View original document

The full text on this page is automatically extracted from the file linked above and may contain errors and inconsistencies.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

Workinn Paper 9217
COMMITMENT AS IRREVERSIBLE INVESTMENT
by Joseph G. Haubrich and Joseph A. Ritter

Joseph G. Haubrich is an economic advisor at the
Federal Reserve Bank of Cleveland, and Joseph A.
Ritter is an economist at the Federal Reserve Bank
of St. Louis. The authors wish to thank seminar
participants at North Carolina State University and
the Federal Reserve Bank of Atlanta for helpful
comments.
Working papers of the Federal Reserve Bank of
Cleveland are preliminary materials circulated to
stimulate discussion and critical comment. The
views stated herein are those of the authors and not
necessarily those of the Federal Reserve Bank of
Cleveland or of the Board of Governors of the
Federal Reserve System.

December 1992

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

Abstract

Considering time inconsistency as a problem of irreversible investment brings some
neglected points to the fore. Making a policy choice in real time and under current
conditions emphasizes the importance of the timing of commitment, the regret over past
decisions, and the option value of not committing. This paper applies these concepts to
monetary policy, banking regulation, and capital taxation.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

In recent years, there has been a drift in economists' way of thinking about policy
rules versus discretion. Beginning with Kydland and Prescott (1977), a theoretical
presumption has developed in favor of rules in certain contexts. From this point of view,
rules allow policymakers to achieve outcomes otherwise precluded by the strategic
behavior of the public. This theoretical emphasis contrasts with earlier arguments for rules
based on practical considerations. According to the early monetarists, simple monetary
rules were necessary precisely because the central bank was incapable of handling the
economy's complexities well enough to make discretionary policy desirab1e.l
One aspect of this shift that has been overlooked to a large extent is the change in
the nature of the rules under consideration. The pragmatic case for rules almost by
definition requires that they be simple and easily implemented. The theoretical case, based
on the time inconsistency of discretionary policies, presumes fully state-contingent rules.
Although sometimes simple (see Barro and Gordon [1983]), the optimal state-contingent
rules are generally rather complex.
Complex rules make commitment more difficult. Governments can make it costly
(to themselves) to change a rule, and this may overcome their incentive to retract it or to
change course in midstream. It is manifestly true, however, that governments'
commitment mechanisms (ranging from campaign promises to constitutions) cannot be
contingent on a l l possible states of the world. Policymakers must choose not between
discretion and optimal state-contingent rules, but between discretion and comparatively
simple and imperfect rules (as recently emphasized by Lohrnann [1992]). Thus, it is
logically possible for policymakers to "regret" their commitment to a rule.
In this paper, we reframe the rules-versus-discretionquestion along these lines and
explore the consequences of the change in perspective. We find that this modification
makes the rules-versus-discretiondecision similar to the choice to make an irreversible
investment (see Pindyck [1991]). Pursuing this analogy further raises the possibility that
the government might want to delay committing to a rule, with the outcome of the

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

decision dependent on the current state of the world. In this sense, it becomes important
that the decision be made in "real time." A broader implication, not recognized in
previous literature, is that choosing discretion today has an option value, since the
government may still choose rules in the future. If this option indeed has positive value -as such options often do -- it adds to the desirability of discretion.

Our exploration of regret and the associated option value of waiting distinguishes
this paper from similar efforts, such as Cukierman and Meltzer (1986) and Hood and Isard
(1988). Cukierman and Meltzer discuss flexibility, but do not consider imperfect fixed
rules and a fortiori miss the associated option value.
The remainder of this paper develops these themes, with several variations.
Section I1 presents an expository example couched in terms of the too-big-to-fail doctrine.
Section III presents a richer analysis in a framework of monetary policy based on Flood
and Isard. Section IV uses some detailed numerical examples to explore the significance
of the results, and section V applies these ideas to capital taxation. Section VI concludes.

11. A Preliminary Example: Too Big To Fail

In this section, we present a concrete example from the banking industry showing
the option value of waiting, the "bad news principle," and the necessity of regret. By
bringing banking into the analysis, we are able to link the discussion to policy and (we
hope) to shed some light on current disputes within the industry.

Our model has two periods, 1 and 2, with no discounting between them, and two
equally likely states of the world, good (G) and bad (B). After waking up on a particular
date and in one of these states, a bank regulator must decide what to do when banks fail.
He may choose to be weak (W) and bail them out, or he can be tough (T) and commit to
refusing them.
In the good state, we prefer to have a tough regulator who eliminates the costly
wealth transfers from the rest of society to bank investors. In the bad state, we prefer the

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

weak regulator. Think of the bad state as one with systemic risk (perhaps a recession)
where being tough leads to a financial panic. We can express this in payoffs, or utility
levels, for the regulator: In the good state, TG>WG; in the bad state, TB<WB. Figure 1
illustrates this game's structure.
Since we have suppressed any explicit choice by the banks, the above example is
formally identical to an irreversible investment problem. This highlights the connections
between the two cases, while the rules-versus-discretion language foreshadows the more
important, complicated models in sections III and IV.
Because the policy decision takes place in real time, we have two cases to
consider. Either the economy starts out in the good state, or it starts out in the bad state.
Suppose the economy starts out in the good state. If the regulator is weak, he gets a
payoff of WG today and chooses to be tough or weak again in period 2. If the regulator is
tough, he gets a payoff of TG today and remains tough in period 2. The payoffs then look
as follows:

Case I: Start in Good State
Strategy W: WG + 1/2(TG+WB)
T: TG + 1/2(TG+TB).

The regulator picks the strategy with the higher expected return,

W-T = WG-TG + 1/2(WB-TB).

In the standard time-consistency literature, failure to commit means that the

suboptimal, or "weak," choice is made in each period. In this simple example, we do not
model that choice, but the natural analogue is that W is chosen in each period. Making
such a decision forever seems simple-minded in this simple model, but it is precisely the

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

choice forced on regulators in most of the current time-consistency literature. The basic
game described here brings out rather sharply the problem of committing in real time.
If the regulator decides at the beginning to adopt either rules or discretion forever
(TF or WF), the new payoff for choosing WF is
WF = WG + 1/2(WG+WB).

Note that the payoff to choosing W today and retaining the option to choose T tomorrow
exceeds the payoff to choosing W in both periods. This is because W-WF=1/2(TG-WG),
and since TG>WG by assumption, W-WDO. Similar calculations hold in the bad state:

Case 11: Start in Bad State
Strategy W: W B + 1/2(TG+WB)
T: TB + 1/2(TG+TB)
WF: WB + 1/2(WG+WB)
W-WF= 1/2(TG-WG)>O.

Thus, the waiting option has value, something not accounted for by studies that ignore the
real-time aspect of choosing rules over discretion. A short numerical example shows that
this cost can be high enough to make discretion the optimal strategy. In the good state,
the comparison is between
W-T=WG-TG + 1/2(WB-TB)
and
WF-T=3/2(WG-TG) + 1/2(WB-TB).

Setting TG=6.2, WG=4.2, TB=O, and WB=4.2 yields WF-T= -0.9, which means that
adopting rules is the better choice. When option value is considered, however, we find
that W-T=O.1, making discretion preferable.2

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

When future prospects change, this example illustrates the bad news principle,
which we suspect lies behind the rhetorical tendency to accentuate the negative. To see
this, we first distinguish payoffs with period subscripts. Now, in the good state,

and thus

Holding the period 1 payoffs (the bracketed term) fmed, because we are already in
that period, consider changing the payoffs in period 2. An increase in TG2 or WG2 has no
effect. What matters is the "regret spread," or WB2-m2. If we end up in the bad state,
we'd like to choose W and get payoff WB2, but if we have already committed, we play T
and get TB2. If the good state ensues and we want to commit, we can. Shifts in WG2 and
TG2 do not matter when deciding between strategies.
The key here is that we sometjmes regret the commitment to be tough. We never
regret an initial decision to be weak, because if it pays to be strong later on, we can make
that choice. Increasing the payoff to toughness does not affect the relative payoffs -- and
thus the choice -- today. This illustrates the bad news principle: Only news about the bad
outcomes affects the value of the option to wait.
One could make a timeless comparison, contrasting expected values before even
the initial state of the world is realized, but the results would be irrelevant. Any current
choice must take place in real time, since the economy already exists.

III. Monetary Policy
Most of the debate about rules versus discretion has taken place in the arena of
monetary economics. The insights from thinking about policy commitment as irreversible

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

investment apply here as well. The central bank must make decisions in real time, and a
failure to commit today does not preclude commitment in the future. This section models
commitment as irreversible investment in a monetary policy context. Though slightly
specialized to highlight the main points, the model derives from a fairly general and
plausible framework based on Flood and Isard (1988).

A. Basic Specification

The growth of base money, b,, relative to a velocity shock, v, (ignored hereafter),
determines the inflation rate, n,:
(1)

nt = b, + vt.

Output depends on unexpected inflation, with the Federal Reserve focusing on the
deviation of output from a natural level. Because of distortions (for instance,
unemployment insurance or imperfectly clearing labor markets, depending on your
preferred ideology), that natural level may not be socially optimal.
Policymakers wish to minimize a social loss function that reflects both output
deviations and inflation:

The term bt-Et-lbtmeasures the unexpected base growth (or unexpected inflation), K
measures distortion, or the divergence between the natural level of output and the socially
optimal level, and u, measures the production shock. The term a measures the relative
weight given inflation, as opposed to output, deviations.
The first step in finding the optimal policy is to minimize the loss function, L,,
under both rules and discretion.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

B. Discretion
From the first-order conditions for equation (I), we find

This implies

Note, as in Barro and Gordon (1983), that the distortion term K determines the
inflationary bias of discretion. Actual base growth under discretion is

From this, we can calculate both the expected and realized social loss using equation (2).

(6)

Realized Loss: LtD = (l+a/a)[-K + (a/l+a)ut]2.

(7)

Expected Loss: Et-lLtD= (l+a/a)~2+ (a/l+a)

2

o,

.

The first term of equation (7) is the loss from the inflation bias of discretion, while the
second is the loss caused by output variance (assuming Eu, = 0), some of which shows up
in the inflation rate via monetary policy.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

C. Rules
If the money supply, b,, cannot respond to u,, money only causes inflation; it

cannot reduce output variance. In that case, the best rule sets b, = 0 in all periods. This is
the optimal rule without state contingency. If it were feasible, a better rule would let the
base react to productivity shocks, but would avoid the inflationary bias of pure discretion.
For the simple rule setting b, = 0 for all t, we can substitute into the loss function.

(8)

Realized Loss: LtR = (u,-K)~.

(9)

Expected Loss: Et-lLP = K2+o,.2

Equations (8) and (9) have a lower inflation bias than discretion, but a higher output
variance.
When is LD - LR < O? Straightforward substitution from equations (6) and (8)
shows that this is the case when

Notice that discretion is preferable in extreme times (that is, for large utts),when
the costs of shocks are especially high. As inflation costs (a) increase, discretion is
preferred in more and more states. This may seem counterintuitive, but it in fact makes
sense. Consider, for example, the case of u, = 0. For the simple rule setting b, = 0, the

(3-f.

loss due to inflation is 0. For discretion, the corresponding loss is a -

--

Asa

increases, this cost decreases. Because discretion weighs the inflationary costs of
intervention, higher inflation costs reduce the inflationary bias of discretion. In the limit,

with inflation infinitely costly, discretion involves zero inflation.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

Similarly, as K increases, discretion is preferable in more states. As distortion
worsens, there is a larger deviation of output from its natural level and thus more of an
advantage to reducing shocks.

If the government can commit to a state-contingent rule, it can replicate
discretion's offset to productivity shocks while simultaneously eliminating the inflationary
bias. When feasible, this rule would let the monetary base react to productivity shocks but
avoid the inflationary bias of pure discretion. In our simple model, it is possible to find
this optimal rule. Its form illustrates several points about the relationships among optimal
rules, simple rules, and discretion.
To find the optimal state-contingent rule, we minimize the expected loss function
from equation (2):

where gi denotes the probability of state i and bi denotes money growth in state i.3
aEL
The first-order conditions -= 0 imply
abi

Taking expected values, we get

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

i=1

This means that the optimal rule has no inflation bias. Setting Ebi equal to 0 in the firstorder conditions gives

which implies

(11)

Substituting into the loss function, we have
a
a
Ku + K'.
Realized Loss: Lt = -u2 - 2l+a
l+a

(13)

a
Expected Loss: E,-l L, = -o2+ K ~ .
l+a

To understand the implications of restricting rules to a subset of those that are fully
state contingent, it is important to look at several relationships. First, by construction, the
optimal rule dominates a restricted or simple rule in expected value. In the current
example, the optimal rule turns out to be linear. Our simple rule is by assumption the class
of linear rules that do not allow b, to respond to u,.
Second, the optimal rule can replicate the behavior of the policymaker under
discretion, so it must be at least as good as discretion in every state. Since the optimal

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

rule ties the policymaker's hands, it allows actions that would otherwise fall victim to time
inconsistency. This again makes the optimal rule better by construction.
Third, while the optimal rule dominates the simple rule on average, this is not true
in every state, as can be seen by comparing equations (12) and (8). In states where 0 < u,

< 2K, the response to u, is not worth the (small) amount of inflation that ensues.
However, a rule that attempts to exploit this inefficient response changes expectations in a
way that hurts more than it helps on average. Suppose, for example, that we attempt to
revise the optimal rule by setting b, = 0 whenever 0 < u, < 2K. This lowers expected
inflation and increases the loss in states where state contingency is useful. The gain in 0

< u, < 2K states is offset by the loss in other states, even though policy is unchanged in
the latter. The response of individual behavior, in this case expectations, distinguishes an
equilibrium problem from a simple control problem

D. Manv Periods

Adequately capturing irreversibility requires a number of adjustments to the model.
First, it clearly needs several periods. Second, to better focus on the problems of regret, it
is also helpful to revise the within-period time structure. In what follows, we let the
government observe the shock before the public does and before it chooses to commit.
The new time line, which leaves equations (1)-(12) intact, is as follows:

Gov't sees u, -+ Gov't decides whether to commit, announces -+ Economy revises
expectations Et-lbi, + Gov't chooses b, -+ Production; economy sees u,.

The contrived aspect here concerns observing the shock. After seeing today's
shock, the government chooses rules or discretion, but the public does not see u, until
much later. In general, this new timing sequence will change the public's behavior.
Seeing what action the government takes provides information about the unseen shock to

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

the economy. In our specific model, however, symmetry of the shocks means that the
public cannot extract useful information from the government's decision to commit or not.
People can infer the size, but not the sign, of the shock, so that

E(u, I gov't choice) = 0 and E(b, I gov't choice) = 0.

Some variant of this assumption appears in much of the literature. In Cukierman
and Meltzer (1986), for instance, the government has information on a state variable that
the public observes one period later. In Canzoneri (1985), the government observes
(perhaps noisily) a random disturbance that the public cannot.
Once the government chooses a simple rule, it must stick with that decision
forever, in effect setting b, = 0 permanently. By contrast, choosing discretion today does
not prevent choosing rules tomorrow.
We wish to illustrate two points regarding this framework. First, if the
government can use the optimal state-contingent rule, there is no value to waiting, and the
irreversibility makes no difference. Second, with a simple, non-state-contingentrule,
irreversibility introduces an option value whose worth is non-negative.
The first point is readily apparent. With the optimal state-contingent rule, no
regret occurs. In fact, the loss from discretion exceeds the loss from choosing the rule, so
it is never worthwhile to wait. The key here is the state contingency of the rule, which
allows enough flexibility to offset future shocks but eliminates the inflationary bias
inherent in pure discretion. Committing to a long-term rule still allows flexibility in dayto-day decisionmaking. If such a contingent rule is politically and administratively
feasible, no conflict arises between maintaining stable prices and responding to economic
shocks.
With a simple, non-state-contingent rule, regret can exist. For example, the
government might regret committing to zero inflation and wish for discretion. This point

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

does not depend merely on the rule's simplicity. The analysis holds even with a more
sophisticated, less than fully state-contingent rule, as long as there are some states in
which discretion is preferred.
The problem comes down to comparing possible courses of action. This is most
naturally done using dynamic programming (see Ross [1983]). For any policy (that is, for
any set of b, choices by the government, denoted n), we have a new value function
0

To rule out reputational equilibria, we restrict ourselves to nonrandomized policies and to
those that depend only on today's shock and whether or not the government has
committed in the past. The government begins this period by observing u,. If it chooses
to commit to zero inflation (the optimal simple rule), the loss is

where VR(u)denotes the value function for rules.
The first term measures today's loss, and the second gives the expected loss
tomorrow. Choosing discretion forever yields a loss of

The general case is more complicated because opting for discretion today leaves
the door open for choosing rules tomorrow. The loss to choosing discretion is

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

Two different representations of EDV(uSturn out to be useful. Without any
simplifying, we can express this term as

where Pjis the probability of state j and UR,,
government uses a rule. Here, UR,,

is the period t+s states in which the

depends on history; that is, commitment to a rule

implies commitment in all future states.
Simplifying this expression takes a little work. First, note that the set of states in
which the government chooses to commit, CR, does not vary with time. (This differs
from UR, in equation [17], where prior commitment does change the action. UR, answers
the question, "At time t, in which state does the government use rules?" CR, answers the
question, "At time t, given that it can still choose, in which states does the government
commit to rules?") The time invariance of CR follows from the simple form of equation
(16). Then, recursively using equation 14(b) yields

The first term is the expected loss if we enter a state in which we choose rules and
adhere to them forever. The second term represents the loss today from using discretion
today only. The third term gives the loss from choosing rules the period after discretion.
The fourth term gives the loss from choosing discretion again, with this pattern repeating
recursively.
Equation (18) simplifies to

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

Finding the value function puts us in a position to examine the central issues of regret,
option value, and delay. Of course, different parameters can make rules or discretion the
better choice, but of interest here is what is unique to our model. To this end, we focus
on parameter values for which an irrevocable choice between rules and discretion would
favor rules. We then show that the possibility of future commitment makes discretion
today preferable, noting the importance of regret in that decision. A big increase in the
attractiveness of discretion means that the government chooses discretion in more states, a
policy shift perhaps best interpreted as a delay in commitment.
To rule out the trivial cases, we need some "regret" so that simple rules do not
dominate discretion in every state of the world. If in every state the loss from rules is less
than the loss from discretion, then it makes no sense to delay commitment or to choose
discretion -- hence we rule out the optimal state-contingent policy. To have any regret, it

'

must be that for some (but not all) shocks u, (u - K ) >
~ - -K+ -u ) ' . ~ e a l s o
a
l+a
want rules to do better in expected value terms than discretion forever, or else discretion
l+a
forever is the obvious trivial choice. This requires K~ > (I: < - +LO:),
or
a
l+a

The problem for the government at t = 0 is to decide between

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

(2 1) Rules:

VR(u, ) = (u, - K ) +~

1-P

(K2 + 0:)

and

(22) Discretion: VD(u, ) =

"(a

2

-K

1
+uo) + PEV(u1),
l+a

where EVR(u1)is equation (17) or, equivalently, (19). It is also important to know how
VD (u,) and VR(u0)compare with discretion forever, VDF(u0)(given in equation [15]).

Comparing VR(u) with VD(u) and VDF(u)shows the option value of discretion. Consider
moving from (21) to a version of (19) in which the choice to commit is based solely on
what's best this period (equation [6] versus [8]). This may not be the optimal policy, but it
is certainly feasible. Such a policy differs from (21), but at each point of difference (statetime pair), the policy leading to (17) results in the smaller loss. This happens because a
discretion term enters (17) only if it is lower than the corresponding rules term. A similar
comparison with (15b) emphasizes the same point from a different perspective. Compared
with discretion forever, (19) and (22) allow rules when rules are better. This is why we
canhave

E V ~ ( ~ ~ ) < ~ ( K ~ + O : ) = E V ~ ( U , ) , ~ V ~ ~ ~ ~

1-P
EVDF> EVR; that is, when

l+a

1
Note that since EVD(u,) < -EVR
1-P

1-P

(u), the government may sometimes choose

discretion even in states where the one-period return favors rules. This conceivably could
create a paradox; that is, even though we prefer pure rules to pure discretion, we delay
choosing rules forever. Actually, this never occurs, as demonstrated by equation (19).
Suppose the government never commits, so that CR = 0. Then (19) reduces to
l+a

= VDF(ut ) ,the discretion-forever case. We assume, however,

that discretion forever is worse than rules.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

Along with eliminating such an "infinity paradox," the above calculation has
another implication. The government commits with a fixed positive probability in each
period, so with probability 1, the government eventually commits (by the Borel-Cantelli
lemma).4

IV. Numerical Examples

To further illustrate our points, this section presents two numerical examples. The
two-period case clarifies the notions of regret, delay, and option value, while the infinitehorizon example explores the quantitative importance of our results. While it cannot be
called a test, nor even a calibration exercise, our approach strives to use plausible values
for the effect of unanticipated money and the distribution of unemployment shocks. In this
scenario, the government chooses discretion in about half the states.

A. Two-Period Exam~le
This example also simplifies the productivity shock, assuming u, is i.i.d. and equals
{-x,O,+x). The probability takes a correspondingly simple form:
Prob(u, = +x) = gl
Prob(u, = 0) = g2
Prob(u, = -x) = g3.
Figure 2 illustrates the sequential probability structure.
Now, Alan Greenspan wakes up and finds that today, ul = 0. If he says, "I
commit," then the two-period social loss function is

The first term, K2, measures the loss today, while the following three terms measure the
next period's expected loss.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

If the Chairman and the government choose discretion today, the loss is

Again, the first term is the loss today. The last term, g2K2,is what happens if the
government commits to rules tomorrow, when u = 0. If the government chooses
discretion, that term would be g2K2(l+a/a). The difference represents the option value of
waiting.
Deciding whether to choose rules or discretion comes down to comparing
equation (24) with (25) and then choosing the strategy with the smaller expected loss.

Removing the option value, that is, forcing the government to make an irrevocable choice
between rules and discretion, leads to a different expression:

Conceivably, VR(o) - VD(o) > 0 and VR(0) - VDF(0)< 0, meaning that correctly
valuing the option translates into choosing discretion, while ignoring it means choosing
rules. That is, taking account of the real time aspect of decisionmaking and properly
valuing the waiting option can reverse the policy decision. As an example, let
a = 1,
x2 = 6K2,and
gl = g3 = 114.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

Then VR (0) - VDF(0)= -K2

1
+(3K2 - K2) = 0, and
2

This example shows that the option to wait can reverse the normal presumption of the
superiority of rules and that the option value may be sizable. Using equation (24), the loss
from adopting rules is 5K2, making the option difference 1/4K2, or 5 percent of the total
value.

B. Infinite-Horizon Example
To add a small degree of realism, the next example employs the infinite-horizon
model, using parameter values we believe to be plausible.
Monthly unemployment rates from January 1948 to August 1992 range from 2.5
percent to 10.8 percent, with a mean of 5.7 and a median of 5.6. Split into thirds, the
mean of each third is 7.5,5.6, and 3.9 percent. To approximate the distribution, we take
the long-run average rate of unemployment to be 5.5 percent and assume a uniform
distribution of shocks every tenth of a point between -2.0 and 2.0 percent. This gives a
variance of 1.4 for unemployment shocks, somewhat below the actual value of 2.7. We
choose a K value of 1.1, indicating that the long-run rate of unemployment differs from
the socially optimal rate by 1.1 percentage points.
Following Barro (1987, p. 469), we assume that a 1percent rise in money above
expectations lowers unemployment by 0.6 percentage point. This makes the social loss
function L, = [a(b,-Et-,bt) - K + uJ2 + ab2,. Consequently, discretionary policy becomes

Adapting the work of section III to these differences allows us to make the computations.
Two more parameter choices will fully spec@ the problem. Give inflation and
unemployment equal values in the social loss function and set a equal to one. Next, set P,

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

the discount factor, to 0.995. Compounded monthly, this yields an annual discount rate of
6 percent. Alternatively, if the decision period is seen as corresponding to the eight yearly
meetings of the Federal Open Market Committee (FOMC), we get an annual discount rate
of 4 percent.
Figure 3 shows the results of this example using these parameters. The top panel
plots the difference between VR(u) and VD(u), or between the value of committing to
rules and adopting discretion in a given state. Since we use.a loss function, a positive
value means discretion is better, and a negative value means rules are better.
Notice that for a u shock between -0.9 and +0.9 (that is, for unemployment rates
between 4.6 and 6.4 percent), the social loss from discretion exceeds that from rules;
consequently, the monetary authority should commit to rules. For larger shocks, the
monetary authority should choose discretion. In 22 of the 4.1 possible states, discretion is
preferable to rules.
The bottom panel shows the importance of considering option value. If we
compare using rules forever with using discretion forever, we would choose rules in every
state. The possibility of future commitment and its associated option value changes
discretion from a poor policy to one preferred in a majority of states.
Unemployment undoubtedly has more serial correlation than the i.i.d. structure of
this model and example. Still, it is interesting to consider the "delay probability," or the
expected time until a commitment is made. For example, if we interpret each decision
time as an FOMC meeting date, the probability that the Fed will go a year without
committing to rules is (22/41)8 = 0.007. The independent nature of the shocks means that
even though commitment is chosen in fewer than half the states, the probability of ending
up in those states at least once increases rapidly. In other words, once we hit the
"absorbing barrier," we stay there.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

V. Capital Taxation and Other Extensions

In some cases, there is no option value to waiting. The standard capital taxation
model is one example of this. The basic difficulty is that once capital is in place, the
government has an incentive to tax it at 100 percent, so no one invests. Issues of
irreversibility may arise in more complex variants of the model, however. Assume that the
government is constrained by an upper limit on its capital taxation rate. Perhaps the limit
is fixed, or perhaps it is bounded by the labor tax rate. In any event, with discretion,
capital is always taxed at that upper bound. Separate from the bound, the government
may want to commit to a lower capital tax rate, perhaps reducing it directly, perhaps
offering tax credits or accelerated depreciation. Commitment in this case offers benefits -lower taxes and higher investment -- but it now also has a cost -- higher labor taxes in a
national emergency.
In principle, the notion of commitment as irreversible investment can be applied to
other areas, such as tariff agreements, deficit reduction, or tort reform. In this sense, our
work complements recent studies focusing on the political economy problems behind the
resistance to reforms (Fernandez and Rodrick [1991]), as well as on the delay in their
implementation (Alesina and Drazen [1991]). Our approach emphasizes delay and
resistance as an optimal response to an uncertain future.

VI. Conclusion
The decision regarding rules versus discretion takes place in real time, not at some
mythical starting date. That means opting for discretion today leaves open the possibility
of adopting rules later on, making discretion look like the better choice. The option
nature of this course of action also explains the tendency to accentuate the negative in
arguing against rules. There is an economic rationale behind the rhetoric, and a concern
with the rhetoric provides a springboard for the economics. But while the option-value
results may explain the delay and refusal to adopt simple monetary targets or tax reforms

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

during recessions or wars, they do not justify permanently abandoning such rules.
Eventually, when the time is right, the government should commit.

Our findings are by no means the last word on the rules-versus-discretion debate.
But we hope that by clarifying some neglected issues -- regret, future commitment, and
the bad news principle -- they will contribute to clearer insight and a more focused
dialogue.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

FOOTNOTES

1. This argument for simple rules represent. just one part of the monetarist critique of
activist policies.

2. In the bad state, both today's payoff and the waiting option work in the direction of
allowing discretion today. Though for some values being tough may still be
preferable, when p=1/2, the option value cannot reverse the optimal policy choice.
Reversal in the good state requires two relations to hold: WF-TcO and W-T>O. For
WF4' (making an irreversible choice), being tough is better than being weak. This
corresponds to the standard rules-versus-discretion dilemma of committing to a rule or
forever facing discretion. Here, adopting the rule is better. For W>T (correctly
considering the option value), discretion today looks better. Both conditions together
imply
1/2(WB-TB) > TG-WG > 1/3(WB-TB).
For the bad state, the first condition for reversal, WF-TcO, now implies that
TG-WG > 3(WB-TB),
which violates the conditions for reversal in the good state.

3. Nothing essential depends on using a discrete probability distribution. A continuous
distribution would lead to identical results, but would necessitate needlessly
cumbersome notation.
4. For a very different view of commitment problems using similar stochastic
commitment techniques, see Roberds (1987).

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

REFERENCES
Alesina, Alberto, and Allan Drazen. "Why Are Stabilizations Delayed?"
American Economic Review, vol. 81, no. 5 (December 1991), pp. 1170-88.
Auernheimer, L. "The Honest Government's Guide to the Revenue from the Creation of
Money," Journal of Political Economy, vol. 82 (1974), pp. 598-606.
Bmo, Robert J., and David Gordon. "A Positive Theory of Monetary Policy in a Natural
Rate Model," Journal of Political Economy, vol. 81 (1983), pp. 589-610.
Bmo, Robert J. Macroeconomics, 2d ed. Toronto: John Wiley & Sons, 1987.
Canzoneri, Matthew B. "Monetary Policy Games and the Role of Private Information,''
American Economic Review, vol. 75, no. 5 (December 1985), pp. 1056-70.
Cukierman, Alex, and Allan H. Meltzer. "A Positive Theory of Discretionary Policy, the
Cost of Democratic Government, and the Benefits of a Constitution," Economic Inquiry,
vol. 24 (1986), pp. 367-88.
Fernandez, Raquel, and Dani Rodrick. "Resistance to Reform: Status Quo Bias in the
Presence of Individual-specific Uncertainty," American Economic Review, vol. 8 1, no. 5
(December 1991), pp. 1146-55.
Fischer, Stanley. "Dynamic Inconsistency, Cooperation, and the Benevolent Dissembling
Government," Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control, vol. 2 (1980), pp. 93- 107.
Flood, Robert, and Peter Isard. "Monetary Policy Strategies," National Bureau of
Economic Research, Working Paper No. 2770,1988.
Friedman, Milton. "The Role of Monetary Policy," American Economic Review, vol. 58
(1968), pp. 1-17.
Kydland, Finn, and Edward Prescott. "Rules Rather Than Discretion: The Inconsistency
of Optimal Plans," Journal of Political Economy, vol. 85 (1977), pp. 473-91.
Lohmann, Susanne. "Optimal Commitment in Monetary Policy: Credibility versus
Flexibility," American Economic Review, vol. 82, no. 1 (March 1992), pp. 273-86.
Modigliani, Franco. "The Monetarist Controversy, or, Should We Forsake Stabilization
Policies?" American Economic Review, vol. 67 (1977), pp. 1-19.
Pindyck, Robert S. "Irreversibility, Uncertainty, and Investment," Journal of Economic
Literature, vol. 29 (1991), pp. 1110-48.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

Prescott, Edward C. "Should Control Theory Be Used for Economic Stabilization?"in
Karl Brunner and Allan H. Meltzer, eds., Optimal Policies, Control Theory, and
Technology Exports. New York: North-Holland, 1977, pp. 13-38.
Ritter, Joseph A., and Joseph G. Haubrich. "Notes on Does Capital Taxation Discourage
Investment? Insights from a General Model," unpublished manuscript, 1992.
Roberds, William. "Models of Policy under Stochastic Replanning," International
Economic Review, vol. 28, no. 3 (October 1987), pp. 731-55.
Ross, Sheldon M. Introduction to Stochastic Dynamic Programming. New York:
Academic Press, 1983.
Schelling, Thomas C. "An Essay on Bargaining," American Economic Revieiv, vol. 46
(1956), pp. 281-306. Reprinted in The Strategy of Conflict. New York: Oxford
University Press, 1962.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

Figure 1: Too-Big-to-Fail Decision Tree

Source: Authors.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

Figure 2: Two-Period Probability Structure

Source: Authors.

Figure 3: Value of Policies
clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

VR-VD

-1

0

1

commit states

VR-VDF

-1

0

commit states
Source: Authors.

1