,” Review of Economic Studies 70 (2003), 715-741.
[2] Allen, Franklin and Douglas Gale, “Optimal nancial crises,” Journal of Finance 53 (1998),
1245–1284.
[3] Bryant, John, “A model of reserves, bank runs, and deposit insurance,” Journal of Banking
and Finance 43 (1980), 749–761.
[4] Calomiris, Charles W. and Joseph R. Mason, “Contagion and bank failures during the great
depression: The June 1932 Chicago banking panic,” American Economic Review 87 (1997),
863-883.
[5] Calomiris, Charles W. and Joseph R. Mason, “Fundamentals, panics and bank distress during
the depression,” American Economic Review 93 (2003), 1615-1647.
[6] Carlsson, Hans and Eric van Damme, “Global Games and Equilibrium Selection,” Econometrica 61 (1993), 989-1018.
[7] Chari, V.V. and R. Jagannathan, “Banking Panics, Information, and Rational Expectations
Equilibrium,” Journal of Finance 43 (1988), 749-761.
[8] Cooper, Russell and Thomas W. Ross, “Bank runs: liquidity costs and investment distortions,”
Journal of Monetary Economics 41 (1998), 27-38.
[9] de Nicolò, Gianni, “Run-proof banking without suspension or deposit insurance,” Journal of
Monetary Economics 38 (1996), 377-390.
[10] Diamond, Douglas W. and Phillip H. Dybvig, “Bank runs, deposit insurance, and liquidity,”
Journal of Political Economy 91 (1983), 401-419.
[11] Diamond, Douglas W. and Raghuram G. Rajan, “Money in a theory of banking,” American
Economic Review 96 (2006), 30-53.
[12] Dominguez, Kathryn M. E. and Linda L. Tesar, “International borrowing and macroeconomic
performance in Argentina,” in Capital Controls and Capital Flows in Emerging Economies:
Policies, Practices, and Consequences, edited by Sebastian Edwards, University of Chicago
Press for the NBER, forthcoming (2006).
[13] Engineer, Merwan, “Bank runs and the suspension of deposit convertibility,” Journal of Monetary Economics 24 (1989), 443-454.
[14] Ennis, Huberto M., “Economic Fundamentals and Bank Runs,” Federal Reserve Bank of Richmond Economic Quarterly 89 (2003), 55-71.
[15] Ennis, Huberto M. and Todd Keister, “Government policy and the probability of coordination
failures,” European Economic Review 49 (2005), 939-973.
[16] Ennis, Huberto M. and Todd Keister, “Bank runs and investment decisions revisited,” Journal
of Monetary Economics 53 (2006), 217-232.

27

[17] Ennis, Huberto M. and Todd Keister, “Commitment and Equilibrium Bank Runs,” Federal
Reserve Bank of New York Staff Report No. 274 (2007).
[18] Friedman, Milton and Anna Jacobson Schwartz, A Monetary History of the United States,
1867-1960. Princeton University Press (1963).
[19] Glomm, Gerhard and B. Ravikumar, “Endogenous public policy and multiple equilibria,” European Journal of Political Economy 11 (1995), 653-662.
[20] Goldstein, Itay and Ady Pauzner, “Demand deposit contracts and the probability of bank runs,”
Journal of Finance 60 (2005) 1293-1327.
[21] Gorton, Gary, “Bank suspension of convertibility,” Journal of Monetary Economics 15 (1985),
177-193.
[22] Green, Edward J. and Ping Lin, “Implementing ef cient allocations in a model of nancial
intermediation,” Journal of Economic Theory 109 (2003), 1-23.
[23] Green, Edward J. and Ping Lin, “Diamond and Dybvig's classic theory of nancial intermediation: What's missing?” Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis Quarterly Review 24 (2000),
3-13.
[24] International Monetary Fund, “Sovereign Debt Restructurings and the Domestic Economy.
Experience in Four Recent Cases,” prepared by the Policy Development and Review Department, February 2002.
[25] King, Robert G., “Discretionary policy and multiple equilibria,” Federal Reserve Bank of
Richmond Economic Quarterly 92 (2006), 1-15.
[26] King, Robert G. and Alexander L. Wolman, “Monetary discretion, pricing complementarity,
and dynamic multiple equilibria,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 119 (2004), 1513-1553.
[27] Kydland, Finn E. and Edward C. Prescott, “Rules rather than discretion: the inconsistency of
optimal plans,” Journal of Political Economy 85 (1977), 473-492.
[28] Peck, James and Karl Shell, “Equilibrium bank runs,” Journal of Political Economy 111
(2003), 103-123.
[29] Saunders, A. and B. Wilson, “Contagious Bank Runs: Evidence from the 1929-1933 Period,”
Journal of Financial Intermediation 5 (1996), 409-423.
[30] Villamil, Anne, “Demand deposit contracts, suspension of convertibility, and optimal nancial
intermediation,” Economic Theory 1 (1991), 277-288.
[31] Wallace, Neil. “Another attempt to explain an illiquid banking system: the Diamond and Dybvig model with sequential service taken seriously,” Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis
Quarterly Review 12 (Fall 1988), 3-16.

28