View original document

The full text on this page is automatically extracted from the file linked above and may contain errors and inconsistencies.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

Working Paver 9415

BANKRUPTCY RULES AND DEBT CONTRACTING:
ON THE RELATIVE EFFICIENCY OF ABSOLUTE
PRIORITY, PROPORTIONATE PRIORITY, AND
FIRST-COME, FIRST-SERVED RULES
by Stanley D. Longhofer

Stanley D. Longhofer is an economist at the Federal Reserve
Bank of Cleveland. The author is grateful to Charles Kahn
for his encouragement and advice, to Richard Arnott, Charles
Calorniris, Stefan Krasa, Da-Hsiang Donald Lien, Robert
McDonald, George Pennacchi, Anne Villamil, and Andrew
Winton for useful comments and suggestions, and to Hai-Ling
Huai for helpful research assistance. He would also like to
thank participants at the 1992 Southeast Economic Theory
and Trade Meetings and those attending workshops at the
University of Illinois, Strathclyde University, the Federal
Reserve Bank of Cleveland, the University of Kansas, and
Northwestern University. Part of this research was supported
by a fellowship from the Irwin Family Foundation.
Working Papers of the Federal Reserve Bank of Cleveland are
preliminary materials circulated to stimulate discussion and critical
comment. The views stated herein are those of the author and not
necessarily those of the Federal Reserve Bank of Cleveland or of
the Board of Governors of the Federal Reserve System.

November 1994

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

ABSTRACT
Typical corporate finance folklore tells us that existing proportionate priority and absolute
priority rules in bankruptcy have evolved in order to eliminate inefficiencies that result
when lenders rush to retrieve their assets from a fm in financial distress. This paper
shows that when a fm is faced with a moral hazard problem, first-come, first served rules
reduce lenders' incentives to free ride on the monitoring efforts of each other. As a result,
these rules may reduce the total social cost of loan contracts compared to other
bankruptcy rules. The bankruptcy rules described here mimic important contractual
arrangements found in real-world debt contracts.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

Standard arguments in corporate finance tell us that existing bankruptcy rules have evolved to
eliminate inefficiencies that result when lenders rush to retrieve their assets from a firm under financial
distress. Thus, both Chapter 7 and Chapter 11 bankruptcy proceedings ostensibly maintain absolute
priority among creditor groups and provide for assets to be divided proportionately among creditors of
equal priority. This rationale, however, may not always be valid. Moral hazard problems relating to the
choice of project may make the act of "running" on a firm desirable, since it can help align investment
incentives.
This paper looks at the problem of an entrepreneur who must raise outside funds to finance one
of two investment alternatives. One of these projects is risky, so that any interest rate which ensures
lenders their reservation return causes the entrepreneur to earn negative profits. Nevertheless, the firm is
unable to commit to the less risky project, so neither can be undertaken.
First-come, first-served (FCFS) rules, often considered a benchmark in the absence of other
bankruptcy rules, serve to diminish this moral hazard problem. We derive a mixed-strategy equilibrium
in which lenders monitor the firm with some positive probability. When the firm is caught investing in
the risky project, it is liquidated; otherwise, it is allowed to continue. Although an equilibrium may exist
under both FCFS rules and proportionate priority rules (PPRs), we demonstrate that it is less likely to exist
under PPRs, and that when it does, the FCFS equilibrium is Pareto superior. Furthermore, FCFS rules
continue to dominate even when lenders are able to appoint a delegated monitor and provide that monitor
with absolute seniority (absolute priority rules, or APRs).
The fact that lenders can run on the firm when they observe that it has chosen the risky project
helps keep the firm honest. The FCFS aspect of asset distribution keeps lenders from wanting to free ride
on the monitoring efforts of others - those lenders who monitor are first in line to receive their claim
on the firm's assets and are thus likely to be paid in full. Lenders who wait to observe the monitoring
of others are less likely to receive anything if the firm goes under. This process is much like that

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

described in the banking papers of Calomiris and Kahn (1991) and Calomiris, Kahn, and Krasa (1991),
where demandable debt is used to control the banker's moral hazard problem, while sequential service
prevents depositors from free riding on the monitoring efforts of others.
The bankruptcy rules we describe mimic many important contractual arrangements found in realworld debt contracts. A trade creditor might refuse to ship new supplies to a firm when its prospects look
bad, effectively refusing to renew its loan. Alternatively, a factoring company might decide to no longer
guarantee payments for new accounts receivable generated with that firm. Also, a bank has the right to
seize a borrower's assets under the bank's control when it discovers that the borrower is in default. In
each case, the action taken by one creditor sends a signal to the rest of the market as to the
creditworthiness of the borrower, thereby forcing a poor borrower into bankruptcy. As such, the act of
monitoring acquires a public-good aspect. Like all public goods, too little monitoring will occur unless
the provider can capture and exclude others from its benefits. FCFS rules, and other contracts containing
their features, serve to compensate monitors for their actions.
Chapter 11 bankruptcy proceedings are often criticized by both legal and economic scholars for
the violation of absolute priority that often results.' Our findings suggest that such violations may in fact
increase social welfare. By refusing to reward senior lenders who fail to monitor the debtor, Chapter 11

strengthens the monitoring incentive: Lenders who wish to obtain the full value of their claims in default
must obtain their assets before a bankruptcy petition is filed.'
The key idea here is that bankruptcy institutions should reward monitors when and only when they

' See, for example, Jackson (1986), Jensen (1991), and Gemer and Scharfstein (1991).
Several recent papers emphasize a similar point - that absolute priority violations may be welfare improving.
Harris and Raviv (1993) show that a banlcruptcy court that mandates violations of absolute priority in some states
of the world can be part of an optimal financial contract. Eberhart and Senbet (1993) argue that APR violations
ameliorate the asset substitution problem when fums are financially distressed, precisely when other incentive control
mechanisms like convertible bonds are ineffective. Eberhart, Moore, and Roenfeldt (1990) provide evidence that
APR violations are anticipated ex ante.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

have performed their duties. A similar argument has been made by Rajan and Winton (1994), who
analyze how the choice of different priority and term structures in loan contracts affects the incentives of
lenders to monitor the firm. They argue that informational conditions determine which structures provide
the best monitoring incentives, meaning that the firm's capital structure can be used to achieve outcomes
that are not directly contractible. In other words, ex ante efficiency is improved by choosing a capital
structure that properly rewards monitors.
In addition, our model implies that the preference section of the bankruptcy code should be used
with extreme discretion. Preference law, as it relates our problem, is designed to prevent claimants from
opting out of the collective proceeding by nullifying payments made to some creditors immediately prior
to the bankruptcy filing.3 Our results suggest that such actions by a bankruptcy judge would in fact
reduce the incentive to monitor, lowering social welfare.
The next section summarizes traditional bankruptcy analyses. Here we outline some of the
standard arguments that an alternative to FCFS rules in bankruptcy law is needed, and question whether
these arguments are valid in all circumstances. We then use this background to analyze other studies of
bankruptcy. In section 11, we introduce our model and show that under certain conditions, a firm may be
unable to obtain financing because it cannot commit ex ante to a low-risk project; possible solutions to
this problem are analyzed. In particular, we show that a mixed-strategy equilibrium exists in which the
firm is able to find lenders. Section I11 looks at the effect different bankruptcy rules may have on the
equilibrium of this game. We show that PPRs reduce the incentive of lenders to monitor the firm, thus
raising the social cost of these contracts. Section IV extends the model to allow lenders to designate a
monitor. As before, PPRs undercompensate the designated monitor (called a bank) for its services, leading
to a less efficient outcome than do FCFS rules. We then show that strict seniority for the designated
monitor is also Pareto inferior, since it overcompensates the monitor. We conclude in section V by

See Jackson (1986), chapter 6.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

examining features of standard loan contracts that look much like the FCFS rules of our model. We also
examine two recent examples of these rules in action. Finally, we discuss the theoretical and policy
implications of our model and propose some possible extensions to our results. Several of the proofs are
relegated to the appendix.

Section I - Justifications for PPRs
Most discussions of bankruptcy institutions start with the assumption that a formal procedure for
distributing the assets of an insolvent firm is needed, and then focus on the specific form such a procedure
should take. But it is not clear that this assumption is valid in all cases. To see this, consider some of
its standard justifications.
In the absence of bankruptcy laws, assets are distributed to creditors in the order in which they
have staked their claims. Thus, the first lender to request repayment is, generally, the first to receive
payment. Lenders who end up last in line are paid last and quite possibly receive nothing. For this
reason, these default bankruptcy proceedings are typically called FCFS rules.
Traditional rationales for a more orderly mechanism cite several potential problems with FCFS
rules. First, lenders may wish to protect their position by expending excessive resources monitoring the
firm's condition. If a lender does not do this, the argument goes, he will certainly be the last to know
when the firm is about to default, and thereby be last in line to collect his claim. Furthermore, since all
lenders are engaged in this monitoring, no one will get a more preferable place in line than he would if
none of them monitored, so these resources are spent in vain. This game looks much like the classic
prisoners' dilemma, in which the Pareto superior outcome with no monitoring is not a Nash equilibrium.
It is argued that an orderly bankruptcy procedure allows lenders to avoid these costs, making all of them
better off.
A second argument against FCFS rules is the classic "common pool" problem. Here it is claimed

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

that in their rush to be paid, lenders might reduce the total liquidation value of the firm by separating
assets that would be more valuable together. An orderly liquidation, on the other hand, would ensure that
the firm's assets are put to their most productive uses, maximizing their value to the creditors. Worse yet,
lenders might actually run too soon and foreclose on illiquid but otherwise viable firms. Here again,
formal bankruptcy rules should help prevent these inefficient liquidations.
Jackson (1986), p. 10, summarizes the intuition behind these arguments: "The basic problem that
bankruptcy law is designed to handle ... is that the system of individual creditor remedies may be bad for
the creditors as a group when there are not enough assets to go around."
With these (often implicit) assumptions, modem examinations of bankruptcy rules investigate what
form formal liquidation rules should take. For example, many authors have looked at the relative
efficiency of APRs (where the order of repayment is determined ex ante by assigning each lender a
priority level) and PPRS.~Under various assumptions, they all conclude that these rules are inefficient
in regard to both the liquidation/continuation decision and the decision to make new investments.
Numerous other studies look directly at the Chapter 11 Bankruptcy Code and show that, in general, it does
not provide efficient investment or liquidation incentives
But none of these studies examines the relative efficiency of various bankruptcy rules compared
to the natural default - FCFS rules. We believe that a formal examination of the efficiency of FCFS
rules is a necessary starting place for analyses of bankruptcy.
In addition, most models analyze the effects of bankruptcy ex post. They begin with a firm having
some existing capital structure that is unable to meet its current debt obligations. The focus is on whether

See, for example, Bulow and Shoven (1978), White (1980, 1983), and Gertner and Scharfstein (1991).
Detragiache (1991) and Gertner and Scharfstein (1991) are two among many examples.
For further information on bankruptcy and financial distress and their impact on incentives, see Aghion and
Bolton (1992), Berkovitch and Israel (1991), Berkovitch and Kim (1990), Berlin and Mester (1992), Hart and Moore
(1989), Jensen and Meckling (1976), and Myers (1977).

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

or not different bankruptcy rules provide proper incentives so that creditors will foreclose if and only if
the firm is insolvent, and will extend new credit to the firm for and only for positive net present value
projects. Whether bankruptcy rules provide for decisions that are efficient ex post is certainly an
interesting question. But debt contracts are designed to resolve ex ante uncertainty, and their efficiency
must therefore be measured from the viewpoint of the initial contracting problem. Indeed, most of the
literature on asymmetric information accepts ex post inefficiency in some states of the world in order to
achieve an outcome that is ex ante Pareto optimal. The proper question, then, is how different bankruptcy
rules affect the social cost of debt contracts at the time in which they are written.
Boyes, Faith, and Wrase (1991) is one of few papers to address both of these issues. They
compare the ex ante social cost of debt contracts under PPRs and FCFS rules and conclude that the PPRs
found in Chapter 7 are more efficient than FCFS rules, since they reduce the cost of contracting. Their
result depends upon the assumption that rushing to liquidate the firm is costly, whereas formal bankruptcy
proceedings are not. In a FCFS world, lenders must pay to enter a queue to obtain the firm's assets. If
they allow a firm to continue despite the fact that its expected return is negative, they will avoid these
queuing costs some of the time (when the firm does well). Thus, lenders have an incentive to allow some
firms with negative net present value to continue?
Their model differs from ours in several important respects. First, they assume that FCFS rules
are more costly to implement than are PPRs. As a result, this model simply shows that the more costly
course of action is the less efficient one.' More important, in our model the firm chooses between two
different investment projects. This choice is the private information of the firm, creating a moral hazard

They also acknowledge that FCFS rules may result in inefficient liquidations of f m s that have a positive net
present value, and claim that this gives further support to their argument that PPRs are more efficient. They ignore,
however, the possibility that these two effects may offset each other, reducing the net inefficiency of FCFS rules.
If they were to assume that both types of rules entailed the same costs, their model would indicate that FCFS
rules are preferred, since they involve these costs only a fraction of the time, whereas PPRs always do.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

problem which requires lenders to monitor it. When there are many lenders, they may wish to free ride
on the monitoring efforts of each other. We propose that FCFS rules can serve to ameliorate this problem.
Some of our conclusions resemble those of Diamond (1992), who finds that when a firm cannot
negotiate with its long-term (public) lenders, short-term (bank) lenders should be made junior, to reduce
their incentive to liquidate the firm early.9 His model differs from ours, however, in several important
respects. His is an adverse selection model, and the monitoring that occurs in the interim phase is
costless. In addition, it is a noisy signal of the firm's true type. More important, efficiency in his model
depends upon the proper continuation/liquidation decision in the interim period. In other words, he looks
at ex post rather than ex ante efficiency.

Section I1 - The Model
Consider a three-period model with a risk-neutral firm. In the first period, the firm has the
opportunity to invest in only one of two projects, each of which has a random return in period three.''
Denote these projects G and B to coincide with their respective distribution functions." Assume that
both projects have the same mean, but that project G is second-order stochastic dominant over B, i.e, that

See also Diamond (1990a, 1990b, 1991).
'O

Alternatively, we could assume that the owner of the fm must choose one of two levels of effort.

I' Unless otherwise stated, we will assume in what follows that both distributions have the same support, [ x , F].
This assumption is for notational simplicity and is not necessary, since we assume that project revenues cannot be
observed by lenders outside of default. If they could be observed and the projects had different supports, then it
would be possible to ensure efficient investment by writing contracts that impose large penalties on the fm when
outcomes that could not have resulted from the designated project are observed.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

with strict inequality for a set of values of x with positive probability.''

Thys, B is more risky than G

in the sense of Rothschild-Stiglitz (1970).13 Furthermore, the choice of project and the resulting revenue
in period three are costlessly observable only by the firm. Outsiders may discover the choice of project
in period two only by paying a cost, c. The results of this monitoring provide a perfect signal of the
firm's choice of project.
Both projects require L dollars to undertake. Because the firm has no resources of its own, it must
raise external financing. Equity is out of the question, since the revenue from these projects cannot be
publicly ~bserved.'~.'~
Consequently, the firm must borrow this initial investment. We will assume that
the loan market is composed of a large number of identical risk-neutral agents, each with an endowment
of Lln. This endowment may be either loaned to the firm or invested in a riskless technology with a
return of 1. In equilibrium, competition will always drive down the interest rate to ensure that all lenders

l 2 The fact that the two projects have equal means implies that, in the absence of transaction costs, both projects
would be useful. However, our informational asymmetry makes project B less socially desirable, since it has higher
expected banlauptcy costs.
This condition is not necessary for the conclusions that follow, but it simplifies the proof of Proposition 2.
This proposition will still hold if project G has a higher mean than does project B, provided that the spread is not
too large. Thus, all our results would still hold even if project B were a negative net present value project.

l3

For a good introduction to the Rothschild-Stiglitz definition of increasing risk, see Laffont (1989).

l4 Here we are appealing to the classic costly state verification model of Townsend (1979). More recently, Gale
and Hellwig (1985), Boyd and Smith (1993a), Dionne and Viala (1992), Krasa and Villamil (1994), and Winton
(1992) have demonstrated the general robustness of this result. Of particular interest are Boyd and Smith and Dionne
and Viala, both of whose models are similar to our own. Boyd and Smith complicate the costly state verification
story by introducing adverse selection (in order to study credit rationing), whereas we focus on a m o d hazard
problem. Dionne and Viala use costly effort (as opposed to second-order stochastic dominance) to introduce the
moral hazard problem.
Note that the monitoring we discuss below is distinct from the state verification of these models. In our
context, monitoring is an action that takes place before the outcome of the project is determined; state verification
occurs after the project's return is realized.
l 5 Recent extensions to the costly state verification literature indicate that stochastic verification may dominate
the deterministic verification assumed here. Since the declaration of bankruptcy seems to occur deterministically
in real life, we are not too uncomfortable ruling out randomization at this stage of the game. In addition, we are
comforted by the results of Boyd and Smith (1993b), who conclude that the relative size of any welfare loss from
this resmction is small and that incentive problems associated with randomization schemes may very well make them
suboptimal.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

make zero profits. Figure 1 shows the order of events in this economy.

1

Period 1
Loans Made
Project Selected

I

Period 2
Short-Term Debt Due
Monitoring Occurs

I

Period 3

1

Long-Term Debt Due
Project Matures

Figure 1 - Sequence of Events

Long-Term Debt
To finance either of these "long-term" projects, the firm could issue long-term debt -that is, debt
that comes due in period three. If the firm commits to invest in a particular project, any prospective
lender will demand a default premium commensurate with that project's anticipated risk. Let x be the
project's realized value. If r is the promised interest rate, then the firm must default if x < rL. The
liquidation proceedings that follow default, or state verification, cost d(rL -x), where d is some positive
constant. Thus, the dead-weight cost of default depends upon its magnitude and is equal to zero when
the firm can just pay its debts.16
If the firm chooses to invest in project G, each lender's expected return is

Setting this expression equal to zero gives us an equation which implicitly determines the zero-profit
interest rate for this project, r,.

On the other hand, if the firm chooses project B, each lender's expected

l6 More generally, we could assume that d ( . ) is some arbitrary function of the size of default r L - x . In this
case, the restriction in Proposition 1 would be that d l ( . ) be sufficiently small - i.e., that the cost of default not
rise too steeply as its magnitude increases. All of our results would follow using this generalization.
We will also assume that d(rL -9 Ix so we can ignore outcomes where the project's returns are
insufficient to pay the default costs. This does not affect our results and simplifies the analysis. Alternatively, we
could assume that when default occurs, the lender must pay these costs even if they exceed the revenue from the
project.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

return is

which implies a zero-profit interest rate r, .I7 It is straightforward to show:

PROPOSITION
1: Ifproject B is more risky than project G (in the sense of Rothschild-Stiglitz), and if d
is suficiently small, then r, > r,.

Proof: See appendix.

One might be surprised that this proposition depends upon d being small - we would expect that
an increase in the interest rate should unambiguously raise the lender's expected return. However, this
increase might cause the borrower to default more often, thereby decreasing the lender's return. Stiglitz
and Weiss (1981) show that this effect can lead to credit rationing.''

Our restriction on d is a mild

technical assumption to ensure that this problem will not arise.
The firm's expected profit from projects G and B is

and

An example may make the results that follow more clear. Suppose that the support of G and B is { 1,2,3 ] ,
with g(1) = g(3) = .0001, g(2) = .9998, b(1) = b(3) = .4999, and b(2) = .0002. Clearly, these two distributions
have the same mean, and B is more risky in the sense of Rothschild-Stiglitz. Let c = .001, d = .5, n = 10, and
L = 1.5. Setting (2.2) and (2.3) each equal to zero and substituting in these parameters allows us to calculate
r, = 1.00005 and r, = 2.0.

''

Our moral hazard story is equivalent to what Stiglitz and Weiss call the ."the interest rate as an incentive
mechanism." See also Longhofer (1994).

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

respectively.
Since project B is successful less frequently than is project G, given any d the expected cost of
default will be higher under project B. If the chance of default is sufficiently high, debt financing will
be too expensive and the firm will forgo the project (recall that the firm may undertake only one of the
two projects). We will assume that the good project is safe enough to ensure that (2.4) is positive, while
the bad project is so risky that (2.5) is non-positive (i.e., that rBL > 3. In other words, r, is so high that
the firm is unable to make positive expected profits.'920 Nevertheless, it is easy to show:

PRoPosITIoN 2: Ifproject B is more risky than project G (in the sense of Rothschild-Stiglitz), then given
any promised payment, the jirm will always prefer project B."

Proof: See appendix.
-

This proposition implies that long-term debt prevents the firm from credibly promising to invest
in the less risky project. Once it receives the (relatively low) interest rate associated with G, it would like
to go ahead and invest in B, since it suffers none of the losses associated with the increased variability
of the project. If long-term debt is the only option, no lender will accept any interest rate below r,, and

l 9 Since project B has the same expected return as project G under full information, this implies that debt creates
an underinvestment problem. This is not a necessary feature of the model. AU of our results can be proved under
the assumption that B is a negative net present value project, eliminating this implied inefficiency.
20 In our example started in footnote 17, the f m ' s expected profit from project G is .499975, whereas its
expected profit would be zero if it were to undertake project B.

This proposition is verified by our example: If the fm were unconditionally offered the good interest rate
( r g = 1.00005), its expected profit from selecting the bad project would be .749912, which is higher than the
expected return from selecting the good project.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

no project will be undertaken.
This inability of the firm to commit to the less risky project obviously entails social costs. Since

r, ensures that lenders make zero profits, the total cost to society is measured by the profits the firm
would make under project G, given by expression (2.4):

Short-Term Debt
Is it possible to avoid this cost? One solution to this moral hazard problem is a maturity mismatch
with short-term debt?2 Suppose the firm must make a payment to its lenders in period two. Since the
firm has no revenues until period three, it must either default or convince the lenders to roll over its debt.
Prior to renewing the debt, however, lenders can monitor the firm and determine which project has been
selected. We will assume that potential lenders are diverse and uncoordinated and thus unable to decide
To analyze this situation, we will assume that each lender
ex ante who should perform the m~nitoring?~
has equal priority and look for a symmetric mixed-strategy Nash equilibrium.
When the firm receives its financing in period one, it decides how often it will invest in each of
the two projects. Let .rr:

E

[O,11 be the probability that project B is selected. In period two, lenders must

decide how often they will monitor the firm, i.e., pick a monitoring probability a

E

[O,]]. Since we are

looking for a symmetric equilibrium, the total probability that the firm is monitored is 1-(1 -a)".
Conditional on the result of his own monitoring (if it occurs), each lender can then decide whether

22 Dionne and Viala (1992) also note that short-term debt can be used to ameliorate moral hazard problems.
However, they assume that the action selected by the agent (or in our case, the project selected by the fm) is
costlessly observable.
23 In section IV, we show that our results remain essentially unchanged even when a
ll monitoring tasks are
delegated to one lender.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

or not to renew his loan. Since the firm has no cash assets in period two, whenever

lender chooses

to demand repayment, the firm is liquidated unless it can obtain alternative financing to pay off its old
debt.
Let z be the (post-bankruptcy cost) period-two liquidation value of the firm. We assume that
z < L, so that this value is insufficient to pay off all of the firm's debts. Lenders who monitor are the

first in line for the firm's assets when it is liquidated, since they are the first to be aware that the firm has
cheated. Thus, under FCFS rules, the firm's assets, z, are first divided among the monitors, with nonmonitors receiving a share only after all monitors' claims are paid in full. If instead PPRs are in effect,
the liquidation value of the firm is divided equally among all creditors, regardless of whether they
monitored.
Finally, if the firm is not liquidated in period two, its project matures and revenues are received
in period three. If the firm is able to pay off all lenders, it keeps the balance; otherwise, it is liquidated
and its residual value is divided equally among the creditors."

Derivation of an Equilibrium
We now look for a symmetric equilibrium. In equilibrium, the probability of monitoring, a , must
make the firm indifferent between choosing project G and project B:

I m a x (x-rl, 0 ) dG(x)

=

(1 -a)"lmax (x-rl, 0 ) dB@).

The return to each lender will depend upon the number of other lenders who monitor. Let M(w)
denote the probability that w of the other lenders monitor the firm in period two. Clearly, w has a
binomial distribution so that

24 Note that in period three, no lender has advance information that the fm will default. Thus, a
ll lenders have
equal priority in this period. We show in section V that strict priority rules which govern the distribution of assets
both in this period and in period 2 are inefficient.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

Given that all other lenders behave in the same way, the expected return to a lender who monitors is
L
(1-7~)RG(r) + n c l ( r ) - c - -,
n

(2.8)

where

is the lender's expected return when the firm chooses project G, and

5, is the expected return to a lender

who monitors when the firm "cheats." Under PPRs, this is just the period-two liquidation value of the

firm divided by the number of lenders, so:

With FCFS rules, this return depends upon the number of other lenders with whom the liquidation value
of the firm must be shared. If z is large enough, each lender receives Lln, the principal value of the loan.
Otherwise, the monitoring lenders divide z equally among themselves. This gives us

"c

n-1

M(W) min {L,

=
W-O

L}.

w+1 n

On the other hand, the expected return to a lender who does not monitor is

where R,(r) is defined like R,(r), and

5, is the expected return to a non-monitoring lender when the firm

is liquidated in period two. Under PPRs,

while under FCFS rules,

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

The intuition behind (2.12)is as follows: The first term is the lender's expected return when the
firm chooses project G. If the firm instead chooses project B, the lender's expected return depends upon
the monitoring decisions of the other lenders. If none of them monitor, then all lenders roll over their debt
and the firm continues until period three, giving us the second term. Finally, if at least one of the other
lenders monitors the firm, it is liquidated, and lenders who don't monitor expect to receive the third
expression.
Define asas the solution to (2.6), and ns and rs to be the probability of monitoring and the
interest rate that simultaneously solve (2.8) and (2.12) equal to zero. Then we have the following
characterization of equilibrium:

PROPOSITION
3: When the period-two liquidation value of the firm, z, is suficiently large, the following
strategies constitute a mhed-strategy Nash equilibrium with short-term debt:
( 1 ) The firm chooses project B with probability n s, and project G with

probability (1-ns);
(2) Lenders choose to monitor with probability as,
and refuse to renew
their loans only when they observe project B; and

(3) All outsiders assume that the firm has chosen project B with
probability one whenever it seeks new financing in period two.

Proof: See appendix.

An examination of the proof of Proposition 3 provides some intuition on the required lower bound

on the period-two liquidation value of the firm: z must be larger than the sum of lenders' expected returns
from allowing a "bad" firm to continue. That is, if lenders as a group expect to receive more from

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

allowing the riskier firm to continue, they will do so, and these strategies will not be an equilibrium. This
is a natural parametric restri~tion.~~
In the next section, we show that this contract is less likely to exist under PPRs than it is under
FCFS rules, and that when it does exist, it is more costly to implement.

Section I11 - Existence and Efficiency of Equilibrium
The equilibrium developed in the previous section was derived in a manner consistent with both
FCFS rules and PPRs. Our goal in this section is to show that 1 ) equilibrium is less likely to occur under

PPRs, and 2 ) when it does exist, the total social cost of the contract will be higher under PPRs. We do
this by examining the interest rate in this problem under each of these rules.
In order for equilibrium to exist, as must solve (2.6):

and .ns and rs must solve both

and

(1 -.n) R,(r)

+

.n(1 -a)"-' R,(r)

+

L
.n&(r) - n

=

0.

(3.3)

In addition, the following conditions must be satisfied: 0 I as I 1 , 0 I .ns I 1 , and 1 I rs I ?/L.26

25 The lower bound on z is more stringent under PPRs than it is under FCFS rules, implying that this equilibrium
exists for a smaller range of parameter values under PPRs (z can be smaller under FCFS rules). This reinforces our
claim that FCFS rules dominate PPRs (see section 111).

Proposition 2 implies that asis always positive. Moreover, it will be less than one whenever project G is
profitable for the fm.
26

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

THEOREM
1: The interest rate is higher under PPRs than it is under FCFS rules.

Proof: See appendix.

The intuition behind Theorem 1 is straightforward and is illustrated in figure 2. Let x, be the
locus of (x, r ) pairs that solve (3.2) and 7c, be the locus solving (3.3). The left-most intersection of these
loci is our equilibriu~n.~~

Figure 2
When the firm is caught investing in project B, FCFS rules give more to lenders who monitor than
do PPRs. Thus,

is everywhere above x y . Similarly, when the firm is caught cheating, lenders

who don't monitor receive less under FCFS rules than they do under PPRs: PPRs allow lenders to free

27 Since any such intersection provides lenders with zero expected profit, the equilibrium is the one that results
in the lowest possible interest rate for the borrower, i.e., the left-most intersection.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

ride on the monitoring efforts of others. Hence,

flis everywhere below .np.
This implies that the

first intersection of these two curves under PPRs must be to the right of the first intersection under FCFS
rules, so the equilibrium under FCFS rules must entail a lower interest rate?8
It is immediately clear that equilibrium is less likely to exist under PPRs:

Existence of an equilibrium is less likely under PPRs than it is under FCFS rules.
COROLLARY:

Proof: For the less risky project to be feasible, the total payment made by the firm, rsL, must be less than

7 , the project's largest possible o ~ t c o m e ?As
~ r increases, this condition is less likely to be satisfied.

4

Basically, the shifts in n, and 7c, due to the change in bankruptcy rules make an intersection
between them less likely to occur within our relevant range. As shown in figure 2, Y / L is the highest
value the interest rate can take and still allow the firm to make non-negative profits. Since

71:y
and

first intersect at an interest rate higher than YIL, an equilibrium does not exist under PPRs (in this
example).
Also note that Proposition 3 implies equilibrium is less likely to exist under PPRs. That
proposition required that the period-two liquidation value of the firm exceed the sum of the lenders'
expected returns from allowing project B to mature. Under FCFS rules, this critical z is smaller than it

Let us again turn to the example that we started in foomote 17. If we assume z = 1.4, direct calculation
verifies that when FCFS rules are in effect the interest rate is 1.00695, while under PPRs it is 1.01092.
29 Strictly speaking, this bound may be even lower. If d is sufficiently large, credit rationing will appear,
reducing the maximal feasible interest rate. In this case, however, it is the lenders who will refuse to participate.
See Longhofer (1994) for a more detailed examination of this type of credit rationing.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

is under PPRs, meaning that equilibrium will exist for more values of z under FCFS rules than under
PPRs.~'
Even when an equilibrium does exist under both types of bankruptcy proceedings, we can show
that the equilibrium under FCFS rules Pareto dominates that arising under P P R s . ~ ~

THEOREM
2: Total surplus is larger under FCFS rules than under PPRs.

Proof:
-

Since lenders make zero profits under both procedures, total surplus is measured by the firm's

expected profits:

When rs changes, (2.6) implies that as adjusts so as to keep:

X

X

As a result, any change in nS is irrelevant - it merely changes the relative weights placed on two equal
quantities. But increases in the interest rate lower both terms in (3.4) because:

Since rs is higher under PPRs, firm profits must be higher under FCFS rules. r

30 In ow example, z must be larger than 1.12917 under PPRs, but it must only be larger than 0.616982 under
FCFS rules.
3' In ow example, total social surplus (as defmed by the f m ' s expected profits) is .489619 under FCFS rules,
while it is only .48367 under PPRs.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

Essentially, PPRs encourage lenders to free ride on the monitoring efforts of others, since these
rules give each of them the same claim on the firm's assets regardless of whether or not they monitor.
With FCFS rules, lenders do have an incentive to monitor, since it gives them first call on the firm's assets
in default. This reduces the interest rate needed to give lenders zero expected profits, letting the firm earn
a higher return.

Section IV - Delegated Monitor
One might argue that FCFS rules result in excessive monitoring of the firm, since monitoring will
generally be done by more than one lender. If instead the lenders were to coordinate and name a
delegated monitor, total social costs might decline. We show in this section that FCFS rules are preferred
to both PPRs and APRs when a delegated monitor is selected.
As before, the firm needs to raise L to finance either project. We will assume that the lender to
whom the task of monitoring is delegated (henceforth called the "bank) loans the firm L,, with the rest
of the investment, L-LB = L,, being provided by the n-1 non-monitoring ("public") lenders. Since the
bank must be compensated for monitoring, the interest rate it receives will in general differ from that paid
to the other lenders. Let rB be the interest rate received by the bank, and r, the rate received by all other
lenders. Then the total obligation of the firm is
p = rBLB+ rpLp.

(4.1)

As before, the probability that the bank monitors in period two must be set so that the firm is indifferent
between the two projects:

The interest rate received by public lenders is determined by their zero-profit condition:

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

where R: and R: are the expected returns to a public lender from the completion of projects G and B,
respectively. The definition of these functions is analogous to that in section 11.

5, is the expected return

to public lenders when the firm chooses project B and is monitored by the bank. Under FCFS rules,
public lenders are paid only after the bank receives its entire claim, while under PPRs, all of the firm's
assets are divided equally among the lenders. Thus,
z -L,
E , F = m a x { , O )
n-1

t,P=hpz,

and

(4.4)

where hp = Lp/(n-1)L is the proportion of the total debt held by an individual public lender. Similarly,
we will define h, = L,/L as the portion of the firm's total debt held by the bank.
The bank's interest rate and the probability that the firm chooses project B are determined by the
simultaneous solution of the following two equations:

(1%)~:
(1 9 ) R,B

+x:h- C
+

-LB =0,

x R,B - L,

=

(4.5)
(4.6)

0.

As above, R: and R; are the bank's expected returns when projects G and B mature, respectively, and

cB is the bank's return when it monitors a firm choosing project B. Under FCFS rules, the bank receives
all of the firm's assets in liquidation up to the value of its claim ( 5 y = min {z, L , ) ) , while under'PPRs,
the assets are divided proportionately among all creditors ( 5 r

=

&z).

Total surplus is measured by expected firm profit:

Expected profit, and hence social welfare, will be increased whenever p is decreased. Our goal is to show
that p will be smaller under FCFS rules than it is under PPRs. To do so, we consider a slightly simplified
version of our model by assuming that the probability of default is unaffected by the interest rate paid to

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

each lender, and that the cost of default (state verification) is a constant d.32

THEOREM
3: Total surplus is higher under FCFS rules than it is under PPRs.

Proof: See appendix.

Equilibrium is less likely to exist under PPRs than it is under FCFS rules.
COROLLARY:

Proof: By Theorem 3, the firm's obligation is higher under PPRs. n

Theorem 3 shows that firm profit is higher under FCFS rules when the bank and public lenders
have the same priority level. The reason is that FCFS rules compensate the bank for performing its
function as a monitor, thereby increasing the amount of this socially desirable activity.
Naive intuition would suggest, then, that banks should be given absolute seniority over public
debt. This conclusion is incorrect. Absolute seniority gives the bank first claim on the firm's assets in
default, whether or not the bank performs its monitoring duties. Paying the bank more regardless of its
actions is no better, from a social welfare viewpoint, than using PPRs. To see this, consider the following.
Let project B take the value

x with probability p and -x with probability (1-p). Project G, on the

other hand, has a fixed return of (1-p)x-

+

p?.

We will assume that project G's expected return is

32 Technically, increasing the payment to one lender increases the probability of default, thereby reducing the
expected return to all other lenders, holding constant the interest rate they receive. Generally, this second-order effect
is small and does not overwhelm those effects analyzed in the proof. The assumption that the probability of default
is unaffected by small changes in the interest rates avoids this problem and simplifies ow proofs. Note that this
assumption is satisfied for most discrete distributions.
Under this assumption, it can also be shown that all previous propositions hold when the cost of default is
a constant d. In particular, Proposition 1 holds with no restriction on the size of d. Although a constant d introduces
a discontinuity into the payoff of the lender at the value of x where default just occurs, the assumption above ensures
that no such x will be observed ex post, always making the lender prefer the less risky project.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

sufficiently high that the firm is always able to make its payments in period three. In contrast, if the firm
chooses project B, it can meet its obligations only when the project is successful. As above, we assume
that the cost of state verification is fixed at d.
Now the bank's expected return from monitoring is
(I-rc)r,~,

+

rccy - c - L,,

(4.8)

while the return from not monitoring is
('-n)r,L,

+

x[pr,L,

+

( l - p ) ~ , ]- L,,

(4.9)

where y ~ , is the bank's expected return when the firm defaults. Under FCFS rules, this is h, (&-d), and
it is x-d
- when the bank has strict seniority.33
The public lenders' expected return is

where

yr, is the expected return to the public lender when project B is chosen, is allowed to continue, and

fails. Under FCFS rules y ~ , = h, Q-d), whereas y ~ , = 0 when the bank has strict seniority.
We will now show that when they exist, the equilibrium under FCFS rules Pareto dominates the
one with strict seniority.

THEOREM
4: Total surplus is larger under FCFS rules than it is when the bank has absolute priority.

Proof: We will show that p is a continuous increasing function of yr,.

Since y, is higher under APRs,

firm profit is lower.
Continuity is immediate, so a discrete change in yr, can be viewed as the limit of a sequence of

33 Note that if 2 - d > rBLB, the bank will receive only rBLB. But in this case, the bank will never monitor,
since the lowest possible outcome of project B is still sufficient to repay the bank. This can never be an equilibrium.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

infinitesimal changes.
The change in the firm's obligation is

Note that

vp= k-d-vB)l(n-l) , so d v p l d v B = -1 l(n-1)

< 0. In the proof of Theorem 3, we showed

that arBlaz and a r , l a ~are both positive. Using (4.9):

Using (4.10):

Combining these results proves d p l d y B > 0. 4

COROLLARY:
Equilibrium is less likely to exist when the bank has absolute priority over public lenders
than when FCFS rules are in efect.

Proof: By Theorem 4, the total obligation of the firm is higher under APRs. 4

With APRs, the problem is exactly the opposite of what it is under PPRs: The bank is being paid
too often. The fact that the bank receives first claim on the firm's assets in bankruptcy reduces its
incentive to monitor. As a result, the firm chooses the riskier project more frequently, for whic6 lenders
must be compensated with a higher interest rate.
The lesson here is simple, but important: In order to properly align monitoring incentives, the
bankruptcy procedure should compensate a lender when and only when it monitors the borrower.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

Section V - Conclusions
This paper has questioned the standard assumption that PPRs within each lender class and absolute
priority among classes are always necessary in bankruptcy. In our model, a moral hazard problem makes
the act of monitoring a socially beneficial public good. As such, the total cost of debt contracting is
reduced when the bankruptcy procedure compensates those lenders who monitor a misbehaving firm.
Allowing creditors to "run" on a financially distressed firm to retrieve their assets serves to implement just
such a compensation mechanism.
While existing bankruptcy law is generally believed to discourage such firm runs, many
contractual arrangements do exist that allow lenders with superior information about a firm's prospects
to retrieve their assets before other creditors may be aware of a problem. We now look at two such
mechanisms.
The model of section I1 closely resembles that of a retail firm with many suppliers. Suppliers of
retail outlets commonly provide them with trade credit. These loans are typically renewed shortly after
they are repaid as new merchandise is purchased by the retailer. However, a creditor may refuse to ship
new supplies on credit if it perceives that the firm is in trouble. Thus, the trade creditor looks much like
a monitor from section 111. By refusing to renew its loan, a trade creditor may force a troubled firm into
bankruptcy earlier than it might otherwise have gone, preventing it from taking actions that would further
weaken its financial condition.
A prime example of this type of monitoring occurred in November 1991. Heller Financial, Inc.,
a major factoring company for R.H. Macy & Co., announced that it would no longer guarantee payment
for new goods shipped to the retailer. This announcement turned out to be the first of a series of pressures
placed on Macy that ultimately resulted in its filing for Chapter 11 bankruptcy protection on January 27
of the next year. Heller's announcement not only protected it from future losses, but also served as a
signal to the rest of the market that Macy's financial problems were becoming critical.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

Another common contractual arrangement is the right of acceleration and setoff a bank may
exercise when it discovers a borrower has breached a clause of its loan agreement. If the bank observes
some breech of the loan agreement, it can accelerate the loan and seize the borrower's deposits and other
assets on account with the bank, thereby ensuring at least partial repayment. This aspect of the loan
agreement looks much like the FCFS contracts considered in section IV. Here, the bank is compensated
when it does monitor the firm and detects a problem early. If the bank is not diligent, however, the
distressed firm will file for Chapter 11 bankruptcy protection, thereby nullifying the right of setoff.
An example of this type of situation occurred in April 1993 when Fidelity Bank, acting on behalf
of a seven-bank group, seized NutriISystem, Inc.'s cash and bank accounts after restructuring talks broke
down. This seizure closed 283 of the company's outlets and led its franchisees to force the company into
bankruptcy. In addition, it forced NutriISystem's management to relinquish control to a new investor
group. As with R.H. Macy & Co., the action of Fidelity Bank not only compensated it for performing
its monitoring duties, but also provided a socially valuable service by forcing NutriISystem to deal with
its problems more quickly than it might otherwise have done.
Clearly, these examples are the exception, not the rule, in dealing with financially distressed firms.
But this fact supports our contention that these agreements are designed as incentive mechanisms. If they
are effective in preventing borrower misbehavior, then they shouldn't be exercised often.
Nevertheless, inefficiencies still exist under all of the bankruptcy rules in our model. Most
notably, we have assumed that both projects have a positive net present value, so in a first-best world,
both should be undertaken. Debt in our model creates an underinvestment problem. This does not change
the fact, however, that FCFS rules are more efficient than the other bankruptcy rules considered.
Furthermore, this underinvestment problem is not a necessary feature of our model. All of our results can
still be derived when the more risky project has a negative net present value, provided that the spread
between the expected returns is sufficiently small.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

Lately, there has been extensive debate about whether or not, and if so how, bankruptcy laws
should be reformed.

One proposal receiving significant attention is by Aghion, Hart, and Moore

(1992).~~
They suggest that each of a firm's creditors should be given an option to purchase the firm's

assets from more senior claimants at the value of their claims. This system would guarantee that a
distressed firm's assets end up with the individual or group who values them most, and would ensure that
economically viable firms will continue. While this proposal would do much to eliminate the ex post
inefficiencies associated with modem bankruptcy proceedings, it does not answer the basic concerns we
address in this paper. Like the PPRs and APRs we discuss above, their proposal does not consider the
impact a proper compensation scheme can have on the probability that bankruptcy will occur in the first
place.
This model is not intended to suggest that existing bankruptcy rules should be discarded. Indeed,
our results suggest that some artifacts of Chapter 11 generally viewed as undesirable may in reality
provide some benefit. In particular, the fact that junior claimants often maintain some value even when
more senior claims are not paid in full is often viewed as a weakness of the law. However, if one
assumes that those senior claimants involved in the collective proceeding are those who failed to monitor
the debtor, social welfare is increased by failing to pay them the full value of their claims.35
The main point we wish to emphasize in the debate over bankruptcy reform is that policymakers
should consider the impact of bankruptcy rules not only on the distribution of a financially distressed
firm's assets, but also on the terms of debt contracts. It is this latter influence that has the largest effect
on social welfare.

34

See also Roe (1983) and Bebchuk (1988).

35 Some recent papers have demonstrated that deviations from absolute priority may be welfare improving ex
ante. See Harris and Raviv (1993) and Eberhart and Senbet (1993).

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

Appendix
Proof of PROPOSITION
1: First consider the effect of a change in the interest rate on the lender's expected
retum from any arbitrary project F:

Thus, if d < [ I -F(rL)]If (rL),this derivative will be positive, meaning that an increase in the interest rate
raises the lender's expected retum. This provides the required upper bound for d. In general, this
relationship is ambiguous, since an increase in the interest rate will also increase the probability of default.
Let RB(rJ denote the lender's expected return if project B is chosen with interest rate r,, and
similarly for R,(r,).

Now lenders have a "utility" function of the following form:
u(x)

=

min {

x -d(rL -x)

rL

,-1,

which is a weakly concave, weakly increasing function. But any agent with such a utility function must
have RB(r,) < R,(r,) by second-order stochastic dominance, so the zero-profit interest rate for project B
must be greater than r,. n

Proof of PROPOSITION
2: We wish to show that the difference between the expected profit from project
B and the expected profit from project G is positive. This difference is

where y is the total payment promised in period three. Integrating by parts, we see that this equals

Now, the condition of equal means,

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

can be integrated by parts to get

This implies

Now, the expression on the right is positive because G is less risky than B. But the expression on the left
is equation (A4), the value to the firm of choosing project B over project G. rcr

Proof of PROPOSITION
3: In the text, we derived the equilibrium probability of monitoring, the probability
of choosing the more risky project, and the zero-profit interest rate. Here we have only to show that no
agent will wish to deviate from his proposed equilibrium strategy.
(1) After observing the more risky project B, a lender who monitors might still wish to renew the
loan. This will not be the case if the expected return from rolling over the debt is less than that from
foreclosing. Under FCFS rules, this requirement is

The left-hand side is the expected return from foreclosing on the loan and depends upon the number of
other lenders who monitor: If the period-two value of the firm is sufficient to pay off all monitors, each
receives Lln; otherwise, the assets are divided equally among them. The right-hand side represents the
expected return from rolling over the debt. If no other lender monitors, the firm continues and the
lender's expected return is RB(r). Otherwise, the firm is liquidated and the lender receives some of the
firm's assets only if all other monitors are paid in full.
29

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

Now notice that the left side of (A8) is always greater than
its smallest value when w

=

Z
-.Z This is clear, since takes

n
w+l
n-1 , and z < L by assumption. Thus, this inequality will always be satisfied

whenever its right-hand side is less than

-.Z Cross-multiplying by n gives us a lower bound for z:
n

A similar lower bound can be derived under PPRs:

(2) A lender might refuse to renew the loan even after observing project G. This is a suboptimal

strategy under both types of bankruptcy rules as long as36

Since the firm has chosen project G, no other lenders foreclose. Thus, the left-hand side is the payment
to a lender who deviates from equilibrium. The right-hand side is the expected return to a monitor who
renews the loan. Clearly, Lln is an upper bound for the left-hand side of this inequality. It is also a lower
bound for the right-hand side, since rs 1r,, the interest rate that ensures R,(r) = Lln. Thus, this
inequality will always hold.
(3) A lender might wish to foreclose when it does not monitor. This will not be the case if the
expected return from foreclosing,

is less than the expected return from rolling over the debt,

36 Technically, the condition under PPRs is min { zln, Lln }
is sufficient for both rules.

30

IR,(rs). But

since zln < z, the above condition

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

( 1 %s

RG(rs) + xs (1 -as>"-I RB(rs>+ +, t2(rs>.

(A131

Now the first term in (A12) is clearly less than ( 1 - x s ) L / n . Furthermore, the second term is less
Z L
L
L
than x s L / n , since min {-,-I I -. Thus, - provides an upper bound on (A12). But (A13) must
w+1 n
n
n
equal Lln, since rs and xs solve (2.12) equal to zero in equilibrium. This ensures that this inequality will

always be satisfied.
(4) The firm might try to refinance its loans using outside lenders in period two. Regardless of

the project chosen, however, outside lenders assume that the firm has selected project B, so the best
interest rate they will accept is r,. This, by assumption, gives the firm non-positive profits. Thus, no
firm will wish to deviate in this manner. r

Proof of THEOREM1: Rewriting (3.2) and (3.3) from the text:
(1 -+)R,(r)

+

+tl(r) = c

+

L
,
n

It is easy to show that
RG(r) 1 c

+

L
n

1 tl(r)

and

ensuring that

+E

[O, I ] .

We can solve (A14) and (A15) for + as functions of the interest rate:

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

nl(r)

R,(r) - c - Lln
=

R G ( ~-) 51(r>

,

n2(r)

=

R,(r) - Lln

(A 18)

RG(r) - (l-ay-lRB(r) - &(r)

The intersections of these two functions will give us (n, r) pairs that simultaneously solve (2.8) and (2.12)
equal to zero. If these curves intersect more than once, the first such intersection is the candidate for
equilibrium, since it entails the lowest interest rate.
Now, xl(r)

= 0

when r

=

rm = R ~ ' ( c + ~ l nand
) , n2(r)

= 0

when r

larger, these must enter the positive orthant, since n is a convex weight.
I C Y ,since Lln L zln and z/(w+l) 2 zln for all w 2 n-1, and

=

r,

= RE'(L/~). As r gets

Clearly, n y m i n ~ r i z e s ~ ~

majorizes n y , since

z-wL1n < l,v w e 11 ,...,n-1).
n-w
n

(A19)

But this implies that the first intersection of n y and n y must lie to the right of the first intersection
of

and

(see figure 2 in the text). Compared to FCFS rules, then, PPRs must entail a higher

interest rate. 4

Proof of THEOREM3: Starting from PPRs and switching to FCFS rules, let d5, denote change in the
bank's expected return when it monitors a firm that chooses project B:
d5,

=

min {z,L,) - h, z > 0 .

(A20)

(This must be positive, since h, < 1 and z < L). Rewrite p as
~(5,) = r,(5,) L,

+

rp(5,) L p .

(A21)

We will show that p(5,) is a continuous decreasing function, meaning that the switch to FCFS rules
reduces p; this reduction increases firm profit and, hence, social surplus.
Continuity is immediate. This means that the impact of the discrete change in

5,

can be

calculated using a sequence of infinitesimal changes.

37 That is, for every r, n y ( r ) < np"(r). Similarly, the phrase
n y ( r ) ,V r.

fl majorizes n

y means that n y ( r ) >

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

The change in the firm's total obligation is

To simplify this expression, we derive each of its terms. Note that

5,

(z<,)/(n-1),

=

which implies

dcp/dcB = -1 /(n-1). Using (4.6), we get:

Following the same argument we used in the proof of Theorem 1, we can see that drB/dcB< 0.
From (4.5) and (4.6), we can calculate
B

nl(rB) =

RG - c

- LB

R,B - 5s

respectively. As before, the r that causes

K, =

and

xz(rB) =

R~~ - L~

R,B

- R~~ '

0 is larger than the r making nZ = 0 , meaning that for

every r < r * (the equilibrium interest rate, if it exists), .n,(r) < .n,(r). Now an increase in
.n,(r) to be larger for every r. As a consequence, the first intersection of

cBincreases; i.e.,

calculating this derivative using (4.5).
Finally, (4.3) allows us to calculate:

and

K,

cB causes

and x2 moves to the left as

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

arpan drs < O, so
We now use these expressions to simplify and sign d p . First, note that arBdS,

a~

Substituting:

where G ( p ) is the distribution of the good project evaluated at p.

R,

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

References
Aghion, Philippe and Patrick Bolton. "An 'Incomplete Contract' Approach to Bankruptcy and the
Financial Structure of the Firm." Review of Economic Studies, 1992, 59, 473-494.
Aghion, Philippe, Oliver Hart, and John Moore. "The Economics of Bankruptcy Reform." Journal of
Law, Economics, and Organization, October 1992, 8(3), 523-546.
Bebchuk, Lucian A. "A New Approach to Corporate Reorganizations." Harvard Law Review, 1988,
101(4), 775-804.
Berkovitch, Elazar and Ronen Israel. "The Bankruptcy Decision and Debt Contract Renegotiations."
University of Michigan, Working Paper, 1991.
Berkovitch, Elazar and E. Han Kim. "Financial Contracting and Leverage Induced Over- and UnderInvestment Incentives." Journal of Finance, July 1990, 45(3), 765-794.
Berlin, Mitchell and Loretta J. Mester. "Debt Covenants and Renegotiation." Journal of Financial
Intermediation, 1992, 95(2), 95-133.
Boyd, John H. and Bruce D. Smith. "The Equilibrium Allocation of Investment Capital in the Presence
of Adverse Selection and Costly State Verification." Economic Theory, 1993a, 3(3), 427-451.
Boyd, John H. and Bruce D. Smith. "The Welfare Costs of Absolute Priority Rules: Stochastic Versus
Nonstochastic Monitoring in a Costly State Verification Environment." Federal Reserve Bank of
Mi~eapolis,Working Paper 512, May 1993b.
Boyes, William J., Roger L. Faith, and Jeffrey M. Wrase. "An Efficiency Theory of Bankruptcy Rules."
Arizona State University, Working Paper No. 91-8, 1991.
Bulow, Jeremy I. and John B. Shoven. "The Bankruptcy Decision." Bell Journal of Economics, 1978,
9, 437-456.
Calomiris, Charles W. and Charles M. Kahn. "The Role of Demandable Debt in Structuring Optimal
Banking Arrangements." American Economic Review, June 1991, 81(3), 497-5 13.
Calomiris, Charles W., Charles M. Kahn, and Stefan Krasa. "Optimal Contingent Bank Liquidation under
Moral Hazard." University of Illinois, Working Paper, 1991.
Detragiache, Enrica. "The Resolution of Financial Distress under Asymmetric Information: Is There a
Need for Chapter 1I?" Johns Hopkins University, Working Paper, 1991.
Diamond, Douglas W. "Debt Maturity Structure and Liquidity Risk." University of Chicago, Working
Paper No. 275, 1990a.
Diamond, Douglas W. "Seniority and Maturity Structure of Bank Loans and Publicly Traded Debt."
University of Chicago, Working Paper No. 308, 1990b.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

Diamond, Douglas W. "Monitoring and Reputation: The Choice between Bank Loans and Directly
Placed Debt." Journal of Political Economy, 1991, 99(4), 689-721.
Diamond, Douglas W. "Bank Loan Maturity and Priority When Borrowers Can Refinance." University
of Chicago Working Paper, 1992.
Dionne, Georges and Pascale Viala. "Optimal Design of Financial Contracts and Moral Hazard."
University of Montreal, Working Paper, August 1992.
Eberhart, Allan C. and Lemma W. Senbet. "Absolute Priority Rule Violations and Risk Incentives for
Financially Distressed Firms." Financial Management, Autumn 1993, 22(3), 101-116.
Eberhart, Allan C., W.T. Moore, and R.L. Roenfeldt. "Security Pricing and Deviations from the Absolute
Priority Rule in Bankruptcy Proceedings." Journal of Finance, December 1990, 1457-1469.
Gale, Douglas and Martin Hellwig. "Incentive-Compatible Debt Contracts: The One-Period Problem."
Review of Economic Studies, 1985, 52, 647-663.
Gertner, Robert and David Scharfstein. "A Theory of Workouts and the Effects of Reorganization Law."
Journal of Finance, September 1991, 46(4), 1189-1222.
Hams, Milton and Artur Raviv. "The Design of Bankruptcy Procedures." Northwestern University,
Kellogg Graduate School of Management, Working Paper No. 137, March 1993.
Hart, Oliver and John Moore. "Default and Renegotiation: A Dynamic Model of Debt." Massachusetts
Institute of Technology, Working Paper, 1989.
Jackson, Thomas H. The Logic and Limits of Bankruptcy Law. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press, 1986.
Jensen, Michael C. "Corporate Control and the Politics of Finance." Journal of Applied Corporate
Finance, 1991, 4, 13-33.
Jensen, Michael C. and William H. Meckling. "Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behavior, Agency Costs,
and Ownership Structure." Journal of Financial Economics, 1976, 3, 305-360.
Krasa, Stefan and Anne P. Villamil. "Optimal Multilateral Contracts." Economic Theory, 1994, 4, 167187.
Laffont, Jean-Jacques. The Economics of Uncertainty and Information. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press,
1989.
Longhofer, Stanley D. "A Note on Absolute Priority Rule Violations, Credit Rationing, and Efficiency."
Federal Reserve Bank of Cleveland, unpublished manuscript, October 1994.
Myers, Stewart C. "Determinants of Corporate Borrowing." Journal of Financial Economics, 1977, 5,
147-175.

clevelandfed.org/research/workpaper/index.cfm

Rajan, Raghurarn and Andrew Winton. "Covenants and Collateral as Incentives to Monitor."
Northwestern University, Working Paper No. 184, July 1994.
Roe, Mark J. "Bankruptcy and Debt: A New Model for Corporate Reorganization." Columbia Law
Review, 1983, 83,527-602.
Rothschild, Michael and Joseph Stiglitz. "Increasing Risk I: A Definition." Journal of Economic Theory,
1970, 2, 225-243. Reprinted in Uncertainty in Economics: Readings and Exercises, Diamond,
Peter and Michael Rothschild, eds., San Diego : Academic Press, Inc., 1989.
Stiglitz, Joesph E. and Andrew Weiss. "Credit Rationing in Markets with Imperfect Information."
American Economic Review, June 1981, 71(3), 393-410.
Townsend, Robert M. "Optimal Contracts and Competitive Markets with Costly State Verification."
Journal of Economic Theory, 1979, 21, 265-293.
White, Michelle J. "Public Policy toward Bankruptcy: Me-First and Other Priority Rules." Bell Journal
of Economics, 1980, 11, 550-564.
White, Michelle J. "Bankruptcy Costs and the New Bankruptcy Code." Journal of Finance, 1983, 38,
477-504.
Winton, Andrew. "Costly State Verification and Multiple Investors:
Northwestern University, Working Paper, 1992.

The Role of Seniority."