The full text on this page is automatically extracted from the file linked above and may contain errors and inconsistencies.
ID НВ ОДМВ у. A0000000000000000000000000000000 000000000000000000000. HARATVEARD L-E- E SOEYspBUUoSoNI IVAEDMRINSISITRTY A O U IL TUNIDAN NESS SCHO OF GRAD L TION TIN IT DOW T WIN SY WE KRESS LIBRARY OF BUSINESS ANDECONOMICS ZOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOO AMERICAN BANK NOTE CO. ERNESTCLEGG FROM TRANSACTIONS OF THE CONNECTICUT ACADEMY, VOL. IX , July, 1892 ) [ The following memoir is in substance the writer's thesis for the degree of Compliments of ULIC THE AUTHOR . By Dr. IRVING FISHER. [ Read April 27, 1892.) ( FROM TRANSACTIONS OF THE CONNECTICUT ACADEMY, VOL . IX , JULY, 1892 ] [ The following memoir is in substance the writer's thesis for the degree of Ph . D . at Yale University , 1891. ] 1. – MATHEMATICAL INVESTIGATIONS IN THE THEORY OF VALUE AND PRICES. By Dr. IRVING FISHER . [ Read April 27, 1892.] ۱۹۰۵ر .ع | 12 % 7۹۰ 3C در یهبر تمر 3 F رج 3 \ PREFACE. John Stuart Mill* asserted that he had left nothing in the laws of value for any future economist to clear up. Until 1871 this state ment doubtless had much the force of dogma. Even Jevonsmade preliminary obeisance before proceeding to break the ground afresh with the mathematical instrument. Jevons with characteristic can dor expressly disclaimed finality ;t but few of his followers have realized with his clearness and honesty the need of further analysis along the lines which he laid down. The truth is, most persons, not excepting professed economists, are satisfied with very hazy notions. How few scholars of the lit erary and historical type retain from their study of mechanics an adequate notion of force ! Muscular experience supplies a concrete and practical conception but gives no inkling of the complicated dependence on space, time, and mass. Only patient mathematical analysis can do that. This natural aversion to elaborate and intri cate analysis exists in Economics and especially in the theory of value. The very foundations of the subject require new analysis and definition . The dependence of value on utility, disutility , and commodity, the equality of utilities, the ratio of utilities, the utility of a commodity as a function of the quantity of that commodity solely , or of that commodity and others conjointly, are subjects, the neglect of which is sure to leave value half understood , and the mastery of which claims, therefore, the first and most patient effort of the economic scientist. These form the subject matter of the following memoir which is a study by mathematicalmethods of the determination of value and prices. Much germane to the subject has been omitted because already elaborated by others. Cases of discontinuity belong to almost every step , to modify or extend the continuous case. But the appli cation of this correction has been thoroughly worked out by Auspitz und Lieben. Multiple equilibrium and monopoly value are omitted for a similar reason . The two books which have influenced memost are Jevons : “ The ory of Political Economy," and Auspitz und Lieben : “ Untersuch * Pol. Econ., Bk. III, Ch. I, $ 1. + Pol. Econ., Pref. 3rd ed . Prefuce. ungen ueber die Theorie des Preises.” To the former I owe the idea of marginal utility and of mathematical treatment in general, to the latter the clear conception of the “ symmetry ” of supply and demand and the use of rate of commodity in place of absolute commodity , and to both many minor obligations. The equations in Chapter IV , § 10 , were found by me two years ago, when I had read no mathematical economist except Jevons. They were an appropriate extension of Jevons' determination of exchange of two commodities between two trading bodies to the exchange of any number of commodities between any number of traders and were obtained as the interpretation of the mechanism which I have described in Chapter IV . That is, the determinate ness of the mechanism was expressed by writing as many equations as unknowns. These equations are essentially those of Walras in his Éléments d' économie politique pure. The only fundamental differences are that I use marginal utility throughout and treat it as a function of the quantities of commodity, whereas Professor Walras makes the quantity of each commodity a function of the prices. That similar results should be obtained independently and by sepa rate paths is certainly an argument to be weighed by those skeptical of the mathematicalmethod. It seemed best not to omit these ana lytical portions of Part I, both because they contribute to an under standing of the other portions of the work and because they were in a proper sense my own . Three days after Part II was finished I received and saw for the first time Prof. Edgeworth 's Mathematical Psychics. I was much interested to find a resemblance between his surface on page 21 and the total utility surfaces* described by me. The resemblance , how ever, does not extend far. It consists in the recognition that in an exchange, utility is a function of both commodities (not of one only as assumed by Jevons), the use of the surface referred to as an inter pretation thereof and the single phrase (Math . Psych., p. 28) “ and similarly for larger numbers in hyperspace” which connects with Part II, Ch . II, $ 5 . There is one point, however, in which, as it seems to me, the writer of this very suggestive book has gone far astray. Mathe * His result, which translated into my notation is | dU / AU 7 d (da ) (ab,) - (2B )(and) = 0, laA . becomes by transposition and division identical with part of the continuous pro portion , Part 1, Ch . IV , $ 3. Preface. matical economists have been taunted with the riddle : What is a unit of pleasure or utility ? Edgeworth, following the Physiological Psychologist Fechner, answers : “ Just perceivable increments of pleasure are equatable ” (p. 99). I have always felt that utility must be capable of a definition which shall connect it with its posi tive or objective commodity relations. A physicist would certainly err who defined the unit of force as the minimum sensible of mus cular sensation . Prof. Edgeworth admits his perplexity : “ It must be confessed that we are here leaving the terra firma of physical analogy ” (p. 99). Yet he thinks it is “ a principle on which we are agreed to act but for which it might be hard to give a reason ;" and again : [ such equality ] “ it is contended , not without hesitation is appropriate to our subject.” This foisting of Psychology on Economics seems to me inappro priate and vicious. Others besides Prof. Edgeworth have done it. Gossen * and Jevons appeared to regard the “ calculus of Pleasure and Pain ” t as part of the profundity of their theory. They doubt less saw no escape from its use. The result has been that “ mathe matics” has been blamed for “ restoring the metaphysical entities previously discarded .” I These writers with Cournot,$ Menger,|| and Marshall appear to me to have contributed the most to the subject in hand. With the exceptions noted I have endeavored not to repeat them but to add a little to them , partly in the theory of the subject and partly in the mode of representing that theory. Readers to whom the subject is new will find the present memoir exceedingly condensed. In the attempt to be brief, the possible uses of the diagrams and mechan isms have been merely sketched , and elaborate explanations and illustrations have been omitted. I have assumed that my readers are already familiar with (say) Jevons, Walras,Menger or Wieser where illustrations and explanations regarding “ final utility ” abound. Much of Part II and Appendix Imay notbe thoroughly intelligible to those not familiar with higher geometrical analysis. These parts are made as brief as possible. My especial thanks are due to Prof. Gibbs and Prof. Newton for valuable criticism . IRVING FISHER. Yale University, May, 1892 . * Menschlich Verhehr., Braunschweig , 1854. # Dr. Ingram . + Jevons, p . 23, also pp. 8– 9. S Théorie des Richesses, Paris, 1838. | Volkswirthschaftslehre, Wien , 1871. [ Prin . of. Econ., Macmillan , 1890. SYLLABUS. PART 1. UTILITY OF EACH COMMODITY ASSUMED TO BE DEPENDENT ONLY ON THE QUANTITY OF THAT COMMODITY . consensus es CHAPTER I. Utility as a Quantity. Page § 1. Psycho -economic postulate, . . . § 2. Definitionsof equal and unequal utilities, . . . 11 12 § 3. Application of these definitions to an equation of exchange, . . § 5. $ 6. § 7. § 8. § 9. $ 10. . . . . 12 . . . . . . . § 4. Definition of the ratio of two utilities, Analogy with other mathematical definitions, . Marginal utility , unit ofutility, . Exact meaning of a utility curve, . . . Total utility, utility -value, gain or consumer's rent, Element of time, Utility curves for a time-period and for an instant, 14 . 17 . . 18 19 . $ 11. A yearly utility curve implies no exact foreknowledge of amounts consumed , . . . . . . $ 12. Theory of probabilities partially eliminates sporadic influences except as regards “ gain ,” . . . . . $ 13. Infinitesimals appropriate though non -existent, $ 14 . The preceding definitions ofutility absolve the econ omist from psychologicaland metaphysical disputes, $ 15. Summary of Chapter 1, · · · · · CHAPTER II. Mechanism . § § § $ 1. 2. 3. 4. Mechanicalanalogy common in economic thought, . .. Ideal suppositions concerning themarket, A new utility diagram . Its related cistern (Fig. 2), A single commodity and a single consumer, . . . § 5. One commodity — one producer; disutility diagram . . 6. One commodity - many consumers (Fig. 4), . and cistern (Fig. 3), . . § 7. Analytical interpretation of S6 , $ 8. Aggregate commodity, . . . . . . . . § 9. One commodity - many producers (Fig . 5), § 10. Preceding simply gives exactitude to the common imagery of thought, . . . . . .. Syllabus. CHAPTER III. One consumer (or producer)- many commodities. Page $ 1. Distribution of income, S2. Mechanism (Fig . 6), . . . . . . . . 83. The three determining conditions of such equilibrium , $ 4 . Analytical interpretation of g3, . . . . . . . . . . § 5 . Aggregate income, . . . . . $ 6. One producer - many commodities (Fig. 7), 34 35 CHAPTER IV . m commodities— n consumers (or producers). § 1. Relative points of view of Chapters II, III, and IV, . § 2 . These points of view compared exactly and analyti cally , . . . . . . . § 3. Equality of marginal utilities now gives way to their . . . § 5. Equilibrium automatic , . . . $ 6 . The various magnitudes represented , . § 7. Two simple relations of these magnitudes, § 8. Complex interdependence traced , 1. Equal incomes, · · · · · 2. One income increased , . . . . 3. One income increased , one decreased, . 4. One commodity increased , . . . . . . . . proportionality , § 4. Mechanism (Figs. 8, 9, 10, 11), . . · . . 45 . 5. One commodity increased with resulting in . . . . 7. All incomes increased , . . . come-increase, . . . 8. Change in individual characteristics, . § 9. Aggregate cisterns impossible , . . . . $ 10. Analytical, $ 11. m commodities - n producers (Figs. 12, 13), . · · · · · · . 6 . All commodities increased , . . .. . 54 CHAPTER V . Production and consumption combined . 8 1. Interdependence of production and consumption must not be overlooked , . § 2. Assumptions, . . . . . . . . . $ 3. One individual consuming just that quantity of a given commodity which he himself produces (Fig. 14), . $ 4. Analytical, . . . $ 5 . n individuals- m commodities (Figs. 15 , 16 ), . . . . . . . . . . .. . . 61 83. Further subdivision of production, . . . . 63 $ 6. Analytical, . . . . . . . . . . . CHAPTER VI. The component processes of production . $ 1. Retailing (Fig. 17), . . . . 82. Analytical, . . . . . Syllabus. PART II. UTILITY OF ONE COMMODITY A FUNCTION OF THE QUANTITIES OF ALL COMMODITIES . Page 64 § 1. Introduction , . . . . § 2. Interdependence of utilities common , § 3. Effect on the cistern-analysis, . . . 4. Competing and completing commodities defined, 5 . Cistern -analysis correct but incomplete, . . § 6. The third definition of utility (Part 1, Ch. I), . . · · · · · · · · · · · con encinco como cos CHAPTER I. Two commodities with interrelated utilities . 65 66 07 Two commodities, § 8. Impossible combinations of two commodities, . .. . $ 9 . Curves of utility , . . . $ 10. Indifference curves, . . . . . . S 11. Partial income line tangent to indifference curve, . . $ 12. Different sensitiveness of competing and completing commodities, . . . . . . . . $ 13. Good and poor qualities of the same commodity, . S 14. “ Maximum directions," . . . . . $ 15 . “ Maximum directions” of all consumers parallel, menu con . . . . S 16 . Production , $ 17. Production and consumption , . CHAPTER II. Three or more commodities. § 1. Construction in three dimensions, .. . . . . § 2. Complicated dependence of utilities, . .. . . . . . . § 3. Equilibrium if only three commodities exist, . . . 8 4. Passage to two dimensions by plane sections, . § 5. m dimensions requisite , · .. $ 6 . m dimensions used , . . § 7. Conditions of equilibrium , § 8. Passage to lower dimensions by “ fat ” sections, $ 9. Analytical (vector analysis ), . . . $ 10 . Peculiar cases ofmarginalutility, . . . . . $ 1. No need to compare two persons' utilities, . . $ 2. How such a comparison might be made, . . CHAPTER III. Mechanical analogies. $ 1. Mechanical analogies discussed , 82. Analogies in parallel columns, . CHAPTER IV . Utility as a quantity . . . S 3. How it could be applied to statistics, . . . 84. Definition (3 ) (Part I, Ch. I) unessential in Part II , . $ 5 . “ Maximum directions” alone important. . . . $ 6 . Integration of total utility probably impossible for in terrelated utilities, . . . . . . . 87. Arbitrary constants unessential, . . . . $ 8. Four attributes of utility unessential in the present in vestigation , . . . . . . . . 67 69 Syllabus. APPENDIX I. MISCELLANEOUS REMARKS ON Part I. Page I. Failure ofequations, . . . . . . . . . 90 II. The cisterns and diagrams of Part I compared with the diagrams of Jevons and of Auspitz und Lieben . $ 1. Possible geometrical representations of commodity and . . III. Gain a maximum , $ 1. For one individual, . . . . . $ 2. For one commodity and in what sense true, . . . . . . . . . . . $ 7. Total utility and gain , · · · · · $ 5. Properties essential to the cisterns, . $ 6. Meaning of the abscissa, . . . · · utility, . . . . . . . . . $ 2. Scheme comparing the cistern -coördinates with those of Jevons and of Auspitz und Lieben , . . . $ 3. A linear assumption , . . . . . . . $ 4. The relative value of the diagrams, . . . . . $ 3. For whole market and in what sense true, $ 4. Under what conditions would the totalmarket gain be maximum if we could obtain the “ true” equivalence between two persons' utilities, . . . . IV . Elimination of variables, . . . . . . . . . Each price is the quotientof two determinants, and all equa 101 tions can be reduced to a single set involving commodities only. APPENDIX II. LIMITATIONS OF THE PRECEDING ANALYSES. § 1. The suppositionswere ideal, . . . . . § 2. Utility a function of many variables, § 3. Articles not homogeneous nor infinitely divisible, . 102 . 103 103 $ 4. Discontinuity in time, § 5 . Statics and Dynamics , . . § 6 . Population , . . . . . 101 102 . . 104 $ 7. No perfect individual freedom to stop producing (or consuming) at any point, . § 8. No perfectknowledge of prices, . 104 . . . . 104 . . . § 9. Production different from consumption in many im portant respects, . . . . . . . . $ 10. Marginal utility and disutilitymay occasionally vary in a manner opposite to that which has been sup posed , . . . . . . . . . 105 106 $ 11. Markets are not isolated and there is no perfect market, . . . . . . . . . 106 Syllabus. APPENDIX III. THE UTILITY AND HISTORY OF MATHEMATICAL METHOD IN ECONOMICS. Page § 1. Its utility is of samekind as the utility of mathemat ical method elsewhere, . . . . . . § 2. Mathematicalmethod distinguished from mathemat ics, . . . . . . . 106 107 . $ 3. Utility of mathematical method is relative to the user, § 4. Mathematicalmethod is for higher economics, . . $ 5. Has mathematicalmethod come to stay ? . . . § 6 . What has it already accomplished ? . . . . § 7. Quotations in favor of mathematical method from 107 108 109 110 Whewell, Cournot, Gossen , Jevons, Walras, New comb, Launhardt, Wicksteed , Foxwell , Auspitz und Lieben , Edgeworth, Marshall, and Cunynghame, . $ 8. Quotations opposed to mathematical method from 112 Anonymous, Cairnes, Wagner, Ingram , and Rab berio , with comments , . § 9. A reason for opposition , . § 10. Conclusion , . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 116 119 119 APPENDIX IV . BIBLIOGRAPHY OF MATHEMATICO -ECONOMIC WRITINGS. § 1. Scope of bibliography, . .. . . . . 120 82. List selected from Jevons' bibliography, . 3. Extension of Jevons'bibliography, . . . . . 122 Part I. - UTILITY OF EACH COMMODITY ASSUMED TO BE DEPEN DENT ONLY ON THE QUANTITY OF THAT COMMODITY . CHAPTER 1. UTILITY AS A QUANTITY . $ 1. The laws of economics are framed to explain facts. The concep tion of utility has its origin in the facts of human preference or decision as observed in producing , consuming and exchanging goods and services. To fix the idea of utility the economist should go no farther than is serviceable in explaining economic facts. It is not his province to build a theory of psychology. It is not necessary for him to take sides with those who wrangle to prove or disprove that pleasure and pain alone determine conduct. These disputants have so mangled the ideas of pleasure and pain that he who follows them and their circular arguments finds himself using the words in forced senses. Jevons makes utility synonymous with pleasure. Cairnes* objects and claims that it leads to a circular definition of value. The circle is however at the very beginning and vitiates psychology not eco nomics ; the last dollar's worth of sugar (we are told ) represents the same quantity of pleasurable feeling as the last dollar's worth of dentistry. This may be true as a mere empty definition, but we must beware of stating it, as a real “ synthetic proposition,” f or of connecting it with the mathematics of sensations| as did Edgeworth. The plane of contact between psychology and economics is desire. It is difficult to see why so many theorists endeavor to obliterate the distinction between pleasure and desire .|| No one ever denied that economic acts have the invariable antecedent, desire. Whether the necessary antecedent of desire is “ pleasure ” or whether indepen dently of pleasure it may sometimes be “ duty ” or “ fear ” concerns a phenomenon in the second remove from the economic act of choice and is completely within the realm of psychology. Wecontent ourselves therefore with the following simple psycho economic postulate : Each individual acts as he desires. * Pol. Econ., p . 21. + Kant, Critique Pure Reason , Introduction . # Ladd, Physiological Psychology, p. 361. See above (Preface). | See Sidgwick , Methods of Ethics, Chap. IV . 12 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations $ 2. The sense in which utility is a quantity is determined by three definitions: (1) For a given individual at a given time, the utility of A units of one commodity or service (a) is equal to the utility of B units of another (6), if the individual has no desire for the one to the exclu sion of the other. A and B are here used as numbers. Thus if the first commodity is sugar and the second calico and if the individual prizes 2 pounds of sugar as much as 10 yards of calico , A is 2 and B is 10. (2 ) For a given individual, at a given time, the utility of A units of (a ) exceeds the utility of B units of (6) if the individual prefers (has a desire for) A to the exclusion of B rather than for B to the exclusion of A . In the same case the utility of B is said to be less than that of A . The third definition will be given in $ 4. The two preceding definitions are exactly parallel to those of any other mathematical magnitude. Thus: two forces are equal if at the same time they alone act on the same particle in opposite directions and no change of motion results. One is greater when additional motion is produced in its direction. Again : “ two masses are equal which if moving with equal velocities along the same straight line in opposite directions and impinging on each other are reduced to rest by the collision." * Two geometricalmagnitudes are equal if they can be made to coin cide, etc., etc. Just as coincidence is the test of equality and inequality of geo metrical figures, and the tip of the scales the test of equality and inequality of weights, so is the desire of the individual, the test of •the equality and inequality of utilities. It is to be noted that in each definition of equality the word “ no ” or some equivalent occurs. A standard mode of cancellation is thus designated . $ 3. Let us see how these definitions of utility apply to an act of pur chase. An individual I enters a market with fixed prices to ex change some of a commodity (a ) for another (6). We may sup pose prices to be such that he gives one gallon of (a) and receives two bushels of (6 ) , then a second gallon for two more bushels and so on * Price , Calculus, vol. iii, p . 316 . in the theory of value and prices. 13 until finally he has given A gallons and received B bushels. At what point does he stop ? Although the “ exchange values ” of A gallons of (a) and B bushels of (6) are equal, their utilities (to I) are not. He prefers B to the exclusion of A , for his act proves his preference (postulate). Therefore by definition (2 ) the utility of B exceeds that of A . Wemay write : ut. of B > ut. of A . Why then did he cease to buy (6) ? He sold exactly A gallons for B bushels. By stopping here he has shown his preference to buy no more (postulate). Ergo the utility of a small increment, say another bushel of (6 ) is less than the utility of the corresponding number of gallons of (a ) (Def. 2). Likewisehe prefers to buy no less. Ergo the utility of a small decrement, say one less bushel is greater than the gallons for buying it. Now by the mathematical principle of continuity , if the small increment or decrement be made infinites imal dB, the two above inequalities become indistinguishable, and vanish in a common equation , viz : ut. of dB = ut. of dA dB and dA are here exchangeable increments. But the last incre ment dB is exchanged for dA at the same rate as A was exchanged for B ; that is A dA B - dᏴ where each ratio is the ratio of exchange or the price of B in terms of A . B =- dAA dB or multiplying this by the first equation , wehave : t. ooff dA uut. ut. of dB . B . A B da d which may be written :* a ab . B == d JAu A . dU The differential coefficients here employed are called by Jevons “ final degree of utility ,”! and by Marshall “ marginal utility.” I Hence the equation just obtained may be expressed: For a given * Cf. Jevons, Pol. Econ ., p . 99. # Marshall, Prin . of Econ. , Preface, p . xiv. Jevons, Ibid ., p. 51. 14 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations purchaser at the time of purchase the quantity of the commodity purchased multiplied by its marginal utility equals the like product for the commodity sold . Or again : for a given purchaser the utili ties of A and B , though actually unequal would be equal if every portion of A (and also of B ) were rated at the same degree of utility as the last infinitesimal. This hypothetical equality underlies, as will subsequently appear, the notion of the equality of values of A and B . § 4. But the two definitions (1) and (2) do not fully determine the sense in which utility is a quantity. To define when the “ grades ” of two parts of a highway are equal or unequal (viz : when they make equal or unequal angles with a horizontal), does not inform us when one shall be twice as steep as the other. It does not oblige us to measure the “ grade ” by the sine of the angle of elevation , or by the tangent, or by the angle itself. If the two highways were inclined at 10° and 20° respectively , the “ grades ” have a ratio of 1.97 if measured by sines, of 2:07 by tangents , and exactly 2 by angles. For a long time philosophers could define and determine when two bodies were equally or unequally hot. But not till the middle of this century * did physicists attach a meaning to the phrase " twice as hot.” It is here especially that exactitude has been hitherto lacking in mathematical economics. Jevons freely confesses that “ We can seldom or never affirm that one pleasure is an exact multiple of another.” + Now throughout Part I the assumption is made that the utility of any one commodity (or service ) depends on the quantity of that commodity or service, but is independent of the quantities of other commodities and services. This assumption is preliminary to the definition we seek . Our first problem is to find the ratio of two infinitesimal utilities. If an individual I consumes 100 loaves of bread in a year the utility of the last infinitesimal, or to fix our ideas, the utility of the last loaf is (presumably) greater than what it would be if he consumed 150 loaves. What is their ratio ? It is found by contrasting the utilities of the 100th and 150th loaves with a third utility. This * The first thermodynamic definition of one temperature as a multiple of another was made by W . Thomson in 1848. See Maxwell, Theory of Heat, p . 155 . 7 p . 13. in the theory of value and prices. 15 third utility is that of oil (say) of which let B gallons be consumed · by I during the year. Let ß be that infinitesimal or small increment of B whose utility shall equal that of the 100th loaf. Now in sub stituting the hypothesis of 150 loaves let us not periit our individ ual to alter B , his consumption of oil.* The utility of the 150th loaf will be pronounced by him equal (say) to the utility of } B. Then the utility of the 150th loaf is said to be half the utility of the 100th . That is, if : ut. of 100th loaf = ut. of B , and ut. of 150th loaf = ut. of B2, the ratio is defined : ut. of 100th loaf B being the total, B being the total again , B ut. of 150th loaf 8 /2 It is essential to observe that if the 100th loaf is twice as useful as the 150th when their ratio is defined as above in terms of incre ments of oil, it will also be twice as usefulwhen the ratio is defined by any other commodity ; also that it matters not what total quan tity ( B ) of oil or other commodity is employed . This theorem may be thus stated : Given (1) ut. of 100th loaf = ut. of B , . B and (2 ) ut. of 150th loaf = ut. of B /2, B also (3) ut. of 100th loaf = ut. of y , C To prove ut. of 150th loaf = ut. of y /2 , C being total, being total, being total, being total, where C is the quantity of another commodity (c) consumed by I in the same period and y is such an increment of C that its utility shall equal that of the 100th loaf. Wemay write from (1) and (3): ut. of 100th loaf = ut. of B = ut. of y , ( 100 loaves, B and C, being totals). Now , if the first total (100 loaves) be changed to 150, B and C being unchanged , the above equation, dropping the firstmember, will still be true, viz : ut. of B = ut. of y , ( 150 loaves, B and C , totals), for, by our preliminary assumption these utilities are independent of the quantity of bread. * As a matter of fact an individual who, if consuming 100 loaves of bread would consume B gallons of oil might, if consuming 150 loaves , use also more oil. But this fact in no wise hinders our inquiring how he would reckon utili ties if he used the same amount. 16 i Irving Fisher — Mathemat ical nvestigations Since B and y are infinitesimal it follows from the mere mathe matical principle of continuity that : ut. of B /2 = ut. of y /2 , (B , C , totals), . : by (2 ) ut. of 150th loaf = ut. of y /2 , (150 loaves, C, totals) Q. E, D. Hence our definition becomes : ut. of 100th loaf y ut. of 150th loafy 2 Likewise : ut. of 100th loaf ut. of 150th loaf = 92 = 2, etc., etc., all of which results harmonize . Since C is any arbitrary quantity it follows that the definition of the above ratio is independent not only of the particular commodity employed as a means of comparison but also of the total quantity of that commodity . It is to be noted here that if the utility of one commodity were dependent on the quantities of others, two applications of the defini tion would yield discordant results.* Wemay state our definition in general terms as follows: ( 3 ) The ratio of two infinitesimal utilities is measured by the ratio of two infinitesimal increments of the same commodity respectively equal in utility to the two utilities whose ratio is required, provided these increments are on the margin of equal finite quantities : In general symbols this becomes : ut. of dA - = n :-- if ut. of dA = ut. of ndM ut. of dB (M total), and ut. of dB = ut. of AM (M also total), where n is any finite number, positive or negative, whole or frac tional. This definition applies not only to infinitesimal utilities of the same commodity (as of the 100th and 150th loaves of bread) but to those of different commodities or services. * We shall afterward see how this affects our notions of utility (Part II, Ch. IV, in the theory of value and prices. $ 5. Definition (3) is perfectly analogous to other mathematical defini tions. To define equality of forces does not fix their proportionality. This property is found in the additional definition : “ The ratio of two forces is the ratio of their mass-accelerations.” Before me chanics was a science, “ force ” stood for a “ common sense ” notion resolvable in the last analysis into a muscular sensation felt in push ing and pulling.* But to construct a positive science, force must be defined with respect to its connection with space, time and mass. So also, while utility has an original “ common sense ” meaning relating to feelings, when economics attempts to be a positive science, it must seek a definition which connects it with objective commodity.t $ 6. (4 ) The marginal utility of a commodity (as implied in § 3) is the limiting ratio of the utility of the marginal increment to themagni tude of that increment. Hence the ratio of two marginal utilities is the ratio of the utilities of two marginal increments divided by the ratio of these increments . If the units of the commodity are small, the marginal utility is practically the utility of the last unit - for bread, of the last loaf, but if this loaf is sliced into 10 parts and these slices have different utilities, the marginal utility of bread is more nearly the utility of the last slice divided by it , and so on ad infinitum . It is now an easy matter to find a unit of utility, the lack of which has been the reproachſ of mathematical economists. The utility of the 100th loaf per year may be regarded as the unit of utility. Or in general: * Spencer, First Principles, p . 169. + Jevons, Marshall, Gossen , and Launhardt, omit indicating in any way what they mean by the ratio of utilities . Yet each of them enabody the idea in their diagrams. Edgeworth (Math . Psych., p . 99) thinks “ just perceivable increments [of pleasure ] are equatable ” and uses this “ minimum sensible ” as a unit in terms of which any pleasure is to be measured (in thought at least). His defini tion and mine show perhaps the very point of departure between psychology and economics. To measure a sensation , theminimum sensible is perhaps the only thinkable method (see Ladd, Physiological Psychology , p . 361). Here the phenomenon is subjective and so is its measure ; while in economics the phe nomena are objective and likewise their measure . † Dr. Ingram , Article : Pol. Econ ., Ency . Brit., xix, 399. TRANS. Conn. ACAD., VOL. VIII. JULY, 1892. Irving Fisher — Mathematical investigations 18 (5 ) The marginalutility of any arbitrarily chosen commodity on the margin of some arbitrarily chosen quantity of that commodity may serve as the unit of utility for a given individual at a given time. This unit may be named a util. Any unit in mathematics is valuable only as a divisor for a second quantity and constant only in the sense that the quotient is constant, that is independent of a third quantity. If we should awaken to -morrow with every line in the universe doubled, we should never detect the change, if indeed such can be called a change, nor would it disturb our sciences or formulæ . $ 7. With these definitions it is now possible to give a meaning to Jevons' utility curve, whose abscissas represent the amounts of a commodity (say bread) which a given individual might consume during a given period and the ordinates, the utilities of the last (i. e. the least useful) loaf. For if corresponding to the abscissa 100 loaves an ordinate of arbitrary length (say one inch ) be drawn to stand for the utility of the 100th loaf, we may use this as a unit (util. For any other abscissa as 85 loaves whose marginal utility is (say) twice the former, the ordinate must be two inches, and so on. For any other commodity as oil the marginal utility of A gallons being contrasted with the utility of the 100th loaf of bread and this ratio being (say) three, an ordinate of three inches must be drawn. In all the curves thus constructed only one ordinate is arbitrarily selected , viz : that representing the utility of the 100th loaf. $ 8. Only differentials of utilities have hitherto been accounted for. To get the total utility of a given amount of bread we sum up the utilities for the separate loaves. Or in general: (6 ) The total utility of a given quantity of a commodity at a given time and for a given individual is the integral of the mar ginal utility times the differential of that commodity. That is : ut. of (x ) = ut. (dx,) + ut. (dxn) + . .. . . + ut. (dan) = S.*ut.(dove) =S in the theory of value and prices. 19 (7 ) The name UTILITY-VALUE of a commodity may be given to the product of the quantity of that commodity by its marginal utility or DU 2 . doc The name is suggested from money-value which is quantity of commodity times its price. (Cf. § 3). (8 ) The GAIN or consumer's rent is total utility minus utility value. That is : Gain = / dU , UA Gain = % de dx – X . die It is the actual total utility diminished by that total utility which the commodity would have if it were all rated at the same degree of utility as the last or least useful increment. It is to be observed that total utility and gain are not experiences in time but the sum of increments of utility substitutionally succes sive. The individual is to assign the marginal utility for the 90th loaf on thehypothesis that hewere consuming 90 loaves per year, and then abandoning this supposition to substitute successively the hy pothesis of 91 loves, 92, 93, etc., all for the same year. That is, a number of mutually exclusive hypotheses for the same period are thought of. $ 9. The preceding definitions have been expressed relative to a par ticular instant of time. This was because in actual life purchases are made by separate instantaneous acts. But the important com modity-magnitudes in economics are “ tons per year,” “ yards per day,” etc., bought, sold , produced , consumed . In order to make our definitions applicable to such quantities the element of timemust be introduced. Hence the following supposition : During the given period of time (that is, the period for which commodity -magnitudes are considered) the marginal utility to a given individual of a given commodity is the same at all instants at which he buys or consumes it or sells or produces it. This involves supposing that prices do not vary, for prices (as we shall see) are proportional to marginal utilities. A housewife buys (say) 10 lbs. of sugar at 10 cts. per pound. As she closes the bargain she roughly estimates that the last or tenth pound is about worth its price. She did not stop at five pounds for she wanted a sixth more than the 10 cts. it cost her. She may not buy sugar again for a fortnight. When she does, we shall suppose 20 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations the price to be the same, so that the last pound she then buys has the same utility as the last pound she previously bought. She may buy fifteen pounds. A fortnight later only five, all depending on her plans for using it. The whole yearly purchase may be 250 lbs. and wemay write : ut. ( 10th 1b .) Jan. 1 = ut. (15th lb .) Jan. 15 . = ut. ( 5th lb .) Jan. 30. = etc. == ut. (250th lb.) for whole year. Thus : The marginal utility of a certain quantity of a commodity for a given period (say a year) is defined to be the marginal utility of that commodity on all occasions during that yeur at which it is bought or consumed , the sum of the individual purchases being the given yearly purchase and consumption . § 10. In the hypothetical case the marginal utility of 250 pounds per year equalled the marginal utility of 10 cts. In the same manner wemay practically estimate the marginal utility of 200 pounds by supposing the price to be such that our housewife would buy 200 pounds. Thus a number of alternative suppositions are made for the same period. By means of these a utility curve can be con structed, one of the coördinates of which is the yearly consumption of sugar. To do this statistically is of course quite a different and more difficult though by no means hopeless proceeding. Curves of this nature are the only ones to be here considered . But it is clear that there also exist utility curves for each time of purchase.* These would differ both from the “ yearly ” curve as well as from each other . $ 11. To meet a possible objection it must be pointed out that the use of a “ yearly ” utility curve assumes no nice calculation on the part of the individual as to his future incomeand receipts. Hemay even be and generally is totally ignorant of the number of pounds of butter he consumes per year. He creeps along from purchase to purchase and only at these individual acts does he estimate his needs and his abilities. Yet if he always completes his purchase with the sameestimate of marginal utility as measured against other com * They would be the curves of Fleeming Jenkin : Graphic Representation of Supply and Demand . Grant's Recess Studies, p . 151, Edinburgh , 1870. in the theory of value and prices. 21 modities , this must be the marginal utility for the year and the total yearly purchase is the quantity which bears this marginal utility. This marginal utility or “ final” degree of utility of the commodity for the year is clearly not the utility of the last amount chrono logically (that is Dec. 31), but the utility of the least useful part of any and each of the separate purchases. $ 12 . It may further be objected that there is a fitful element in the problem which the above supposition ignores. We have supposed prices do not vary during the given period and also that the indi vidual's utility -estimate does not vary . It may justly be claimed that not only do prices vary from day to day, but even if they did not, the individual's estimate of utility is fitful and, although at the instant he closes a bargain his estimate of utility must be regarded as corresponding to the given price, yet he is likely gen erally and certain sometimes to regret his action so that if he were to live the year over again he would act very differently . This objection is a good illustration that a microscopic view often obscures the general broad facts. As a matter of fact the use of a period of time tends to eliminate those very sporadic elements objected to. First, though prices vary from hour to hour under the influence of excitement and changing rumors, and from season to season under causesmeteorological and otherwise, yet these fluctua tions are self-corrective. The general price through the year is the only price which is independent of sporadic and accidental influences. This general price is not the arithmetical mean of the daily prices but a mean defined as such that had it been the constant price during the period the amounts bought and sold would have been just what they actually are. Secondly, the individual caprice is self-correc tive. If a man lays in too large a stock of provisions this week he will buy less next. The theory of probabilities therefore substan . tially harmonizes the theoretical and the actual. The apparently arbitrary suppositions regarding constancy of price, etc., may be looked upon as convenient definitions of an ideal average as just described . One observation however must not be overlooked . Although accidental variations of price or choices of caprice afford both posi tive and negative errors and thus largely cancel each other, yet the effect on the total utility and the gain is always to diminish them . To buy too much or too little, to sell too cheap or too dear will be cal Irving Fisher - Mathemati 22 equally sure to diminish gain. tions investiga Herein lies the virtue of insur ance and the vice of gambling. Neither alters (directly) the amount of wealth. But insurance modifies and gambling intensi fies its fluctuations. Hence the one increases the other decreases gain . $ 13. Again it may be objected to the foregoing definitions that the use of infinitesimals is inappropriate since an individual does not and cannot reckon infinitesimals. The same apparent objection attaches to any application of the calculus. We test forces by weights but cannot weigh infinitesimal masses nor do they probably exist; yet the theory of forces begins in infinitesimals. We apply fluxions to the varying density of the earth , though we know that if we actually take the infinitesimal ratio of mass to volume we shall generally get zero since matter is discontinuous. The pressure of a confined gas is due to collisions of its molecules against the containing vessel. As each molecule rebounds the change of momentum divided by the infinitesimal time is the pressure. Yet at any actual instant the value of this fluxion is quite illusory. But these facts do not mil itate against the use of fluxions for a thinkable theory of forces, density and gaseous pressure . In cases of discontinuity fluxions have important applications though infinitesimals may not exist . The rate of increase of population at a point in time is an impor tant idea, but what does it mean ? It is convenient to define it as infinitesimal increase of population divided by the infinitesimal time of that increase though we know that population increases discon tinuously by the birth of whole individuals and not of infinitesimals. Practically we can find the approximate marginal utility of a commodity just as we approximately find the rate of increase of population by taking small increments in place of infinitesimals. In actual fact inequality of utilities is the rule and absolutely equal utilities never exist. Instead of a curve of utility we should draw a belt (fig . 1) whose limits are ill-defined and whose width in general depends on the amount of antecedent atten tion which the individual has bestowed on the alternative amounts and modes of consumption . in the theory of value and prices. 23 $ 14. Utility as defined in the preceding sections does not involve the economist in controversy as to the laws of the subjective states of pleasure and pain , the influence of their anticipation as connected with their probabilities,* the vexed questions whether they differ in quality as well as in intensity and duration, whether duty can or cannot exist as a motive independently of pleasure, etc . It does not follow that these discussions have no meaning or im portance . Doubtless pleasure and pain are connected with desire and doubtless they have an important biological and sociological function as registering “ healthful” or “ pathological” conditions. But the economist need not envelop his own science in the hazes of ethics, psychology, biology and metaphysics. Perhaps utility is an unfortunate word to express the magnitude intended. Desirability|| would be less misleading, and its opposite , undesirability is certainly preferable to dis -utility. “ Utility ” is the heritage of Bentham and his theory of pleasures and pains. For us his word is the more acceptable, the less it is entangled with his theory. $ 15. This chapter may be thus summarized : Postulate : Each individual acts as he desires. Definitions of utility . (2) and (1) ut. of A ? ut. of B if the given indiv. at the given time prefers A to B or neither. ut. of dA ut. of dB = if ut.ofdA = ut. of ndM ( M total) and ut. of dB = ut. of dM (M also total). du JA = Marginal utility . AU = Unit of utility (util.) (A being given). + Jevons, p . 28, etc. * Jevons, p . 72. † Darwin , Descent Man , I, p . 76 , Sidgwick , Methods Ethics, Ch . IV . § Marshall, Prin . of Econ., p. 181, Spencer, Data of Ethics, p. 79 , L . Stephen , Science of Ethics, p. 366 . | Marshall, Prin . of Econ., p. 306. 24 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations CA du - . dA = Total utility. A du pAdU dA - A dAdA - A '° Assumption : Corrollaries : From . JA . = Utility-value. = Gain . dU NA = Function of A only. (1) and (2) and postulate , when B is ex changed for A U B : B , DdU ddU CdA · A . From (3) and assumption , in the equation : ut. of dA /ut. of dB = n , the value of n is independent of the particular commodity and of its quantity M used in the definition. CHAPTER II. MECHANISM . $ 1. Scarcely a writer on economics omits to make some comparison between economics and mechanics . One speaks of a “ rough cor respondence” between the play of “ economic forces ” and mechan ical equilibrium . Another compares uniformity of price to the level seeking of water. Another (Jevons) compares his law of exchange to that of the lever. Another (Edgeworth ) figures his economic “ system ” as that of connected lakes of various levels. Another compares society to a plastic mass such that a “ pressure” in one region is dissipated in all “ directions.” In fact the economist bor rowsmuch of his vocabulary from mechanics. Instances are : Equi librium , stability, elasticity, expansion, inflation, contraction, flow , efflux, force, pressure, resistance, reaction, distribution (price ), levels, movement, friction . The student of economics thinks in terms of mechanics far more than geometry, and a mechanical illustration corresponds more fully to his antecedent notions than a graphical one. Yet so far as I know , no one has undertaken a systematic representation in terms of me chanical interaction of that beautiful and intricate equilibrium which manifests itself on the “ exchanges ” of a great city but of which the causes and effects lie far outside. in the theory of value and prices. 25 $ 2. In order to simplify our discussion the following preliminary sup positions* are made : (1) A single isolated market large enough to prevent one man's consciously influencing prices. (2) A given period , say a year. (3) During this period the rate of production and consumption are equal and such that stocks left over from last year and stocks held over for next may have an influence which is unvarying or which is not a function of quantities produced and consumed during the year. Their influence is accounted for in the form of the curves to be employed just as is the influence of climate, population, polit ical conditions, etc. (4 ) Each individual in themarket knows all prices, acts freely and independently and preserves the same characteristics during the period , so that the forms of his utility curves do not change. (5 ) All articles considered are infinitely divisible and each man free to stop producing and consuming at any point. (6 ) The marginal utility of consuming each commodity decreases as the amount consumed increases, and themarginal disutility of pro ducing each commodity increases as the amount produced increases. (7) As stated in Chapter 1, § 4, the utility of each commodity is independent of the quantities of other commodities and likewise for disutility . $ 3. In fig. 2 let the curve MN be drawn with axes OE and OA. This curve is such that the shaded area represents any amount of the given commodity consumed by the given individual in the given period of time, and the ordinate (drawn downward) from OtoR represents its marginal utility. The figure evidently interprets the fact thatas the quantity of commodity increases its marginal utility de creases and vice versa . t OA indicates what the marginalutility would be if only an infinitesimal quantity of the commodity were consumed. Furthermore let a glass cistern (fig. 2) be formed having the figure OAMN for its front Af - -- - - --- -- - * These are (essentially) those of Auspitz und Lieben . + For the further properties of the curve MN and its relation to the curves of Jevons, Auspitz und Lieben and Fleeming Jenkin , see Appendix I, Division II . 26 cal Irving Fisher - Mathemati ions investigat face and a uniform thickness of unity so that the volume of liquid contained is always equal numerically to the area on the face. Hence the amount of liquid in the cistern may represent commodity and the distance of its surface from 0 , its marginal utility . ONE COMMODITY (A )- ONE CONSUMER (I). Let fig. 2 represent the utility cistern for I relative to A . Let us select as a unit of utility themarginal utility of money supposing this to be constant. Thus the cistern is (say) one inch in thickness ; the number of cubic inches of water represents the number of units of the commodity ( yards, gallons, or pounds, etc.) consumed by the individual during a given period (say a year) and the ordinate OR (in inches ) represents the number of dollars at which the individual prizes the last yard or gallon ( say) of the commodity. Since the market is large enough to prevent any conscious influ ence on the price by the individual I, he acts with reference to a fixed price ( p dollars ). He will therefore consume such an amount of A that its marginal utility in dollars equals that of the price P, that is, the cistern will be filled till OR = p . This is evident, for if less should be consumed OR would be greater than p , that is, a little more commodity would be valued more highly than the dollars exchanged for it and so would be purchased , and if more should be consumed , reverse considerations hold . If the price rises OR will increase and less be consumed but if it falls, more. If the price falls to zero as is the case for water and air the quantity consumed fills the whole cistern up to the horizontal axis. This volume is therefore the quantity ofmaximum satisfaction . If the price rises to OA the individual will cease consuming. This price is therefore the limiting maximum price at which he will buy. The liquid contents of the cistern may be regarded as made up of successive horizontal infinitesimal layers each representing an incre ment of commodity. The height or distance of each layer from the origin represents the degree of utility of that layer. The last or top layer is on the margin of the whole and its vertical distance from the origin is the degree of utility of that marginal layer or incre ment of the commodity or briefly its marginal utility . Thus the margin of consumption has in the cistern an actual physical analogue. in the theory of value and prices. $ 5. ONE COMMODITY -ONE PRODUCER . The definitions of utility in Chapter I apply also to negative util ity or disutility . Corresponding to all that has been said relative to consumption are analagous remarks for production. 3. Thus wemay construct a disutility curve and cisterna (fig. 3) marginal disutility (O R ) being measured a upward from the origin . If utility be measured in money as in the last section , O A represents the minimum price at which the individual will produce the commodity, O R the current price and the shaded area (or the cubic contents behind it ) the output. LE The marginal disutility of production is here represented as de creasing as the amount of the product increases. “ law of diminishing returns.” This assumes a It is true that this law is seldom if ever rigorously true when applied to small amounts ; that is, the cost or disutility of producing the first unit is not less but greater than that of producing the second. But the marginal disutility con tinues to decrease only up to a certain point, after which it increases. This is usually true even of manufacturing. American bicycle fac tories are now running behind their orders. If they attempted to run their factories at a higher velocity the cost of the additional product would become greater than its price. In general at the actual rate at which a concern produces, the law of increase of dis utility applies. It would be possible by looping the curve MN near the bottom to make a cistern of such a form as to represent correctly both the law of decrease and increase , but as we are chiefly concerned with the point of equilibrium and as at equilibrium the law of increase usually applies such complicated curves are not here drawn . If a producer has such a productive capacity as to consciously in fluence prices by a variation of his product, he may find his maxi mum gain by restricting his output even at a point where the law of decreasing disutility applies ; for if he should extend his production, his price might decrease faster than his cost. These considerations together with the important one that in a productive enterprise the expenses are classified as " fixed ” and “ running,” make many interesting cases of instability and indeter minateness and lead to the discussion of monopolies, combinations, rate wars, etc., etc. These each require special analysis. In the 28 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations present memoir, however, attention is confined to those features of production which are strictly analogous to consumption. (See Ap pendix II, § 8 .) $ 6. ONE COMMODITY - MANY CONSUMERS. Let fig. 4 represent the utility cisterns for all individuals I, II, WWWWWW III, IV, . . . N , in the market and let utility be measured in money as before,the marginal utility of money being considered constant (say 1 util.). The water in the connecting tubes (represented by oblique shad ing) does not stand for commodity. The water will seek its own level. This is exactly what happens in the economic world and may be stated in the theorem : A given amount of commodity to be consumed by a market during a given period will be so distributed among the individuals thatthe marginal utilities measured in money will be equal. Furthermore the margi nal utility thus determined will be the price. This follows, for there can be but one price , and each individual will make his marginal utility equal to it, as shown in $ 4. If the stopper,* S, be pressed; more liquid (commodity ) flows into the cisterns, there is an inevitable change in level and the price de creases. When it cheapens to 2, IIbegins to indulge. It is for the first time “ within his reach .” It is to be noted that from the standpoint of a single individual the existence of the general price level is an unalterable fact and the amount which he consumes is accommodated to it, just as the gen eral water level in several hundred cisterns may be said to determine * A rubber compression ball would be used in practice. Throughout the de scriptions, the mechanisms are those simplest to delineate and in many cases not those which might be actually employed. in the theory of value and prices. 29 the amount in any particular cistern . But, for the system as a whole, the price level is a consequence of the amount of commodity marketed. What appears as cause in relation to effect to an indi vidual is effect in relation to cause for the whole market. The quantities of commodity and the marginal utilities mutually limit and adjust themselves, subject to three conditions, (1) that due to the forms of cisterns, (2) that due to the total amount of commod ity marketed, (3) uniformity of price, or of marginal utility . $ 7. ANALYTICAL The algebraic interpretation of the preceding mechanism or of the economic phenomena themselves is as follows : Let A ,, A ,, A ,, . . . An be the (as yet unknown) quantities of the 3 commodity consumed by I, II, III, . . . N . Let DU DU dA ' MA,' DU .. DA, be their (unknown) marginal utilities. Then the three conditions mentioned in § 6 become: (The unit of utility (util.) is that of themarginal dollar.) GU IN = F,(A,) ? JA = F,(A,). |n equations. 2 n unknowns. au =F.(A.) J on . K ſnoequati A , + A , + A , + . . .. + A , =- K11 new unknowns. (Unit of utility is that of marginal dollar.) dU M dU dU in - 1 independent equations dA = A JA, .. . . A, S no new unknowns. Hence the number of equations is : n + 1 + (n - 1) = 2n and of unknowns : 2n + 0 + 0 = 2n . Therefore the numbers of equations and unknowns are equal and all quantities and utilities are determinate . 30 Irving Fisher-- Mathematical investigations 30 $ 8. AGGREGATE COMMODITY. Let C , fig . 4,be the average curve* of all the individual curves, I, II, III, . . . . N , and let the new cistern have a thickness equal to the sum of the thicknesses of the individual cisterns. Then asmuch water will be in the aggregate cistern as in all the others.* The water in the aggregate cistern may be regarded as a repetition of the con tents of the individual cisterns. It represents no new commodity. In cistern C it is almost too evident to require mention that an in creased supply of this commodity (indicated by pressing the stopper) reduces the price while a diminished supply increases it. This fact is all that is usually exhibited in “ demand curves” such as of Fleeming Jenkin . $ 9. Fig. 5 and completely analogous explanations apply to production cisterns. lom * Formed as follows : Select pts. of like price on the individual curves, that is, pts. of like ordinates (as Yı, ya, y3, . . . Yn ) and using the same ordinate for the new ordinate, take the average of their abscissas for the new abscissa and make the thickness of the new cistern equal to the sum of the thicknesses of all the in dividual cisterns. Then if in such a cistern liquid be allowed to flow to the level of the individual cisterns the amount of liquid contained in it will equal all that contained in the individual cisterns. For evidently the free surface of the water in the large cistern equals in area the total free surfaces in the small, and as such equality of horizontal infinitesimal layers or laminæ holds true at all successive levels, it holds true of the sums of the layers. + The Graphic Representation of Supply and Demand . Grant's recess studies , p . 151. in the theory of value and prices. 37 $ 10 . The mechanism above described simply gives exactness to a com mon imagery in economics, such as “ margin ," " price levels," “ planes” of demand (and supply) and : “ a plentiful supply brings the commodity within reach ' of consumers." The notion of a cistern is also natural. Says Adam Smith : “ The demand for food is limited by the capacity of a man's stomach .” Not only is there a “ limit,” but the demand for food has varying intensities according to the degree in which the stomach is filled. The economic man is to be regarded as a number of cisterns or stomachs, each relative to a particular commodity. CHAPTER III. ONE CONSUMER (OR PRODUCER )--MANY COMMODITIES. $ 1. The next problem is that of the distribution of an individual's in come over all the commodities in the market . The income-spender considers not only the price of a given article in determining how much of that article he will take but also the relative advantages of using the samemoney for other things. The manner in which this consideration affects the mechanism de scribed in Chapter II is through the utility of money.* In the last chapter, while the price varied in relation to the quan tity of commodity, each individual's valuation or marginal utility ofmoney was regarded as constant. This is nearly true when only one commodity is considered. In the present chapter, on the other hand , the individual valuation of money varies in relation to the quantity ofmoney income, butthe prices of all commodities are re garded as constant. This is nearly true when only one individual is considered . * This sort of interaction, especially when extended to several consumers and several commodities (as in the next chapter), presented the most difficulties to the Auspitz und Lieben Analysis ; on p . 63 in $ 16 they say : “ Welche Aende i rung eine Einzelkurve erleidet wenn sich die Vermögensverhältnisse des be treffenden Individuumsändert, lässt sich im allgemeinen nicht verfolgen . Wenn auch in der Regel die Ordinaten der kurven länger werden , wenn das Individuum wolhabender wird , so wird dies doch keineswegs gleichmässig der Fall sein, vol · lends nicht, wenn wir verschiedene Artikel betrachten ." Irving Fisher — Mathematical investigations $ 2. Let the individual I distribute his income over the commodities A , B , C , . . . . . M . Let the thickness of each cistern in fig . 6 be proportional to the price of the commodity it contains. Thus if A bears a price of $2 per yard, B $ 1 per gallon and C $ t per pound, the thickness of cistern B is 2, of B 1, and of Ct. IIIIII AUW PETENCE Let the unit of area on the front surface of each cistern represent a unit of commodity , yards for A , gallons for B , etc . Then the volume of liquid will evidently indicate themoney value of the commodity , for it equals the front area times the thickness, that is, the quantity of commodity times its price. Moreover the sum of all the water will indicate the whole * income in dollars. The unit of volume thus represents not a yard, gallon, pound, etc ., but a dollar's worth in each case. For A it would be } yard , for B 1 gallon, for C 2 lbs., etc . Accordingly let the curves which limit the cisterns be so con structed that the ordinates shall represent marginal utility per dollar's worth not per yard , gallon , etc. $ 3. The liquid will seek its own level corresponding to the economic proposition : A consumer will so arrange his consumption that the marginal utility per dollar 's worth of each commodity shall be the same. * Saving is here regarded as a form of spending, the commodity purchased being capital. The analysis implies that the marginal utility of saving a dollar equals the marginal utility of the dollar spent in other ways. This would be elaborated from another standpoint in a theory of distribution . Cf. Launhardt ; Volkswirthschaftslehre; Böhm -Bawerk ; Kapital und Kapitalzins. 33 • in the theory of value and prices. This follows because if the individual should vary his consumption . from such a distribution, by expending an extra dollar on A he would divert that amount from another article or articles, say B . Then the level in the A cistern would be higher than in the B , which interpreted , is the dollar spent on A had less utility than if it had been devoted to B . If the stopper be pressed , i. e. if the individual had had a larger income, the valuation of the last dollar's worth of each commodity decreases, or themarginal utility of money decreases. If it becomes at the maximum marginal utility of B he begins to spend on B. As it is in the figure he “ cannot afford it.” The amount spent on any particular commodity depends on the general water level, i.e. the valuation of a dollar, while reversely the valuation of money depends on the total amountto be spent on all commodities. Three conditions suffice to make the distribution determinate : (1) that due to the forms of the cisterns, (2) the condition that the total income equals a specified amount, (3 ) uniformity of marginal utility (per dollar's worth ) of each commodity . $ 4. ANALYTICAL Let A , B , C , . . . M be the (unknown) quantities of various com dU dU modities consumed by 1, and ini . . . . JM their (unknown) mar ginal utilities. Let Pa, Po, . . . Pm be their (known ) prices. Then the above three conditions become : ( The unit of commodity is the dollar's worth .) I DU dA = F(A) dU . = F (B ) | m equations. (1) · · : | 2m unknowns . AM = F(M ) (2) Ape+ Bpo + . . . . +Mpm = K —no new unknowns. Trans. Conn. ACAD., Vol. VIII. , - JULY, 1892. 34 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations (Unit of commodity is dollar's worth.) DU NU Im - 1 independent equation . (3) QA = dB = . . . = M no new unknowns. Number of equations = m + 1 + m - 1 = 2m . I AU 66 - unknowns = 2m + 0 + 0 Hence the system is determinate. = 2m . AGGREGATE INCOME. Let I, fig. 6, be the average curve* of all the separate commodity curves A , B , C , . . , M , and let the new cistern have a thickness equal to the sum of the thicknesses of the original cisterns. Then the water in the resultant cistern equals the sum of that in the com ponents.* The liquid in the new cistern represents the money collectively considered and the ordinate the utility of the last dollar. If this income increases, its marginal utility decreases and de creases in a law whose relation to the laws of utility for the separate commodities is shown by the relation of the resultant cistern to the components. * In this case the average is not a simple arithmetical mean but a weighted average. Select points of like utility on the component curves, that is, points of equal ordinates . Average their abscissas, multiplying each by the ratio of the thickness of its cistern to that of the resultant cistern (viz : the sum of the thick nesses of the original cisterns). Thus if the thicknesses are p , P ., . . . Pon and the abscissas xq, xg,. . . xm, the resulting thickness and abscissa (P and X ) are : P = P, + P8 + . . . + Pm 2 ,2 , + X, P, + . . . + xm P. X = 1 Pc + Pr + . . . + P.m If in a cistern thus formed liquid enters to the level of the component cisterns, the liquid in the resultant cistern equals the total in the component. For the sum of the free surfaces in the component cisterns is X ,P , + X7P8 + . . . + xmp m and the free surface in the resultant is ( PQ + P , + . . . + 2 ) . MaPa + 3 , P , + . . . + a in p m I Pe + P + . . . + Pm Since these two expressions are equal and this equality holds of infinitesimal layers at the free surface and so successively at all levels it must hold of the sums of these layers. in the theory of value and prices. 35 $ 6. An analogous discussion applies to fig. 7. In place of a given in come wemust suppose a given amount of expenses to bemet by the production of various commodities.* It is at this point that an im portant distinction between production and consumption enters, viz : in civilized life men find it advantageous to consume many things but to produce few . The discussion of this difference pertains to Part II. CHAPTER IV . M COMMODITIES – N CONSUMERS (OR PRODUCERS). $ 1. We have seen the laws of distribution of commodities from two points of view , by first restricting our discussion to one commodity among many consumers and afterward to one consumer among many commodities. Our discussion is like a tourist's view of a great city , who glances up each east and west street while riding along the same avenue and then takes a “ cross town ” course and sees each avenue from a single street. We are now to seek a bird's-eye view . The variables and their variations which have been described are comparatively simple. But the possible variations in the more gen eral case are so complicated that they can scarcely be seen or de scribed without the aid of a mechanism . * Borrowing capital is to be here regarded as a form of producing. The dis utility of borrowing the last dollar equals the disutility of producing the last dollar's worth of goods. See foot note to $ 2. Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations 36 $ 2. First of all an analysis will serve to set the two preceding discus sions in a common point of view . In any purchase the last infinitesimal commodity bought has a utility equal to that of the money given , that is : ut. of dA = ut. of dm or : au da = a...Am du or : (see Ch. I, § 3 .) du dm JA = dm .da du _ dU or : dA = dm . Pa where pa is the money price . That is, the marginal utility of a commodity (per pound, yard, etc.) equals the marginal utility of money (per dollar) times the ratio of exchange of money for commodity : This equation is fundamental. · In our first discussion (one com modity, various consumers) the marginal utility of money was sup posed constant so that AU dA « Pa or the marginal utility of a commodity is measured by it price. In the second discussion the other factor, the price, was supposed constant, and : dU dU dA " dm or the marginal utility is measured by the valuation of money. § 3. In the present chapter we are restricted to neither of these special suppositions. For the individual I, we may write du du A = dm , .Pa au du dB, – dm , .Po . . . .. . .. . . . d [ _ «U . dm = dm , Pm 37 in the theory of value and prices. whence, since the marginal utility of money to I is the same in each case, dU AU dU da, " ĀB, : .. . . īm . = PaiPoi. .. .Pm Since this is true for every individual and the prices to all individ uals are the same, wemay write : du dU MU . . . . Pa : Po : . . . . Pm = • ' dM DU = . .... dU dUdU = da . : dB. : . .. . M. These equations express in the most general way the theory of marginal utilities in relation to prices. This theory is rot, as some times stated, “ the marginal utilities to the same individual of all articles are equal,” much less is it “ the marginal utilities of the same article to all consumers are equal,” but : The marginal utilities of all articles consumed by a given individual are proportional to the marginal utilities of the same series of articles for each other con sumer, and this uniform continuous ratio is the scale of prices of those articles. The idea of equality is inadequate and must be replaced by the idea of proportionality. The problem which confronts the individ ual must be figured as to so adjust his consumption of all commodi ties that the utilities of the last pound, yard , gallon , etc., shall bear the ratio which he finds their prices do, while the market as a whole must cause such prices to emerge as will enable each individual to solve this problem and at the same time just take off the supply. $ 4. This notion of a ratio is introduced into the following more com plicated mechanism (fig . 8 ). Fig. 9 (an elevation of fig . 8 ) shows the various cisterns of various commodities for the individual I. The ordinates represent marginal utility per unit of commodity . It corresponds to fig . 6 , except that in the latter the utility is per dollar'sworth of commodity. The tops of the cisterns are no longer at the same level. The cisterns are now to float like boats in a 38 Irving Fisher— Mathematical investigations 8. MIN I . IA пс | TOWN s imdainlai wun an do in the theory of value and prices. 39 9. キ こニ こ ここ こ ここ にこ ここ M 1 TA IB tank* and free to move only vertically (being so constrained by a telescope arrangement beneath and not shown in the diagram ). A glance at fig . 8 or fig . 10 . 10 (a plan of fig . 8 ) will show that any right and left row of cisterns is rela tive to a single individual and corresponds to fig . 6 and thatany front and back row is relative to a single commodity and corresponds to fig. 4. The water in these cis terns must be subjected to two sets of conditions, first: the sum of all the contents of IA , IIA , IIIA , etc., shall be a given amount (viz : the whole of the commod ity A consumed during the given period) with a like given sum for the B row , C row , etc., secondly : the sum of IA , IB , IC , etc., each multiplied by a coeffi cient (the price of A , of B , of C , etc.), shall be given (viz: the whole income of I during the period ),with a like given sum for the II row , III row , etc. * The level of water in each cistern is intended to be that of the level in the tank. The only constant cause which will makethe levels different is the differ ence between the weight of the whole cistern and the weight of the water dis placed by its walls (partly wood) which difference is slight, may be plus or minus, and is equal to the weight of the excess or deficit of water in the cistern above or below the outside level. 40 Irving Fisher — Mathematical investigations To realize these two sets of conditions each cistern is divided into two by a vertical partition of wood. The frontcompartments are all of unit thickness one inch (say). All front compartments belonging to the same front-and -back row are mutually connected by tubes (in the tank but not in connection with the water of the tank ) thus ful filling the first set of conditions. The thickness of the back compartments is adjustable but is (as will soon appear) constrained to be always equal to the price, thus if the price of A is $ 1, of B $ 3 and C $ 1.20, the thickness of all cisterns in the A row will be 1, in the B row 3 and in the Crow 1.2 (inches). Since the thickness of the front compartment is unity, the con tents of each back compartment equals the contents of the front multiplied by the number of inches of thickness of the back cistern, that is the back compartment contains a volume of water equal to the amount of the commodity multiplied by its price. . It contains therefore the money value of the commodity. The double cistern represents the double light in which each commodity is commonly regarded — so many pounds, yards, etc. and so many dollar's worth . All back compartments of the same right and left rows are mutually connected by tubes — that is the sum of their contents is given — thus fulfilling the second set of conditions. The back compartments can change their thicknesses, as the walls at the right, left and bottom are of flexible leather; the back plane is kept parallel to the wood partition by two double “ parallel rules” not diagramed . There remains to be described the system of levers. The purpose of these levers is to keep the continuous ratio of marginal utilities, the same for all individuals and equal to the ratio of prices. First there is a system of oblique* levers (F12, etc., fig. 9 ) con nected by sliding pivots with the tops of the cisterns and having their lower extremities hinged to wooden floats F , the hinges being on the level of the water of the tank. These floats are free only to shift laterally . It is evident from the similar triangles FR1 and FR2 in fig . 9 that the ordinates of the two cisterns IA and IB are proportional to the distances of the A and B rods R and K from the hinge in the left float F . Likewise in the row behind , the ordi nates are proportional to the same distances. Hence the four ordinates are proportional to each other and in general all the -- - -- - -- -- - - - - - - - - -- - - - --- * A convenient angle for each lever can be assured by a careful selection of commodity units. Thus if the marginal utility per pound gives inconvenient ordinates in the A row , reconstruct the cisterns in that row so that the ordinates are lengthened to represent marginal utility per ton or shortened for the ounce . in the theory of value and prices. 41 ordinates of the front row are proportional to those of the row next behind , also of the second row behind and so on . Remembering that each ordinate is a marginal utility we have: . du du du du du du da , ' dB, . . . = da . : dB . : . . . = A : B : . . . = . . which is the required condition that marginal utilities must be pro portional (83). Secondly there are the horizontal levers (F34, etc., fig. 10 ) lying on the surface of the water in the tank. These relate to prices. The sliding pivots 3, 4, etc. are connected with rods RRR , which in turn are connected by vertical pins with the rear walls of the cisterns. A motion of one of these rods causes all back compart ments in that row to expand or shrink in unison. The pivots 3, 4, etc . are so situated on these rods that if the levers F34, etc. should assume a right-and-left position along the dotted line FF , the back compartment of every cistern would be completely closed. Hence R3 equals the thickness of each back compartment in the A row , R4 the corresponding thickness in the B row and so on. By the similar triangles FR3 and F :34 in fig . 10, it is clear that the lines R3 and R4, and consequently the rear thickness in the A and Brows are proportional to the distances of the A and B rods R and R from the float F . But we have just seen that the ordinates of IA and IB are proportional to these samedistances. Hence the thicknesses of the back compartments of the cisterns are propor. tional to the ordinates of those cisterns, that is to marginal utilities. Hence we are free to call the thickness of each back compartment, the money* price of the commodity to which that cistern relates. - - - - -- - -- -- - - - -- * Money is here used solely as a measure of value. It is not one of the com modities in the market. The high or low price of commodities in terms of this money is dependent entirely on the amount of it at which we agree to rate the yearly consumption of the market , that is the amount of liquid originally in the back cisterns. We are so accustomed to regard money as the medium of exchange and therefore as a commodity that we may not observe that it is per fectly possible to have a measure of value which is not a commodity at all. Thus wemight agree to call the consumption of the United States for a year $ 10 ,000, 000,000, and this agreementwould immediately fix a measure of value, though the new dollar need bave no equality to the gold or silver dollar. It would be easy to translate between such an arbitrary standard and any commodity standard. Thus if statistics showed that the consumption measured in gold dollars was $ 12,000 ,000 ,000 , the agreed standard is at 120 compared with gold and by means of this factor we can reduce the prices of all commodities. In the mechanism the aggregate amount of liquid in the back cisterns corresponds to the $ 10 ,000 , 000,000. If we take it so and if the amount of liquid in the I row is given at $ 1,000, this means that (in whatever standard ) the consumption of I is one-ten millionth in value the aggregate consumption . 42 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations It is to be observed that the cisterns are free to move only verti cally , the rods and rear cistern walls only forward and backward , the wooden floats can shift only sidewise right and left while the levers assume such positions as the mechanism compels. $5. Let given quantities of water be introduced into each front-and back -row of front cisterns and into each right-and-left row of back cisterns. The system will attain a stable equilibrium and the level of water in each cistern will be that of the tank . The front cisterns of a front-and-back row must have a uniform level on account of their mutual connection. The back cisterns of a right-and-left row must preserve a uniform level for a similar rea son . The movable rear walls allow the pressure of the outside water in the tank to keep the back cisterns at the samelevel as the front. Without taking account of the levers the cisterns would thus all have the same level as the tank . But it would be possible to arrange their vertical positions and their rear thicknesses in many arbitrary ways. The levers simply specify or determine this arrange ment. $ 6. It may be needful to restate carefully the magnitudes, their units and the conditions which determine them . The magnitudes are : 1. The quantities of each commodity consumed by each individual during the year. These are represented by the quantities of water in each front compartment. 2. The given total quantities of each commodity consumed by the whole market — represented by the fixed amount of water in each front and back row of front comparments and registered on scales* A , B , C , at the rear of the tank. Each commodity-water may have a distinguishing color. 3. Themoney paid for each commodity by each individual— rep resented by the water in each back compartment. 4. The total money income of each individual— represented by the fixed amount of water in each right-and-left row of back com partments, and registered on scalest I, II, III, at the right of the tank . * The stoppers A B , C regulate this amount of water. The stoppers are each directly connected with the pointers on the scales A , B, C , and so arranged that when the stopper is withdrawn so that the scale reads zero, the water entirely disappears from the cisterns. + The stoppers I, II, III are also directly connected with pointers on the scales I, II, III. 43 in the theory of value and prices. 5. The marginal utility of each commodity to each individual — represented by the ordinate of each cistern, i. e. by the distance from its top to the water level. 6 . The money price of each commodity — represented (in any cistern in the same front-and-back -row ) by the thickness of the back compartment, and registered on scales* Pa, Po, P. at the rear. (The relation of price to marginal utility will recur.) 7. The prices of commodities in terms of each other — represented by the ratios of their ordinates. 8. The marginal utility of money to each individual — repre sented (in any cistern in the same right-and -left-row ) by the ratiot of the ordinate of that cistern to the thickness of its back compartment 11. and registered on scalesI UI, U JI, U III at the right. The units of these magnitudes are : 1. The unit of commodity is a ton, yard, gallon , etc., and is repre sented by (say) a cubic inch of water. 2. The unit of money is (say) a dollar and is represented by (say) a cubic inch of water . 3. The unit of price is one dollar per ton , yard, gallon, etc., and is represented by one inch . 4. The unit of marginal utility for each individual is the marginal utility of (say ) 100 tons of A . It may be called a util and by a proper * The rodsRRR are each connected by a cord and pulley with the pointers of the scales p . , P . , P . . + This ratio is evidently the marginal utility of money (“ valuation ofmoney ?) dU because as seen in chapter IV, 82, QU da = dm • Pa dU dU whence : dA dm – P ordinate of cistern thickness of its back compartment Fig . 11 (which views the outside of the right wall of the tank) shows the device by which this is accomplished. Evidently from the labels dU xdA dU ī = p or x = dm The pointer obviously varies with x. It is so arranged as to register zero when c = 0. Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations adjustment of the breadth of each cistern may be represented by one inch . That is, if 100 cu. in . of water are put in each A cistern the ordinate must be one inch. This applies as well to the utility of money, so that the scale U at the left indicates the number of utils at which the individual values the last dollar of his income. It should , however , be noted that the variation of utils is only valuable in the same register , that is, for the same individual. There is no important meaning attached to the ratio of the scale readings U for two individuals. If that of I is 1 and of II 2 it means simply that II values his last dollar twice asmuch as his 100th ton of A , while I values his last dollar just asmuch as his 100th ton of A . It is in teresting to observe that analogously the price registers are not to be compared, for while one indicates price per ton the other indicates price per yard, etc. Thus the mechanism is independent of any common measure of utility for different individuals and any common measure of prices for different commodities. $ 7. It will be observed that the numbers on the various registers are so connected that the product of the register of A by that of its price added to the like products for B, C, etc., will equal the sum : of all the income registers. Moreover if each cistern is provided with a graduation to show marginal utility, this number will be found to be the product of the number for price in its front-and-back row , by that for valuation of money in its right-and -left row . $ 8. The mechanism just described is the physical analogue of the ideal economic market. The elements which contribute to the determination of prices are represented each with its appropriate rôle and open to the scrutiny of the eye. We are thus enabled not only to obtain a clear and analytical picture of the interdependence of the many elements in the causation of prices, but also to employ the mechanism as an instrument of investigation and by it, study some complicated variations which could scarcely be successfully followed without its aid . Its chief uses may be briefly classified as follows : 1. Arrange the stoppers I, II, III, etc ., so that the money incomes of I, II, III, are all equal. The differences of distribution of the commodities will depend on individual characteristics, that is, on in the theory of value and prices. 45 the character of the cisterns. If all the A cisterns are alike and also all B cisterns, all C cisterns, etc., then each commodity will be distributed in equal parts among the individuals. 2. Press stopper I. This amounts to increasing the income of I. It does not increase the amount of commodities in the market but gives a larger share to I. The total money value of the same aggre gate commodities in the whole market has increased by the amount of liquid added by depressing the stopper. The added water in the back cisterns of the I row will make the back compartments in this row fuller than the front. The back level will be temporarily above the water level of the tank and (as the cisterns will sink) the front level will be temporarily below . The effect of the former is to bulge out the movable rear wall in the I row , to extend the rods and to cause the same expansion in the back compartments of the II, III, etc. rows. This makes the back liquids in these rows lower and the front liquids higher than the tank level. Hence the front cisterns of the II, III, etc . rows pour part of their contents into the I row whose level as we have seen is below that of the tank . In economic language to give a greater money value to one indi vidual causes for him smaller marginal utilities (cisterns sink ), a lower marginal utility of money, and increased consumption of com modities. For other individuals it increases marginal utilities (cis terns rise), decreases consumption , increases prices (back cisterns 'expand), and may increase or decrease their marginal utility of money-income according as marginal utilities (ordinates) increase faster than prices (back thicknesses) or the reverse. So much for the effect on different individuals. Now as to the effect on the various commodities. Prices in general have risen but not necessarily of all articles. Suppose article C is consumed little or not at all (cistern narrow ) by the enriched individual I but is ex tensively used by those whose valuation of money has increased . Then since the valuation of money to II is equal to the quotient of the ordinate of IIC divided by the thickness of the back cistern of IIC, and since this ordinate has not lengthened by any appreciable loss of commodity C from II to I,the thickness must have lessened, that is, the price has been reduced. Not only may there be such exceptional commodities but there may be exceptional individuals. Thus a man may be the principal consumer of just those commodities and those only whose price has fallen. His consumption will increase,his marginal utility ofmoney 46 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations decrease. He is benefited not injured by the increase of income of his neighbor I. 3. Press stopper I and raise III. I, II, III now represent a wealthy middle class and poor man respectively . We observe first that this change causes the poor man to relinquish entirely some things (luxuries) as C while decreasing his necessaries slightly ; second that the rich man increases his luxuries enormously and his necessaries slightly, and thirdly that slight modifications will appear in the prices and hence in the middle-class consumption. The nature of the effect on prices depends on the character of the cisterns of I and III, and on themagnitude of the changes in their incomes. In order that prices may not change, one condition (neces sary but not sufficient) is that the amount of money income added to I must equal that taken from III, for if the amounts of com modities are not to change, nor their prices, their totalvalues cannot. If all prices rise it proves a net increase of money income in the whole system . If the increase of income of I equals the decrease of that of III, so that the total money value in the market is unchanged , and if furthermore all the cisterns of I and III have straight walls on the right and have their breadths* proportional, there will be no change in price. For if the cistern breadths of the III row are each, (say) half the corresponding ones in the I row , equilibrium will clearly be satisfied by shortening each ordinate of the I row by a uniform per centage ( say 10 %), and lengthening those of the III row by just twice the amount of shortening in the corresponding I ordinates. This will evidently cause the lengthening of the III ordinates to be uniform (say 15% ). The ratio of marginal utilities has thus been preserved and hence the prices. Obviously the contents added to IA equals that taken from IIIA and equilibrium is reëstablished by a simple transfer from III to I. In this case there is no effect on II or any individual save I and III. * The breadth of a cistern is evidently the differential of its area divided by the differential of the ordinate that is the fluxion of commodity in reference to its marginal utility. It is a magnitude important in the discussion of distribution of commodities. Involving as it does the second differential of utility it has no perfectly distinct recognition in popular language. A narrow cistern means that a slight reduction of its contents causes its ordinate to increase much , i. e. causes it to be greatly desired . The individual is very sensitive to a change in that commodity. He misses a little less of it and appreciates a little more. Reversely a broad cistern signifies that it is hard to satisfy the man by increase and hard to annoy him by decrease. These two sorts of cisterns may be called “ sensitive ” and “ callous ” (see Appendix I). in the theory of value and prices. 47 More generally in a redistribution of incomes without altering their aggregate , in order that no prices may change (1) no condition is necessary for those whose incomes have not changed ; ( 2) for those whose incomes have changed the geometrical character of the cisternsmust be such that a proportional shortening of the ordinates for each and every richer man will absorb in the aggregate,the same additional commodity of each sort as is lost in the aggregate by the poorer through a proportional lengthening in the ordinates of each of them . If the enriched man or men absorb more of a given commodity than this requirement its price will rise, if less it will fall. If the increase of income of I equals the decrease of III effects on prices must be compensatory. If one rises some other or others must fall. If IA is much broader than IIIA but IB is much nar rower than IIIB , the price of A may rise and of B fall unless counteractions come from other commodities. For if we were to suppose prices unaltered, the cistern IA would absorb from IIIA so much and IB from IIIB so little that the ordinate of IIIA would be too long and of IIIB too short for equilibrium . In order to partially permit this lengthening and shortening there must be a corresponding lengthening and shortening in the whole A and B rows respectively and prices must be proportioned to these ordinates. In this case it is to be noted furthermore that a change in prices causes a change in the distribution of the income of II and all other individuals . The marginal utility of money for I decreases, for III increases, and for II may slightly rise or fall, owing to the change of prices. With the breadths of the cisterns properly adapted to the changes in prices there may be no change* in the valuation of money for II. - - * If the prices of only two commodities A and B change and AII and BII are straight walled , and if their breadths are inversely proportional to the difference of the squares of the old and the new prices, there will be no change in the valu ation of money. For, let p and p ' be the old and new prices, let a , and x , be the breadths (for II) of the A and B cisterns and let y ., y , and y ', y , be their old and new ordinates. Since the marginal utility of money is not to change nor the prices of C , D , etc., their ordinates cannot and therefore their quanti ties (for II) cannot change. Hence the added expenditure (by II) on A must equal that taken from B , i. e. : x,yPC - X,90Pa = x,y,Po — X;y "Pó But since the valuation of money is to be kept constant, Ya _ Y _ Y _= Y , _= Po Po Po Pó k. Irving Fisher — Mathematical investigations 48 If the price of A rises slightly and of B falls relatively more while the breadth of IIA is less than of IIB , the valuation of money to II will fall. For if not then the ordinates of IIA and IIB must change pari passu with the thickness of the back cisterns. The thickness and ordinate for IIA are , say each increased 10 % and for IIB reduced 50 % . There is clearly not room in IIA for all the money poured out of IIB . This surplus will spread over all A, B , C , etc., and reduce the ordinates and reduce the money valuation of II. These artificially exact cases obviously stand for more general and approximate economic theorems. There are no such delicate adjust ments in the actual world as here presented , but through ideal cases we study real tendencies . 4. Depress stopper A. The chief effect will be to lower the price of A . If it is a necessary* a relatively large share of the increase will go to the poor. It will probably occur that while the total money expenditure by the poor for this commodity will increase, that for the rich will decrease. Themarginal utility of money in general decreases especially for the poor man. Most other commodities will rise in price if A decreases in price faster than it increases in quantity. For there will be a saving in the expenditure for A which must be made up elsewhere . But an exceptional commodity may fall in price. Thus if B happens to be extensively used (cisterns deep and broad) only by those who use A slightly, these persons will not save materially in the expenditure Hence Hence x,kp." — kpo = x,kp,? — ,kp,"?. X ,: x,:: p.9- P ”? : Po - Po , which is the condition required . More generally in order that the valuation of money to an individual shall not change, the cisterns of II must be so formed that when the money saved on some articles equals the extra spent on the others the ordinates may all change proportionally with the prices. If the ordinates increase more than this requirement or decrease less, the valuation of money will rise. In the reverse cases it will fall. * A necessary may be defined as a commodity whose cistern is relatively deep and narrow . I. e. a very small quantity has a very great utility and a slight addition gives satisfaction very rapidly . A luxury has the reverse properties . + When commodity begins to flow into a cistern its money value (the contents of the back cistern ) increases in about the same rate as the commodity — itmatters little how much the price (thickness) falls . Contrariwise when the cistern is nearly full a fall of price decreases the money value at about the same rate - the increase of commodity matters little . The dividing point is where the commod ity increases at the same rate as the price decreases. These characters are more plainly shown in the diagrams of Auspitz und Lieben , p. 48, etc. in the theory of'valueand prices. for A , but will be compelled to pour much money into C , D , etc. of which the prices have risen. This will cause a rise in their valuation of money and as the quantity of B does not decrease its price must. Moreover there will be slight changes in all other quantities IB , IIC , etc. If (say) IIC decreases, it is due to one or both of two causes, a rise in price of C or a rise in valuation of money of II. In general the valuation of money will decrease. The decrease will be relatively great for the poor as compared with the rich , but (as just seen ) will not necessarily decrease for all persons. If A is a “ luxury ” the fall in its price will be small relatively to the foregoing case. Most of the increase of A will go to the rich . The total amount of money spenton it will probably increase which will in general decrease the price of other articles. Exceptions can be found analogous to that in the former case. The valuation of money will in general decrease, most perhaps for the middle class and more for the rich than the poor, but not necessarily for all. 5. The cases just discussed assume that the additional production of A is such that the incomes of I, II, III, etc. are not disturbed . To represent the case in which I produces all of A , after depressing A a given amount, slowly depress I until the difference of income as registered on the I scale shall equal the final reading on the A scale multiplied by the price of A minus the former A by its former price. The chief change to any one article will be in the price of A which will decrease. The chief change to any one person will be to I whose income is increased (especially if the commodity is a luxury), whose expenditure for most other articles will increase though not necessarily for all, and whose valuation of money will decrease, owing both to an increase of income and to a decrease in price of other articles consequent on the withdrawal of money from them to be spent on A . *Only exceptional articles will increase in price if their chief consumers sufficiently decrease their expenditure for A . But it may be that the increase of A will so greatly depress the price that the value of the total will decrease. This is generally true of necessaries. The producer I will lose income, that is stopper I must be raised instead of depressed . His valuation ofmoney will increase doubly, owing to the contraction of his income and the rise in price of other articles. The money* return to such a benefactor * Monopoly price is not treated here . It is interesting to note that the Dutch East India Co . used to destroy a part of their spices to prevent a great fall of price . The same thing has been done by the Japanese in silk -worm eggs. TRANS. CONN. ACAD., Vol. VIII. JULY, 1892. 50 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations is therefore not even roughly proportioned to his benefaction . If the exact shares among I, II, III, etc . in the old and new produc tion of A are known, the proper combination of stopper-positions may be made and the reactions, now exceedingly complicated,may be watched. 6. Depress each stopper A , B , C , etc. There will be a general fall in prices. But it will not be true that if the quantity of each com modity is doubled its price will be halved , and the price of one commodity in terms of another unaltered as Mill* apparently thought, for the ratios of exchange are not the ratios of the con tents of the cisterns but of their ordinates. Nor will the ratios of distribution of commodities remain the same. If however all cis terns in each front and back row are geometrically similar and their filled portions also similar (a most unreal condition ), the ratios of distribution of commodities will be unaffectedt and if furthermore all cisterns are similar, the ratios of prices will be unaltered.I In the actual world aside from differences in the shapes of cisterns there are more important differences in the way in which they are filled. Those for necessaries are relatively full as compared with those for luxuries and those for the rich as compared with those for the poor. Hence the effect of a proportionate increase of produc tion in all commodities will depress the price of necessaries much more than of luxuries. The effects on the valuation or marginal utility of money will be more complicated. If we suppose the depression of the stoppers to begin when they are far extended, the effects may be roughly described as follows. At first the valuation of money increases since the prices decrease fasters than the marginal utilities, reaches a maximum (which is different for each individual and depends on the initial distribution ), and decreases when the decrease of ordin ates is faster than that of the thickness of the back cisterns. These - -- - - -- - - --- * Pol. Econ., Bk. III, Ch. XIV , $ 2 . + For proportional increase of the contents of the cisterns in the same front and back row will reduce their ordinates proportionally and shrink the back com partments alike, thus restoring equilibrium . # For in addition to the above consideration the reduction of ordinates in all rows will be alike. $ Because when a cistern is relatively empty , a rise in the surface of its con tents diminishes the long ordinate by only a slight percentagebut very materially contracts the back compartment. in the theory of value and prices. 51 changes in the valuation of money are of course subject to the con dition that each incomemeasured in money remains the same. 7. Depress all income stoppers proportionally , i. e. increase all incomes in the same ratio. Then will all prices increase and the valuation of money decrease exactly in this ratio. There will be no change in the distribution of commodities. There is merely a depreciated standard of money. Formerly the whole marketed commodity was valued at a given number of dollars, now this number is increased . We have seen under number 1, that an increase in the money income of a single individual without an increase in commodities is a benefit to him , but such an increase when universal is bene ficial to no one. 8. Remove cistern IA and replace it with a shallower one, i. e. suppose a change in the taste of I for A , making the article less attractive. It is as if we raise the bottom of the original cistern IA. More of A will flow to other consumers and more of l's money will flow to the purchase of other commodities. A will fall in price, most other articles will rise. I's valuation of money will fall. For those who consume A extensively the valuation of money will fall. For others it may rise . If all of the I cisterns grow shallower there will be a fall in the valuation of money for I, but either prices will not change or their changes must be compensatory, for the quantities of commodities have not been altered nor their aggregate value. If all of the I row cisterns change so as to admit of a uniform percentage shortening of ordinates without any commodity flowing out of any cistern , no commodity will flow out, no prices will change and there will be no change whatsoever in the distribution of commodities nor in the valuation of money to other people. If one cistern shortens more than this requirement, the effects will be analogous to those just described for a single cistern. • If all the cisterns of the A row are made shallower the price of A will decrease.* That of other articles will in general increase. In order that the distribution of commodities may not change, the A cisterns must be so changed as to admit of a shortening of ordin - - -- * Otherwise while the A ordinates shorten and their ratio to other ordinates lessens, the back cisterns would have a relatively too great thickness compared with the other thicknesses. 52 Irving Fisher - Mathemat ic investiga tions al ates in a uniform percentage without loss or gain of commodity. In this case the price of A will decrease while that of all other articles will increase exactly alike.* The valuation of money will be re duced since the ordinate of a B cistern (say) has not changed while its back thickness has increased. The changes just considered may be brought about if A suddenly goes out of fashion . Perfectly analogous changes occur if a cistern or cisterns become narrower. The individual is then more keenly “ sensitive ” to changes of quantities. This change may occur through a discovery by which a little of the commodity is made to “ go farther ” than before. Reverse changes occur if cisterns are broadened or deepened . $ 9. It is impossible to combine all the A cisterns into a single demand cistern for A as was done in Ch. II or to combine all the I cisterns into an income cistern as in Ch. III, for we can no longer overlook the influence of other commodities and other individuals. The analysis therefore which treats of but one commodity at a time and constructs a demand curve for it is a superficial one for it does not reach all the independent variables . $ 10 . ANALYTICAL. Suppose there are n individuals and m commodities in our given isolated market during the given period and suppose the amounts of the commodities A , B, C , etc., are given Ka, K , K ., etc., and the given incomes of I, II, III, etc. are K ,, K ,, Ky, etc. Then the con dition that the commodity -sums are given is: A + A + A , + . . . . . . . . + An = K , ) + B, =- KK ,. B , + B , ++ BC ., ++ .. .. .. .. . . . .. AC. C . + C + -- -- --- --- M ,+ M , + M , + . . . . . . . = K. Į - -+ M , K m equations. í mn unknowns. J * For their mutual ratios cannot change since the ordinates to which they are proportional do not. 53 53 . in the theory of value and prices. The condition that the incomes are given is : A , · pa+ B, · pot . . . . . + M , - Pw = K , ? A , · Pa + B , . Pot . . . . . + M , · Pm = K , ?į n equations. m new unknowns . . . . . . . .. . . .. . . . .. . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . (prices). An · Pa + B , · Pot . . . . . + M , · Pm = K , The utility functions (the cistern-forms) are: du dU E dU = F (B ) ; : . . . ; ZT mn equations. dƯ = F (À ,); je = F (B .); . . . . ; IN = F (M ) mn new unknowns --- . . (marg. ut.). ax.=F(A.); 28.= F(B.);.... ;MN. F(M.) The principle of proportion is : du du du dU da, dB,- 70, . . . am , du du n (m — 1) independent du DA, -dB, . . . . . : equations. no new - - - dU dU AU _ m .mm dA, - dB.: . . . . . unknowns. M . = Pa: Po:Pc:...: P. Total number of equations : m + n + mn + n (m - 1) = 2mn + m (6 66 unknowns mn + m + mn + 0 = 2mn + m Therefore allmagnitudes are determinate and the number of these magnitudes as well as the number of the equations is twice the num ber of commodities times the number of individuals plus the num ber of commodities. The valuation of money for each individual can be found from the equations: dU IV , $ 2.) = etc. . 54 Irving Fisher - Mathemat ical investigation s $ 11 For production the treatment is precisely parallel to the foregoing (figs. 12, 13). 12. LIC IBRI = -- -- - = -= -# -- = *- -- -- = == == - = = 6I IB CHAPTER V . PRODUCTION AND CONSUMPTION COMBINED. $ 1. Hitherto it has been assumed that the quantities of commodities and incomes (or expenditures) have been given. But these quanti ties have themselves been determined by economic causes. Jevons* arranges the sequence as follows: “ Cost of production determines supply, Supply determines final degree of utility, Final degree of utility determines value.” * Pol. Econ., Ch. IV, p. 165. in the theory of value and prices . 55 This represents the chronological order but only part of the causa tion. Cost of production is not the sole determinator of supply . Production is prophetic . When prices are steady the certain future price is an unquestionable regulator of supply . Auspitz und Lieben appear to me to deserve much credit for showing how all these facts harmonize . Price, production , and consumption are determined by the equality of marginal utility and marginal cost of production.* Their clear exposition of this theory not only exbibits the “ funda mental symmetry of supply and demand,” but reconciles in a captivating manner the old one-sided and seemingly contradictory theories of value making them fall in place as opposite facets of the same gem . It is discouraging to find the old fight still going on. Dietzelf attempts to play the peacemaker by the makeshift of dividing the field between the contesting theories. The apparent conflict grows out of an inadequate conception of mathematical ileterminateness. As the quantity of any commodity increases its marginal utility to consumers decreases while its mar ginal disutility to producers increases. If the latter exceeds the former the price which consumers will give is less than what pro ducers will accept. Production is contracted and the utility and disutility approach each other. If the quantity is too small the machinery acts in the reverse way. The equilibrium though always miscalculated is constantly sought and its more delicate and rapid deflections are corrected by a special functionary, the speculator. $ 2. It is assumed that the rate of production during the given period is exactly equal to the rate of consumption. This is asserting an ideal equilibrium . The expenses of transportation and retailing are included in “ pro duction.?? The principle of proportion previously explained is now extended. The marginal utilities of consuming and the marginal disutilities of producing are in the same continuous ratio for each individual- the ratio of prices. $ 3. As the simplest case of combining production and consumption , suppose an individual to consume himself just that quantity of a given commodity which he produces. - - -- * Auspitz und Lieben , S5, p . 17. + Die Klassische Werttheorie und die Theorie vom Grenznutzen . Conrad 's Jahr buch , 20 . 56 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations 14 . UTILIZZZETTITIETZITTTTIINTET In Fig. 14 the stoppers * or pistons S and S' which regulate the quantities in the cisterns for production and consumption, respect ively, are so connected as to move together, keeping the quantities in the two cisterns equal. Furthermore the water pressure on them from the tank keeps the level of all three liquids the same— that in the tank and those in the two cisterns. The lever keeps the mar ginal utility equal to the marginal disutility, for its pivot is a fixed one and is placed midway between the axes of ordinates. The resulting determinate equilibrium is subject to three sets of condi tions : (1) The quantity consumed equals that produced - a condition pro vided for by the duplicate pistons. (2) There must be a relation between the quantity produced and its marginal disutility and between the quantity consumed and its marginal utility — the character of the cisterns. (3) Marginal utility and disutility are equal— the lever. $ 4. ANALYTICAL. If A , and A , be the quantities of A produced and consumed , respectively, the conditions of equilibrium are : A . = A { 1 equation . * | 2 unknowns. dU dA = F (A.)' | 2 equations. 40 = F (A ) !? 2 new unknowns. WATT dU dA. = dU 11equation. MA, S no new unknown. No. equations: 1 + 2 + 1 = 4 . No.unknowns : 2 + 2 + 0 = 4. * In practice a more intricate frictionless bellows would be used . 57 in the theory of value and prices. 57 $5. In the more general case there are n individuals and m com modities. 15. Ą IR Be HUA Fig. 15 simply connects fig . 9 and fig . 12 by a series of new levers like that in fig . 14, so that for each individual the ordinates of the production cistern and its consumption cistern shall be equal. There are also analogous horizontal levers (fig. 16) to keep the price for 16 . H - - - - - - R consumers equal to that for producers. The stoppers are all duplicate as in fig. 14 for each commodity. Moreover there are analogous duplicate pistons to keep each individual's incomes and expenditures equal. The industrial machinery is now seen to be self-regulative. There is no arbitrary assignment of incomes or of commodities. The only 58 ical nvestigations i Irving Fisher - Mathemat changes possible are effected by change in the forms of the cisterns or by changing their number, that is by changing the “ cost” of pro duction or the utility of consumption, or by changing the population (which changes, we may remark , go together). By making the cisterns removable and replaceable the effects of varied conditions can be studied as in the preceding chapter. However, this equilibrium is indeterminate in one respect. Unlike the former it does not fix the unit of value. The sum of the income-cistern -contents is arbitrary. If all duplicate income-and expenditure -pistons are simultaneously depressed so as to increase all incomes proportionately, the equilibrium will not be upset nor will the distribution of commodities be affected. The rear cisterns will simply dilate in uniform * ratio . The money standard has alone changed . This may be remedied by making the thicknesses of all back cis terns for the commodity A equal to unity . A thus becomes the stand ard of value, and henceforth all prices are in terms of this com modity. This is what is done in the actual world. ALYTICAL . $ 6 . ANALYTICAL. A.1,1 + An, + ... + A.,n = Ax,1 + Ax,2 + . .. + Axon B.7,1 + B1, 2 + . . . + B .,n = Bx,1 + Bx2 + .. . + Bkv m equations. 2mn unknowns. . .. . . . .. . . . . . . . . .. . . . . M .,it M .,2 + ... + Mnn = M 1 + Mx2 + . .. + Moni ) (n — 1) inde A 1,1•Pat .. .. + M .. . Pm = Axıl. Pat ... + M «,1• Pm ! pendent equa ---- . .. .... .. .. .- -- --- - ---- ---- --- - ---- - --. į A ,,n•Pat .. . . + M . Pm = Arn : Pat . . . + Myn Poi m new un ſ knowns (prices). . du dU dA.1,1 DU tions. TM 1 = F F'(A7,1) ; . . . . TAK, = F ( A / I) ; . . . - - - - = FC U Mko1 - - - - - - - - - - - - 2mn equations. - - - . - - . - - - - - - - - - - - - - dU DAF, = F (A ,,n) ; . . dU = F (Akın) ; . . . dU d M , = F (M ,,n) dU = F (Mx,n) * Cf. Ch . IV , § 8, number 7. 2 mn new un knowns (marg. ut.). ' in the theory of value and prices. du du du du du 59 du da , dB .. M , JA : dB ., . .-2M , = du du du du du dU dA. , AB , , . . . an ... : JA : dB . . . JM . . . . . . . . . - - - - - - - . . . - . . - - - . . - . . . . . . . . . . . . . . du dv dᏓ - du dv dA dB. .. .2M ndAconi a Be ...AM = dent e onations L equations. dᏌ . - Pai - Po : . . : - Pm : + Pa : + Po : . . : + Pm No. equations: m + (n | (2 m - 1) n indepen no new unknowns. J 1) + 2mn + (2m – 1 ) n = tmn + m - 1 No. unknowns: 2mn + m + 2mn + 0 = 4mn + m . There are just one too few equations. It may not be evident at first why the second set does not contain n independent equations instead of (n - 1). The point is that any one of these equations can be derived from the others together with the equations of the first set. Thus multiply the equations of the first set by Pa Po . . . Pm respectively and add the resulting equations arranging as follows: A7,1 · Pa + B .,1. Put . . . + M1,1· Pmt ? + A7,2 · Pa + B7,2 • Po + . . . + M7, · P. t. + -- -. .- .- .- .- .- .- . -. - . -. - .- -. -- -. . .. .. + A .,n . Pa + Brenº pot . . . + Mn,n · Pm ) [ A ,1 · Pa + Bk 2• po + . . . + Mk,* · P.net } + Ax,2 • Pa + Bk,2 • Pi + . . . + M & • P'm + . - . - . - -. . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . + Arn : Pa + Bxr · Pot . . . + Man: Pm . Subtracting from this equation the sum of all but the first (say ) of the second set, our result is : A. ,1 · Pat B7,1 · Pot . . . + M .,1 . Pm = Ak,1 . Pat Bk1 . Pot . . . + Mx, 2· Pm which is the first equation of the second set. This equation is there fore dependent on the others, or there is one less independent equa tion than appears at first glance. Hence we need one more equa tion . Wemay let : Pa = 1. This makes A the standard of value (cf. $ 5 ). No such limitation applies to the equations in Chapter IV . 60 i ical nvestigations Irving Fisher — Mathemat CHAPTER VI. THE COMPONENT PROCESSES OF PRODUCTION . $ 1. Without dwelling on the economic applications of the mechanism just described we hasten on to the description of a more complicated mechanism . Production usually consists of a number of successive processes . The last of these is retailing. Let us group all other processes under the head of production. The price for production and con sumption are no longer equal. Hitherto we have had two sets of cisterns, the production set and the consumption set. Separate now , these sets far enough to introduce a third set for exchange or retailing as in fig. 17. 17 The exchange set is a series of double cisterns each related to a particular commodity,and a particular person . Consider the cistern IA for instance (the sub-letter for exchange or retailing). In the front compartment is the quantity of A which I buys and sells or transfers from producer to consumer. The back compartment con tains the money pay for doing it. These exchange cisterns are connected with each other and with the production set by levers precisely as if they were so many new commodities produced. 61 in the theory of value and prices. So also the rodsmaintain a constantmoney rate for exchange; in stead, however, of the former simple relation between the producers and consumers there is now the following that the sum of the ordin ates of A I., and A I , equals the ordinate of Alk, and likewise for II, III, etc., also that the thickness of the back cisterns of A , plus that of A , equals that of An. These results are effected by parallel rulers, those for the former purpose being represented in fig . 17. The new machinery required for the exchange process consists then (1) of triplicate pistons* which necessitate that the same quantity of A shall be produced , exchanged , and consumed ; (2) the additional rods and levers (horizontal and inclined ) to make the marginal disutilities of producing and exchanging proportional to the recompense and which also maintain a constant price for exchang ing the same thing ; and (3) the special contrivance to add the marginal disutilities of producing and exchanging for any individ ual so as to equal that of consuming, and also equate the sum of the prices of producing and exchanging to that of consuming. $ 2. ANALYTICAL. A..,1 t . .. + A1.n = A6,1 + .. . + Ac, = A \,1 + . .. + Akon ) 2 m - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . i equations. | 3 min M . , + . . . + Mon - Mc,1 + . . . + Mon = Mx, + . . . + Mkn ) unknowns. A7, Part + . .. + M .,1P.,7 + A ., Page + . .. + M .,1 Pm,e= Ak, Pok + ... + Mxi Pmore -- - - - -- - - -- -- -- - - - - - -- - - -- -- - - -- - - . -- . - -. - - -- - -- - - -- - - -- - -- - A.,n Patt.. . + M ,1,n Pm,8 + Ac,nPave to.. + MenPm,e = Axın Park + .. . + Men Pink n - 1 independent equations. 3 m new unknowns (prices) . JU DU _ F (1 731) - = F (A ,,1) ; . . . ; DA , QU dU dA . = F (A )) ; . . . ; DU DAC, = F (AX,1) ; . . . ; - = F (M ) dU - = F (M ., ) ) 3 mn equations. į 3 mn new unknowns dU dA = F (A ,,n); . . . ; - = F (M _ ) 1 1 (marg. ut.). TT , AU AU dAC, = F (Ac,n) ; . . . ; M dU = F (M .) | dU dAkin = F (A ..») ; . . .; = F (M «,n) * The income and expenditure-pistons are merely duplicate as before. Irving Fisher — Mathematical investigations 62 du du du dA. .. UM , JA, du du du du du AMEA du du ) n (3m - 1) -AM = | independ du du ent equa dA . MM., da ,:..-JM , JA... .--dM ..= tions. - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -- - - - - - - - - - - - - - . . = no new du du du du du du un dAFT .-- MandACXdM ., d . ..-AM ,na Pa, .. .:Pm, wns , :Pare i. . :Pm,e : – Paki.. : – Pm, Pa,y + Pane = Paix ) m equations. -- -. . .-. .. . . ... P .,g + Pm,e = Pmin ) no new unknowns. No. equations : 2m + (n - 1) + 3mn + n (3m - 1) + m = 6mn + 3m – 1. No.unknowns: 3mn + 3m + 3mn + 0 . + 0 = 6mn + 3m . The second set apparently contains n equations instead of n - 1 as above recorded . But, by multiplication of the first line of the first set, we have : (AT + . . . + A ,,n) Pat = (Ax,1 + . . . + Axın) Pa, (Ac,1 + . . . + Ac,n) Page = (Ax,1 + . . . + Akin ) Pare adding and remembering that Pak = Pat + Pare we get : A ., 1 · Part . . . + Anni Part Ac, 1 • Pase + .. . + Ac,n. Pane = Ak,1• Parkt . . . + Axon • Pa,K Writing the similar equations from the second, third , etc. lines of the first set and adding we get (rearranging terms): A7,1•Part .. + M .,1• Pm,n + A ,1.Page + .. + M ,1. Pm,et ? + A .,2. Part . . + M7,2• Pm,it - - - .. . . . .. .. li ; : - - - - -- - - - - - - - - - - - .. . . .. .. . - --- .. .. + Men : Pm,ej -a + 4 ,1,n · Part -- --. . r Æg,1• Pax + . . . + Mx,1• Pmx + + Ak,2 · Pa,x + -- -- - -- -- - -- -- --- - --- - - - . .. - - - - - - - - - - - - - + Ann · Part . . . + Mane Pmir If from this equation the sum of all but one of the second set be subtracted the result will evidently be the remaining one. Weare therefore at liberty to write Park = 1 to determine a standard of value. in the theory of value and prices. 63 $ 3. An analogous mechanism and discussion applies to the separation of production into retailing, wholesaling, transportation and even the various technical processes distinctive of the production of each commodity. In making worsted for instance there are some 16 processes having this sort of dependence. The reactions and equilibrium in the real world are still more complicated than those here presented . Notonly is there equilibrium in one market as New York city, but a mutual dependence of vari ous markets. The rate of transportation determines in part the amount of dependence and the amount of communication deter mines in part the rate of transportation . As Cournot* says, “ * * le système économique est un ensemble dont toutes les parties se tiennent et réagissent les unes sur les autres." End of Part I. * Principes mathématiques, Ch. XI, p . 146. 64 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations Part II : - UTILITY OF ONE COMMODITY A FUNCTION OF THE QUANTITIES OF ALL COMMODITIES . CHAPTER I. TWO COMMODITIES. § 1. Hitherto it has been assumed that the utility of a commodity is a function of the quantity of that commodity alone. It is true that it depends upon that quantity more than any other and the analysis of Part I is a necessary first approximation . In astronomy the attraction of the sun on the earth is first studied alone to determine the earth 's motion ; next the moon 's influence is admitted, then the occasional “ perturbations ” due to planets and comets. Absolute accuracy is never attained for the earth's motion is a function of the mass and position of every body in the universe. So also the utility of the 100th lb . of butter (100 lbs. per year) depends mostly on that 100 lbs. It would not be perceptibly in fluenced by a change in the quantity of clothing, but it would be perceptibly reduced if the amount of bread consumed were reduced from 300 loaves to 200, for bread and butter go together. It is needful here to distinguish carefully between two ways in which the quantity of one commodity can affect the utility of others. Even under the supposition of Part I, a change in the price of clothes effected a change in the individual valuation of money and so changed the quantity of bread consumed and so in turn changed the marginal utility and price of bread . But under our new sup position, a change in the price of butter directly changes the utility · of the same quantity of bread . In the first case marginal utility of bread can change only after a change in its quantity . In the second the marginal utility of the same amount of bread changes; the first contemplates a variation in the quantity of water in a cistern , the second contemplates a variation in the cistern wall itself. . assumed . .: dU _= FN ( A ) ; but now we must write: In Part I we we dusuncu . A " Nil dU TĂ = F (A ,, B , C , . . . M ). in the theory of value and prices. 65 $ 2. It will be seen that this sort of dependence of particular commodi ties is very common. Articles are 'bought with reference to each other, oil with reference to the number of lamps used, bed linen to the number of beds, bureaus to the quantity of clothes to be stored , carpets to the amount of floor rented or built, bookcases to the number of books owned ; the demand for steel rails is connected with that for railroad ties, that for locomotives with that for cars , etc . Again in production , the “ peculiar cases of value ” of which Mill* speaks and which Jevonst treats come under the samehead ; coke and coal gas; mutton and wool; beef, hides, and tallow , etc . The cases above instanced are cases of “ completing” ! articles. Under the head of “ competing ” # articles, come, mineral oil and other oils, various “ qualities ” of any article as meats, grades of flour, etc., while under production almost every two articles are competing. A man in one business does not wish to meddle with another or, otherwise expressed, the marginal disutility of produc ing 1,000 tons per year of coal is increased if the producer attempts to run a paper mill or trade in jewelry. $ 3. Introducing this new dependence of utilities, it is seen that, if the cisterns contain at one point of equilibrium the proper amount of water and have as ordinates the proper marginal utilities , as soon as any income or commodity stopper is pressed , not only does the water redistribute but the shapes of the cisterns change. If the quantity of bread is increased, the cisterns for biscuit may shrink and those for butter widen. That is the ordinate (marginal utility) for the same quantity of biscuit decreases, and of butter increases. The general effect is to keep the ratio of marginal utilities of bread and biscuit and so also their prices nearly constant, while the cheapening of bread may directly increase the marginal utility and price of butter irrespective of its quantity . The essential quality of substitutes or competing articles is that the marginal utilities or the prices of the quantities actually pro duced and consumed tend to maintain a constant ratio . Wemay * Bk . III, Ch . XVI. # Auspitz und Lieben , p . 170. TRANS. Conn. ACAD., VOL. VIII. + Page 197. JULY, 1892. cal nvestigations i Irving Fisher - Mathemati 66 define perfect substitutes as such that this ratio is absolutely constant. The essential attribute of completing articles is that the ratio of the quantities actually produced and consumed tends to be constant (as many shoe-strings as shoes for instance, irrespective of cost). Wemay define perfect completing articles as such that this ratio is absolutely constant. If we suppose each set of competing and completing articles to be “ perfect,” it is possible to arrange the cisterns so that the change of form of some cisterns as due to change in the contents of other cisterns shall be small or nothing. Thus if four grades of flour be “ perfect ” competing, so that their marginal utilities are always in the ratio 8, 9, 11, 17 ,we may form a joint cistern for individual I whose contents shall be “ flour,” the quality unspecified . Each cubic unit of liquid shall represent equivalent quantities of each grade, i. e. barrel of the first quality, \ of the second, 1 of the third or 1 of the fourth, while the ordinate shall represent the com mon utility of any one of these equivalent quantities. If four completing articles as the parts of a coat, sleeves, pockets, buttons, and coat proper are always produced and consumed in num bers proportional respectively to 2, 4, 3 and 1, we may form a joint cistern for individual I whose contents shall be “ coats,” parts un distinguished. With such combinations as these, the cistern analysis of Part I will represent the economic relations fairly well and almost per fectly if the deviations from equilibrium are not followed too far. But few articles are absolutely perfect representatives of either the competing or the completing group, and a member of one group may also belong to another. Thus butter is completing to bread and biscuit, and although a cheapening of bread directly increases the utility of butter it indirectly increases it by decreasing the use of biscuit. It is readily seen that the interrelations of the shapes of the cis terns — if we now treat each quality of meat, etc. and each part of a utensil as a separate commodity — are too complicated even to be mentally representable without some new mode of analysis. $ 5. The former analysis is incomplete, not incorrect. All the inter dependence described in Part I exists , but there also exist other connections between the shapes of the cisterns which could not be mechanically exhibited . For any one position of equilibrium the : in the theory of value and prices. cistern mechanism may represent accurately the quantities, utilities , and prices, but the shape of each cistern is a function of the whole state of equilibrium and differs as soon as that differs. However in general the interdependence in the shapes of the cisterns is very slight. That is, the utility of a commodity usually varies so much more under a variation in the quantity of that commodity than under variations of other commodities that the relations discussed in Part Imay be regarded as good first approximations. Especially is this true if the interdependent commodities are grouped as in § 4, so as to eliminate all the really important influences of commodities on each other.* It will subsequently appear that the analysis of Part II is also incomplete and so will it ever be. Neither economics nor any other science can expect an exhaustive analysis. $ 6. Recurring to the definitions of utility as a quantity (Part I, Ch. 1), it will be noted that the third definition which indicated the ratio of two utilities was based on the assumption that the utility of each commodity was independent of the quantity of any other com modity. This assumption was necessary to prove that two applica tions of def. (3 ) led to harmonious results (Part 1, Ch. I, § 4 ). To abandon this assumption as we have now done is to forego the use of that third definition. At the close of Part II a further discus sion of “ utility as a quantity ” will be given . At present we con tent ourselves by assuming the marginal utility of a given amount of some one article as our unit of utility. Of course if we should use some other marginal utility as a unit, themeasurements will not now agree. This, however, is no calamity . It will presently appear that the meaning of the phrase “ one utility is twice another ” is of no real importance for the subject in hand. $ 7. Confine attention first to two commodities (a ) and (6 ) consumed by one individual. Let this individual first arrange his whole consump tion combination to suit himself. Then in order to partially analyze this equilibrium of choice let us metaphorically experiment on him * Marshall, Prin . Econ ., Math , note xii, p. 756, says: “ Prof. Edgeworth 's plan of representing U and V as general functions of x and y [see preface to this memoir ] has great attractions to the mathematician ; but it seems less adapted to express the every day facts of economic life than of regarding, as Jevons did , themarginal utilities of apples as functions of x [the quantity of apples ] simply.”, Irving Fisher — Mathematical investigations 68 as follows. He is directed to alter this consumption combination by arranging bis quantities A and B of the two selected commodities (a ) and (b) in all possible ways, but without changing the quantities C , D , etc. of other commodities. The marginal utility of each will vary not only in relation to its own quantity but also the quantity of the other commodity. Thus, dU A = F (A , B,) dU dB = F (B , A ,) These may be regarded as derivatives with respect to A and B of U , = P ( A ,B ,) where U , is the total utility to I of the consumption combination A , and B . In fig. 18 let the abscissa OX represent the quantities B , of (6) and theordinates (OY) thequantities A ,of (a ). 18. Any point P by its co -ordinates represents a possible combination of quantities A , and B , consumed by I. By varying point P all possible combinations of A , and B , are represented . At P erect à perpen dicular to the plane of the page whose length shall representthe marginal utility of A , for the combination , that is, the хв degree of utility of a small addition of A , ( B , remaining the same). If Pas sumes all possible positions, the locus of the extremity of this per pendicular will be a surface. Again at P erect a different perpendicular for the marginal utility of B,; its extremity will generate another surface. The first sur face takes the place of a utility curve for (a ), the second for (6). These two surfaces may be regarded as the derivative surfaces (with respect to the variation of A , and of B,), from a primitive whose ordinate (perpendicular at P ), is the total utility of the com bination of A , and B , represented by the point P. This surface is usually convex like a dome with a single maximum part ,but it need not always be. There may be twomaxima as will presently appear. In such a case it cannot be everywhere convex. If a plane be drawn tangent to this last surface at a point over P, the slope of the plane parallel to the A direction will be the ordinate in the theory of value and prices. 69 of the first derived surface ; i. e., will be the marginal utility of A ,, while the right and left slope will be the marginal utility of B , or theordinate of the second derivative surface . The primitive surface thus supplies a convenient way of uniting in thought the two mar ginal utilities. Its absolute height* above the plane of the paper is of no consequence ; it may be lowered or heightened without dis turbing tangential directions or affecting its two derivatives. $ 8. The three surfaces thus constructed need not extend indefinitely over the plane. They may approach vertical plane or cylindrical asymptotes so that for some points in the plane there may be no surface vertically over or under Mathematically the total utility and marginal utilities at these points are imaginary. Economically it is impossible that the indi vidual should consume quantities of (a ) and (b ) indicated by the co ordinates of such points. Those parts of the plane where such points are may be called “ empty.” If (fig. 18 ) the point P moves vertically (up and down on the page) the extremity of the perpendicular for the total utility describes one of Auspitz und Lieben 's curves for An, it being understood how ever that the quantities of other commodities do not change.I The perpendicular for the marginal utility of A , generates in the first derivative surface a Jevonians curve of utility for A , it being understood that B , C , etc. are constant. This curve will usually descend but it may not and cannot in certain regions if the surface is derived from a primitive with two maxima, or any concave primi tive. The other perpendicular, however, traces a curve which has never been used , viz : one which shows the relation between the quantities A , and themarginal utility of B , while B , remains con stant. This curve will in general descend or ascend according as the articles (a ) and (b) are competing or completing. For instance, * It is in fact the arbitrary constant of integration . + This “ asymptote ” and “ imaginary ” interpretation appears to cover the class of difficulties which led Marshall to say his curves failed to have meaning at points at which the individual could not live. # It is rather, then , an “ Elementarkurve ” of a “ Lebensgenusskurve ” there being an “ anfangsordinate .” Jevons' curve is evidently the derivative of Auspitz und Lieben's. See table Appendix I, Diyision II, S 2. 70 i ical nvestigations Irving Fisher — Mathemat suppose (a) and (6) are two brands of flour. If I consumes during the period X units of one brand and 20 units of the other his desire for a 21st unit of the latter will depend on how much he has of the former (how large X is). If he has much of the first kind his desire is small. A similar pair of curves may be found by moving P horizontally . If the supposition in Part I were true the two strange curves (viz: connecting marginal utilities of A and B with quantities of B and A , respectively), would reduce to straight lines parallel to the plane ofthe paper. $ 10. The relations indicated by these three surfaces are really all included in one of them — the primitive. Consequently , to avoid troublesome transitions from one mode of representation to another we shall hereafter confine ourselves to this primitive surface . Consider horizontal sections of this surface, that is sections par allel to the plane of the A and B axes. Each section forms a curve which may be called an indifference curve. It is the locus of points representing all consumption-combinations of A and B which have a given total utility. In fig . 18 the attached number to each curve represents the amount of this utility. They in general form a family of concentric curves vanishing finally at the point M of max imum satisfaction . M is the point at which the individual would arrange his consumption -combination of A and B if they cost noth ing. There may be two or more maxima. For competing articles these maxima may lie in the axes (fig . 19), for one may prefer not to consumeboth. The ordinates may of course have any units of length. Suppose 19. this unit to be indefinitely reduced from an inch to a millimeter, etc. Then our surface becomes a layer. Its thickness may be fig ured as a density (rather than an ordinate), distributed over the plane of the paper as electricity over à conductor. Each indif ference curve is the locus of points where the density (formerly ordinate ), is a given amount. This idea of density will behence forth used though the necessity for its use does not come till the next chapter . Fig . 20 shows the curves for competing articles and fig . 22 for completing. For “ perfect” substitutes the curves (fig. 21) reduce - in the theory of value and prices. to parallel straight lines whose intercepts on the A and B axes are inversely proportional to the fixed ratio of their marginal utilities. The point M is indeterminate on the line 99. “ Lehigh ” and 21. ca 20 . 10 B \B 7 8 9 “ Lackawanna ” anthracite coal are nearly perfect substitutes. If it cost nothing the individual would indifferently consume the quan 22. 23. А м ALDE B " B'B tity 09 (vertical) of one or 09 (horizontal) of the other or any combination of the two on the straight line 99 inclined in this case at 45°. For perfect completing articles the whole family of curves reduces to a straight line passing through the origin (fig. 23). Let us regard a pair of shoes as two distinct commodities : right shoes and left shoes. For any point in the line OM (fig. 23), the desire for right shoes vanishes as long as no new left shoes are admitted , and yet the desire for a new pair may exist. The idea of marginal utility for right shoes has no application though that for pairs of shoes has. $ 11. There are endless points of view from which the primitive and its derivatives may be approached and made to yield the economic relations we seek .* Descriptions will be confined chiefly to the * For instance we might take curves corresponding to the sections of the deriv ative surfaces at various heights, or curves orthogonal to the indifference curves these will be again referred to ), or curves representing the locus of points at which the marginal utilities of the two commodities have a given ratio . Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations indifference curves, the tangents and normals to which play an important rôle . When our individual fixed his whole consumption combination to suit himself, let us suppose that he spent $25 per year on the two articles fa and b) under consideration. Wemay metaphorically compel him , while not altering in the least his purchases of other articles and hence having the same $ 25 to spend on (a ) and (6 ), to contemplate spending it in a different way. If the price of (a) is $0. 25 and of (6) is $0.50, the two simplest methods of spending his $ 25 is to spend it all on (a ) and purchase 100 units, or to spend all on (6 ) and purchase 50 units. In fig . 18 lay off OA = 100 units and OB = 50 units. Then any point on the straight line AB will represent a consumption combina tion of A and B purchasable for $ 25.* AB may be called a partial incomeline. Our individual is therefore left free only to select his combination somewhere on this line. The combination 5 or 5 pre sent equal inducements but not as great as 6 or 6 on an arc of greater utility, nor there asmuch as at I. Hewill select his combtha tion in such a manner as to obtain the maximum total utility, which is evidently at the point I where AB is tangent to an indifference curve.f At this point “ he gets the most for his money." His selection I is of course just what it was before we began our analysis. But we have advanced one step. Wehave partially anal yzed this equilibrium , that is we see the equilibrium for A and B while the prices and quantities of other articles remain the same. It is as if a pendulum free to swing in any vertical plane is found at rest and a scientist attempts to analyze its equilibrium . He forth with confines its motion to a single plane and discusses its equilib rium there. The analogy suggested may be extended . The prin ciple underlying the equilibrium of a pendulum or any mechanical equilibrium (as of a mill pond or of a suspension bridge) is : that configuration will be assumed which will minimize the potential. So also the supreme principle in economic equilibrium is : that arrange ment will be assumed which will maximize utility 1. -- --- - * Proof: Equation of AB is OA + 20 = 1 where x and y are the co-ordinates 25 of any point on AB. This becomes y . 25 + x . 00 = 25 ; that is, ac times its price + y times its price equals $ 25 . + When AB is tangent to two indifference curves that one will be selected which has the greater utility. # See interesting remarks, Edgeworth : Mathematical Psychics. Also in his address as Pres. section Econ. Sci. and Statistics Brit. Asso., Nature, Sept. 19 , 1889, p. 496 . 73 in the theory of value and prices. $ 12. Since OA and OB represent quantities A and B of commodities ( a) and (6) purchasable for the same sum ($ 25 ), they are inversely proportional to the prices of (a ) and (6). If prices remain the same but the individual grows richer and the sum he can afford to spend on (a ) and (6) is no longer $ 25 but $50, the line AB simply recedes twice as far remaining parallel to itself. As it changes, its varying point of tangency follows a tortuous line the locus of all points at which the individual would arrange his combination of A and B at the given prices. If the price of (a ) increases, O A relatively diminishes and a new point of tangency is found. If the articles are completing (fig . 22) a change of price will not cause the tangent line to very greatly alter the proportion of consumption of the articles for it will merely change the position of I to (say) I', and it is clear that the coördin ates of l' have nearly the same ratio as those of I ; if substitutes ( fig . 20) a slight relative change in price will cause an enormous change in the proportions used (I and I'). This was found to be the case in 1889 when a copper syndicate attempted to raise the price of copper. Hardly any article exists which has not some substi tute . This sort of dependence keeps manufacturers watchful. It is because of this dependence that some “ useful” articles go out of use . $ 13. Fig . 24 represents two “ grades ” of the same commodity, as brown and granulated sugar. The superior grade is laid off on the B (hor izontal) axis, and the inferior on the 24 . A (vertical) axis. The point of maxi mum satisfaction is in or near the B axis. If the individual is poor and can afford to spend little on the article he will buy the poorer quality. The line AB is tangent to an indifference curve in or near the A axis at I. If he grows richer the line AB recedes from the origin and he purchases the combina tion I' containing considerably more of 1 B B ; he uses this superiorquality on Sun days (say) while consuming A on week days. If he grows richer still, he changes the position to I" using none of A or only a little. Irving Fisher — Mathematical investigations The inclination of the line AB is such that ( A > OB that is A is cheaper than B, for OA and OB are the quantites of A and B pur chasable for the samemoney. If the prices of A and B were equal so that OA = OB , it would not be tangent to an indifference curve unless on the B axis and A would go out of use. Moreover it is evident that a slight variation in the relative prices of A and B will change greatly the position of I for a poor man but will not change materially that of l" for a rich man. If the poor consumers predominate the line AB will follow the general trend of the curves near the origin . If the rich consumers predominate the line AB will become steeper (as in the dotted posi tions). That is the two prices of the two qualities separate widely . This interprets the fact that in a rich market like New York City a slight difference in quality will make an enormous divergence in price while in some country towns different grades either do not exist or sell for nearly the same price. In the country districts of “ the west ” all cuts of beef sell for the same price (about 10 cts. per lb .). In the cities of the west two or three qualities are commonly dis tinguished , while in New York a grocer will enumerate over a dozen prices in the same beef varying from 10 to 25 cts. per lb . $ 14. In fig . 25 if the individual III attempts to change the position of 25. III he may do so in many different “ directions.” If he changes in the direction III &, he will increase his con sumption of A without alter ing that of B or if toward B , III B , without altering A , if in an intermediate direction, III O , he will increase both A and B and in the ratios of the components of that direc tion (III a and III B). The direction of maximum in crease of utility is perpendicular to the indifference curve.* We may figure III S as a force. If III were in any other position the force would evidently have a component along the line A , B , and would move III back to the position of equilibrium III. * For between two infinitesimally distant indifference curves the shortest route is on their perpendicular. in the theory of value and prices. 75 We may call the perpendicular direction III Ở the “ maximum direction.” It has the important property that its components III a and III B are proportional to the marginal utilities of A and B . This follows from a theorem * of vector calculus or thus : III a and III B are inversely proportional to 0A , and OB,, that is directly proportional to the prices of A and B and therefore proportional to their marginal utilities. $ 15 . If (fig . 25) the separate curve systems of all individuals I, II, etc. are drawn, and the lines AB drawn in each case , they will be paral lel. For the prices are uniform among all individuals and OA and OB in each case are inversely as the prices. Since the normals to these lines will also be parallel, this theorem may be stated : The “ maximum directions ” of all are alike. $ 16. These methods apply to the comparison of any two commodities and afford a means of graphically representing statistical relations connecting the demands for two articles so far as the variations in the quantities of other articles can be eliminated The same principles apply to the production of two articles. Hides and tallow are completing articles from a producer's standpoint. Likewise coke and coal gas, mutton and wool, and in general any article and its “ secondary product.” On the other hand most articles are competing or substitutes from a producer's point of view . The difficulty of producing cloth is greatly increased if the same individual produces books. This is the root of the principle of division of labor and leads to that im portant contrast between production and consumption once before alluded to. This and other contrasts will be mentioned in Appen dix II, § 8. Marshall and others are fond of using the expression “ fundamental symmetry of supply and demand." This notion must be supplemented by that of a “ fundamental asymmetry.” As social organization progresses each man (and each community or nation) tendsto become producer of fewer things but consumer of more. * Gibbs, Vector Analysis , 88 50 -53. III a 83 ; | For by similar triangles : il 3 = 11L 3 = OB 0 , = pa tical ma Irving Fisher - Mathe 76 ations ig invest Fig . 26 shows the usual sort of indifference production curves. 26 . . В B is here laid off to the left and A downward ; the line AB is the locus of production combina tions of A and B which can be sold for the same money, say $ 1,000. The point of tan gency * I is the point at which the individual can produce the required $ 1,000 worth of A and B with the minimum disutility. The curves are such that the points of tangency will be gener ally at or near the axes, especially if the amount of production is large i. e. if the line AB is far from the origin. If B becomes cheaper (OB longer) the point of tangency will change but slowly until presently there are two points of tangency and if B becomes still cheaper the individual will change his profession suddenly from the position I to a position in or near the A axis. The numbers on the indifference curves for production increase in definitely negatively . There is usually no maximum or minimum point. $ 17. Finally an article consumed may be competing or completing to another produced. A blacksmith finds small utility in dumb bells; the production of horseshoes " competes ” with the consumption of dumb-bells . The relations between competing articles and completing articles are not always so simple, for articles may be competing at some combinations and completing at others . Statistical inquiries along these lines might be made with profit, and have apparently attracted little attention .t CHAPTER II. THREE OR MORE COMMODITIES. $ 1. The foregoing methods extend very readily to three dimensions. Suppose the whole market to attain equilibrium . As before, let us as it were,freeze this equilibrium except for three commodities A , B , and C . Then as before,we obtain a fixed sum of money disposable * The tangency must be such that the curve is on that side of the straight line toward the origin . The other kind of tangency represents an unstable equilib + See Jevons, p. 135 . rium . 777 in the theory of value and prices. for the purchase of A , B, and C , by each individual. Construct three mutually perpendicular axes (OA, OB, OC,) in space. Con ceive this space to be filled with matter whose density distribution is the total utility for A , B, and C ,relative to a particular individual I. There may be " empty ” portions of space. The locus of points representing combinations of A , B , and C , possessing a given utility will be an indifference surface. All such loci will form a “ family " of concentric surfaces like the coats of an onion around one or more points of maxima. Lay off on the A axis OA , equal to as many units of A as can be bought for the sum of money disposable by I for the purchase of A , B , and C. Lay off OB and OG similarly defined . Draw the plane A B C . This is the locus* of all consumption-combinations of A , B , and C, purchasable with the given sum of money. It is a “ partial income plane.” Its point of tangency with an indifference surface will mark the chosen combination. A normal at this point indicates the “ maximum direction ” and its A , B , and C components are the marginal utilities, proportional to the prices of A , B , and C. § 2. The utility distributions may be very complicated. If the three articles are substitutes like oats, corn , and rye, the indifference sur faces may be almost plane and will allow but little change in the orientation of the partial income plane, while each slight change shifts the point of tangency greatly (cf. fig . 20 for two dimensions). If they are completing articles as cuffs, collars, and ties the indiffer ence surfaces are arranged like concentric cocoons directed toward the origin (cf. fig . 22 for two dimensions). But the three articles may be more intricately related in utility. Of tea, coffee and sugar, the first two are substitutes while the last is completing to both . If this triple completing and competing rela tion of articles were “ perfect,” the utility distribution would reduce to a plane passing through the origin and cutting between the “ sugar ” and “ tea ” axes, also between the “ sugar ” and “ coffee ” axes. Several characteristics of such an ideal utility dependence would exist. If the triple dependence is not “ perfect ” the plane referred to swells out into a flat disk or rather a “ family ” of con centric disks. The triple variation of prices and its effects on the A B C ñ = 1, whence : A . * For its equa. is a + OB5 + oc or Apa + Bpo + Cpc = 50. 50 50 + B .00 OR ++ C .OC 50 = 50 78 Irving Fisher — Mathematical investigations relative amounts of the three articles (that is on the position of the point of contact) can readily be discerned by its aid . Far more complicated cases are supposable and exist in reality. $ 3. If we suppose for an instant that there are but three commodities in the market, the preceding analysis yields a complete account of the equilibrium in that market. To sketch this briefly let us suppose the space to be filled with a utility density for I, another superposed but different distribution for II, and so on . Let us include production . If one man should be both a consumer and producer of the same article,the net con sumption or production is now to be taken , and the totalutility or dis utility of this net amount is the density. The planes before referred to as partial income planes may now be called “ total income and expenditure planes,” and they must each pass through the origin * 27. (OI, fig. 27 for two dimensions). Since the “ maximum directions” (normal to their planes) are parallel, these planes must all coincide. The point in this plane selected by I will be that of tangency to an indifference surface for I. Likewise for II , III, etc. Such points * For since income balances expenditure, if A1, B , C , represent the (net) amounts consumed or produced by I, those consumed being treated as positive, and those produced as negative, the whole money value must be zero : i. e. A . Pa + B . Po + C . P . = 0 , which is the equation of a plane passing through the origin . in the theory of value and prices. could be found whatever the position of the plane. But the plane must assume such an orientation that the center of gravity of these points shall be the origin . That is the algebraic sum of all the A coördinates consumed must equal the sum produced . Likewise the algebraic sum of the B and C coördinates must each be zero. Hence with the geometrical analysis just described the equilib rium for a market of three commodities is determined when : (1) All individuals' combinations lie in a common plane through the origin (each individual's sales and purchases cancel). (2 ) Each individual's combination is at the point where this plane is tangent to an indifference surface for that individual (the point of maximum net utility). ( 3) The points in the plane are so distributed as to make the origin their centre of gravity (the production and consumption of each com modity balance). Whence it follows geometrically that the “ maximum directions " are parallel, their components (marginal utilities) proportional as between different individuals and that this proportion is that of the orientation of the plane (the ratio of prices). When this equilibrium is attained, let us, through the point of tangency I, representing the consumption combination for I, pass a section parallel to the plane of the A and B axes. The section of this plane with the total income plane gives a straight line which is none other than the partial income line of Ch . I, § 11 and its section with the indifference surfaces gives back the indifference curves of Ch. I, $ 10. $ 5. We have temporarily assumed only three commodities for we have only three dimensions wherewith to represent them . A complete presentation of the interdependence of utilities would require m dimensions, for the utility of any one commodity A , is subject to m independent variations according to a change in any one of the m commodities, though (in general) the change of the quantity A itself is most important. There is a curious glamour over “ the fourth dimension.” The popular interest is all to prove that it “ exists.” Its origin histor ically and its present usefulness is in the interpretation of a fourth independent variation, i. e. in representing just such relations as now 80 Irving Fisher — Mathematical investigations concern us. It seems unfortunate that only mathematicians should be acquainted with this fact. $ 6. In this m dimensional space make m mutually perpendicular axes for the commodities A , B , C , . . . M . Fill the space with a total utility density. Pass an m - 1 flat* through the origin giving it the proper orientation in view of the prices. The indifference loci will be (m - 1) spaces (curved). The point of tangency of the (m - 1) flat with an (m - 1) indifference locus will indicate the total con sumption and production combination for an individual. A normal · to the (m — 1) flat and (m - 1) indifference locus at their tangency shows his “ maximum direction ” and its components the marginal utilities of all articles. These ideas are not so unfamiliar as they appear. This space is simply the “ economic world ” in which we live. We often speak of spending an income in this or that “ direction,” to express the rela tive amounts of commodities. When one speaks of the “ point” which a consumer or producer reaches, the use of the word is a natural attempt to group in thought m different magnitudes. This is accomplished by regarding them as coördinates of a “ point” in the “ economic world.” It is an application to economics of those ideas of “ multiple algebra ” which have addedt so to the beauty and simplicity of geometry and mathematical physics. These conceptions will tend to a more compact comprehension of the nature of economic equilibrium . In order to have equilibrium in the whole system including production : (1) The utility distribution must be given for each individual. (2) The “ maximum directions ” must be alike among all indi viduals and between production and consumption. (3) The origin must be the centre of gravity of all the individ ual points : that is the sum of all A coördinates for consumption must equal the sum for production and likewise for B, C, etc. (4 ) The common income and expenditure flat must pass through the origin : that is the money values of each man's production and consumption must cancel. * I. e. a Euclidean space of (m — 1) dimensions related to the m -dimensional space as a plane is to our space. + See J. W . Gibbs, Multiple Algebra, Proceedings Amer. Asso, Adv. Sci., vol. XXXV . in the theory of value and prices. $ 8. . By passing sections successively through the point I, we may nar- , row the discussion to as few variables as we choose. Wemay thus select any three and discuss them as before in real space (cf. § 4 ). § 9. ANALYTICAL. For those familiar with multiple algebra, that is with the quater nion analysis of Hamilton, the “ ausdehnungslehre ” of Grassman, or the vector analysis of Prof. J. Willard Gibbs, the foregoing geo metrical simplification will lead to a striking analytical simplifica tion .* Let I, II, . . . N , be vectors to the points I, II, . . . N from the origin. Let U ,, U ,, etc., represent the total utility at the points I, II, etc. Let vU , U , etc ., be vectors to represent in magnitude and direction the maximum rate of increase of utility at the points I, II, etc. (i. e. in tke “ maximum directions ” ). The conditions of equilibrium expressed in $ 7 become : (1) TU , = F (I) ; •U, = F ( II ) ; . . . (2) VU, « Un = F (N ) U , a v U , a . . . 0v Un (3) I + II + III + . . . + N = 0 (4 ) I . VU, = II . VU, = . . . = N . VU, = 0 The first equation represents the several utility distributions. The second means that the “ maximum directions ” are alike ; the third that the amount of each commodity produced and consumed cancel, and the fourth that for each individual the values of produc tion and consumption cancel. t -- - - -- - - - * See J. W . Gibbs' Vector Analysis, p . 16 , $ 50. + The scalar equations which the preceding vector equations replace can readily be deduced from them . Let a , b , c, etc., be unit vectors along the A , B, C, etc. axes . Multiply v U = F (I) by a , b , c , etc . respectively . Weob tain m equations of the form U , . a = F (I) . a or: ' dU JĀ. = F (A1, B1, C1, . . . . M ). Likewise m scalar equations are contained in U , = F ( II), etc. Again from (2) since v U , a v U2, VU , . a : VU , . b = VU , . a : VU , . b or: dU dU dU dU dA , - dB, - dA , AB.Z. Likewise for C ., D ., . . . M . Likewise for v U3, etc. Again (3 ) yields I . a + II , a + III , at . . . + N . a = () or Ai + A2+ A3 + . . . + Ar = 0 . Likewise for B , C , . . . M , making m equations. TRANS. CONN. ACAD., Vol. IX . JULY, 1892. 82 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations $ 10 . It is seen that analytically the treatment of interdependent com modities differ from that of independent commodities only in this, that the equations which represent the functions have more letters ; i. e. we have dU N = F (A ,, B , . .. N ,) instead of = F (A ,). All other equations are just as in Part I. In fact these function equations are, so to speak, the residuary formulæ ; they contain all the unanalyzed conditions of the problem . The marginal utilities are (as in Part I) in a continuous ratio which is the ratio of prices. Yet there are some peculiar cases which could not occur under the suppositions of Part I, viz : those cases arising when the marginal utility of one or more articles has no meaning . If two articles are perfect completing articles, as gun and trigger, there is no such quantity as the marginal utility of triggers alone. There is, however, a marginalutility of a combined gun and trigger. Now there are separate marginal disutilities for producing the gun and trigger. How are all these quantities to be introduced into our continuous proportion of marginal utilities ? Suppose for a moment there were no difficulty of this sort. The proportion for each individual would be just as before (Part I, Ch. IV , $ 10) and might be expressed as follows [G & g for gun T & t for trigger] : P. du - dG Per P, i * dU IT dG . 1 - I dT ) I P + P *dU į dū == i det dT, P, + p "QU U MG& T), Finally : It is clear that au a dUBib I = Aa + Bb + . . . + Mm and vU, = GA + (ID ) + . . . + dU . M . Mm . Substituting these values in 1 .VU, = () we have after performing the multipli cation and remembering that a , a = 1 and a . b = a . c = . . . = b . c = . . . = 0 , dU AiJA, + B , B , + . . . + M , MM , = 0 or since prices are proportional to marginal utilities: Alpe + Bip: + . . . M , Pm = 0. Likewise for II, III, etc. making n equations. Conversely we could derive the vector equations from the scalar. in the theory of value and prices. 83 The last two members of this equation are new and require a word of explanation. The next to the last is an obvious conse, quence of the principles of composition and division. Its denom inator represents the marginal utility of Gun and Trigger combined dU and is written Teen in the last member. But the quantities which are starred are those which can under our supposition no longer be said to exist. Hence all members of the equation containing a star drop out and we have left the first, second and last members. In other words, if two articles are perfectly completing their joint marginal utility is in the ratio to their joint price as the marginal disutility of producing either article is to its price (negatively ) or as every other marginal utility. is to its price. In like manner if two articles are perfect completing articles from the producer's standpoint, as beef-hides and beef-meat, their joint marginal disutility is to their joint price as the marginal utility of either is to its price (negatively ) or as any marginal utility is to its price. If two articles are such that they are perfect completing both as to production and consumption and in the same ratios, they not only have no separate utilities or disutilities but they can have no separate prices. Thus, the head, limbs, tail and other parts of a horse are produced together and consumed (used) together ; they have no separate price. It is impossible for articles to exist which are perfect completing articles both for consumption and production but are produced in one ratio and consumed in another. Suppose two articles are such that the production of one is per fectly completing to the consumption of the other. Suppose, for instance, that the production of a ton of iron involves the consump tion of a ton of coal, and that the consumption of the ton of coal also implies the production of a ton of iron. The iron producer in this case could not be said to have utility for more coal so long as he does not produce more iron, nor can he be said to have disutility of producing more iron without consuming more coal. What utilities or disutilities then does he have ? He may be said to have a joint marginal disutility of producing iron and consuming coal. This “ joint ” disutility is to the difference of the prices of iron and coal as themarginal utility of any commodity to him is to its price. Like principles apply to three or more perfectly completing articles. As long as articles are not perfectly completing there is 84 i tical nvestigations Irving Fisher - Mathema no need for the substitution of joint utilities for single ones. As a matter of fact the number of really perfectly completing articles is relatively small. If two articles are “ perfect ” substitutes for consumption and the ratio of their marginal utilities is the same for all consumers, while from a producers standpoint they are not “ perfect” substitutes, the consumers fix the ratio of their prices (viz : that of their marg. ut.) and the producers produce quantities accordingly . But the quan tities of each consumed by different individuals is entirely indeter minate. · Thus the milk from each cow may be regarded as a sep arate commodity. The consumer is indifferent to which milk he drinks, and purely accidental causes determine how much of each he gets ; the producer, however, milks determinate amounts from each cow . If two articles are perfect substitutes both for production and consumption and the ratio of their marginal utilities and of their marginal disutilities are all alike their prices will have this ratio , but the relative quantities of each produced and consumed is entirely indeterminate ; (e. g. the colors in the binding of a book ). If two articles are perfect substitutes and the ratio of their mar ginal utility of the first to the second is for every consumer greater than the ratio of their marginal disutilities to all producers, the first commodity alone will be produced and consumed and its price will be determined as for any commodity. In general if two articles are perfect substitutes, but the ratio of their marginal utilities and the ratio of their marginal disutilities is different for different individuals, those to whom the ratio of mar ginal utilities of the first to the second is greater than the ratio of their prices will consume only the first, those whose utility ratio is less than the price ratio will consume only the second, those whose disutility ratio is greater than the price ratio will produce only the second ; those for whom it is less, only the first.* In this case the price of each article is determined just as usual, but for each indi vidual who does not consume or produce one or the other, its mar ginal utility or disutility simply fails to have meaning and drops out of the equations ; just as in Part I, occasionally a cistern may be entirely out of the tank water. - - - - - - - -- - - - - * If some producers and consumers should have their utility or disutility ratio identical with the price ratio the relative amounts produced and consumed are indeterminate to the extent of this coincidence. in the theory of value and prices. 85 CHAPTER III. MECHANICAL ANALOGIES. $ 1. For each individual situated in the “ economic world ,” suppose a vector drawn along each axis to indicate the marginal utility in that “ direction .” The marginal utility of consuming (a ) is a vector positive along the A axis, the marginal disutility of producing (a ) (or the disutility of paying money for a) is an equal vector in the opposite direction. In like manner the marginal utilities and disutilities along all axes are equal and opposite. This corresponds to the mechanical equilibrium of a particle the condition of which is that the component forces along all perpen dicular axes should be equal and opposite. Moreover wemay combine all the marginal utilities and obtain a vector whose direction signifies the direction in which an individual would most increase his utility. The disutility vector which indi cates the direction in which an individual would most increase the disutility of producing. These two vectors are (by evident geo metry ) equal and opposite. The above is completely analogous to the laws of composition and resolution of forces. If marginal utilities and disutilities are thus in equilibrium “ gain” must be a maximum . This is the mere application of the calculus and corresponds exactly to the physical application of the calculus which shows that at equilibrium the balancing of forces implies that energy is a maximum . Now energy is force times space, just as gain is marginal utility times commodity . $ 2. In Mechanics. A particle corresponds to Space Force Work Energy Work or Energy = force x space. Force is a vector (directed in space). Forces are added by vector addition . (“ parallelogram of forces." ) Work and Energy are scalars. In Economics. An individual. Commodity . Marg. ut. or disutility. Disutility. Utility . Disut, or Ut. = marg . ut. x commod . Marg. ut. is a vector (directed in com .) Marg. ut. are added by vector addition . (parallelogram of marg. ut.) Disut. and ut, are scalars. 86 Irviny Fisher - Mathematical investigations The total work done by a particle in | The total disutility suffered by an indi moving from the origin to a given po - vidual in assuming a given position in sition is the integral of the resisting the “ economic world ” is the integral forces along all space axes (resisting forces are those directed toward the axes (marg. disut. are directed to origin ) multiplied by the distances ward the origin ) multiplied by the moved along those axes. distances moved along those axes. of themarg. disut. along all commod . The “ total energy ” (the work done | The total utility enjoyed by theindivid upon the particle) may be defined as ual is the like integral with respect the like integral with respect to im to marg . utilities. pelling forces. The net energy of the particle may be | The net ut. or gain of the individual is defined as the “ total energy” less the the “ total utility ” less the " total “ total work ." disutility.” Equilibrium will be where net energy Equilibrium will be where gain is max is maximum ; or equilibrium will be imum ; or equilibrium will be where where the impel. and resist. forces themarg . ut, and marg . disut. along along each axis will be equal. each axis will be equal. subtracted (If “ total ut.” be subtracted from from (If “ total energy ” be “ total work " instead of vice versa total disut." instead of vice versa the difference is “ potential” and is minimum ). the difference may be called “ loss” 1 and is minimum ). CHAPTER IV . UTILITY AS A QUANTITY. $ 1. In Part I, Chap. I, Utility was defined with reference to a single individual. In order to study prices and distribution it is not neces sary to give any meaning to the ratio of twomen 's utilities. Jevons apparently did not observe this. Auspitz und Lieben did . So did George Darwin.* § 2. It would doubtless be of service in ethical investigations and pos sibly in certain economic problems to determine how to compare the utilities of two individuals. It is not incumbent on us to do this. When it is done the comparison will doubtless be by objective stand ards. If persons alike in most respects show to each other their sat --- -- - - - - -- -- - - - - - - - - * The Theory of Exchange Value. - - -- --- - - - - -- -- - Fortnightly Review , new series, xvii, 243. in the theory of value and prices. 87 isfaction by similar gestures, language, facial expression , and gen eral conduct we speak of their satisfaction as very much the same. What however this may mean in the “ noumenal ” world is a mys tery. If on the other hand differences of age, sex, temperament, etc . enter, comparison becomes relatively difficult and inappropriate . Very little could be meant by comparing the desire of a Fuegian for a shell-fish with that of a college conchologist for the same object and surely nothing is meant by comparing the desires of the shellfish itself with that of either of its tormentors. § 3. When statistics becomes a developed science it may be that the wealth of one age or country willbe compared with that of another as “ gain ” not money value. If the annual commercial product of the U . S. was in 1880 $ 9,000,000,000 * and by increased facilities for production prices are lowered so much that the product in 1890 is only valued at (say ) $8,000,000,000 it proves a gain not a loss. The country would be the richest possible when all things were as plenti ful as water, bore no price, and had a total valuation of zero. Now money value simply measures utility by a marginal standard which is constantly changing. Statistical comparison must always be rough but it can be better than that. The statistician might begin with those utilities in which men aremost alike- food utilities , and those disutilities in which they are most alike — as the disutilities of de finite sorts of manual labor. By these standards he could measure and correct the money standardt and if the utility curves for vari ous classes of articles were constructed he could make rough sta tistics of total utility, total disutility, gain , and utility-value which would have considerable meaning. Men are much alike in their di gestion and fatigue. If a food or a labor standard is established it can be easily applied to the utilities in regard to which men are unlike as of clothes, houses, furniture, books, works of art, etc. § 4. These inquiries however do not belong here. Let us instead of add ing to the meaning of utility do the very opposite and strip it of all attributes unessential to our purpose of determining objective prices - - - - -- * Edward Atkinson , Distribution of products , p . 141. + Cf. Edgeworth, On the method of ascertaining and measuring variations in the value of the monetary standard , Report of the British Association for the Advancement of Science, 1887. Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations 88 and distribution. Definition 3, Part I, Chap. I, § 4 yielded uniform results only on the assumption that the utility of each commodity was independent of the quantity of others. Similar assumptions are nec essary in geometry. A unit of length is a yard. A yard is the length of a standard bar in London. To be used it must be assumed that its length is not a function of its position nor dependent on the changes in length of other bodies. If the earth shrinks we can measure the shrinkage by the yard stick provided it has not also shrunk as a nec essary feature of the earth 's change. Definition 3 was essential in Part I to give meaning to the cisterns used. Such a definition is essen tial to the analyses of Gossen, Jevons, Launhardt, Marshall, and all writers who employ coördinates. analysis of Part II. Yet it is not necessary in the $ 5. In fig. 28 the “ lines of force ” are drawn perpendicular to the in difference loci. The directions of these lines of 28 . force are alone used in the formulæ in Ch . II, § 9 which determine equilibrium . Therefore the directions alone are important. It makes abso lutely no difference so far as the objective de termination of prices and distribution is con cerned what the length of the arrow is at one point compared with another. The ratios of the components at any point are important but these ratios are the same whatever the length of the arrow . Thus we may dispense with the total \B utility density and conceive the “ economic world ” to be filled merely with lines of force or “ maximum directions.” § 6. Even if we should give exact meanings to the length of these ar rows (so that the equation v U , = F (I) should signify not only that for each position in the economic world a definite “ maximum direc tion ” exists but also that the rate of increase of utility or the length of the vector along this line is given ) — even then there would not be a complete primitive U = P (I) unless certain conditions were ful filled .* These conditions are ( 1) that the lines of force are so ar ranged that loci (surfaces in two dimensions , m - 1 spaces in m di mensions) perpendicular to them can be constructed , and (2) that * Osborne, Differential Equations, p. 12 . . in the theory of value and prices. 89 the rate of passing from one locus to the next along a line of force shall for all positionsbetween the two loci be inversely proportional to the value of v U , already assigned to these positions. If v U , is not distributed in the above manner integration is impossible and there is no such quantity as total utility or gain . $ 7. Even if the integration were possible there would still be an arbi trary constant. We could even claim that total disutility exceeds total utility and all man can do is to minimize the disagreeable in stead of maximize the agreeable. In other words, if we embrace hedonism , there is nothing in economic investigation to cause us to choose between optimism and pessimism . $ 8. Thus if we seek only the causation of the objective facts of prices and commodity distribution four attributes of utility as a quantity are entirely unessential, (1 ) that one man 's utility can be compared to another's, (2) that for the same individual the marginal utilities at one consumption-combination can be compared with those at another , or at one time with another, ( 3) even if they could , total utility and gain might not be integratable, (4 ) even if they were, there would be no need of determining the constants of integration . END OF PART II. 90 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations APPENDIX I. MISCELLANEOUS REMARKS ON PART I. 1. FAILURE OF EQUATIONS. Jevons (p. 118 ) discusses the failure of equations for simple ex change. It is clear that such failure must frequently occur in com plex exchanges butno one has apparently commented on it. It would seem at first sight that this would introduce an indeterminate element into our results. Such however is not the case unless we take account of articles neither produced nor consumed ; then the highest price which any consumer will pay for the first infinitesimal is less than the lowest price at which any one will produce it ; there is no pro duction nor consumption and the term price has no determinate meaning. As soon as changes in industrial conditions, that is in the shape of the cisterns or their numbermakes this inequality into an equality, the article enters into our calculations. Suppose A is produced by n , people, consumed by now , and ex changed or retailed by nic, where N . , Ny and n are each less than n (the number of individuals.) Moreover from the nature of our former suppositions if any of the three are greater than zero all must be, for anything once in the system is supposed to be produced , exchanged and consumed within the given period of time. The number of people who do not produce A is n - n. exchange A is n - ne, consume A is n - nr. The number of unknowns dropped out of the equations in Ch. VI, § 2 , is 3n - (n. +ne+ nr) of the type A , Ale, Ak, etc., dU and 3n - (n. + na + nx) of the type ZA , or 6n — 2 (n + n + nn) altogether. . The failing equations in the first set are none, 06 66 « 66 " 65 second third 66 none, 66 " fourth “ 31 - (n + n + n ), 66 fifth « none, 6 3n - (notnetnx), or 6n — 2(n + ne+ n .) altogether. From the above agreement it appears that there can be no indeter minate case under the suppositions which were first made. Let us look at this somewhat more closely. in the theory of value and prices. 91 In the fourth set of equations there are really n (3m - 1) (0 2 ) separate equations but only n3m – 1) are independent. Which shall be selected is a matter of convenience. Wemay make every equa tion contain Pan for instance and write du Par : P6,1 = A. du • OR du = a WAT2 dU : 2D - - = etc . T 2 Par : Per = etc. . .. .. .. .. . Paso : Pax = , . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Pan : Page = , . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Now from the first two equations wemay derive by division dU Por :Pes = dB dU . 2C , ' but we might wish to use this last as one of the n (3m - 1 )3mindepen dent equations, if A1, should “ fail.” From the n ( 3m - 1) -6 sepa rate equations we are at liberty to select for use any n (3m – 1) inde pendentones; and if in this selection there occur any which by some change of quantities fail, we are compelled to change our selection so that the new n (3m - 1) equations shall avoid the “ failing ” magni tudes. This is interpreted in the mechanism as follows : when a cistern is wholly above the surface of the tank (as IIIC fig . 8) and so con tains nothing, the quantity of commodity and its utility “ fail.” The levers which keep the ordinates in proportion to the corresponding ordinates of other individuals may be far more numerous than the levers pictured in former diagrams. Thus for four cisterns there may be six levers (by joining each pair) but only three are neces sary . The “ failure ” of any magnitudes will not invalidate any system of levers originally selected ; it will simply make their num ber greater than necessary. II. THE CISTERNS AND DIAGRAMS OF PART I COMPARED WITH THE DIAGRAMS OF JEVONS AND OF AUSPITZ UND LIEBEN . $ 1. In order to represent geometrically the relations between quantity of commodity ,marginal utility , total utility, and gain (any two of which four magnitudes are determined by a specified relation between 92 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations the other two) it is only necessary to have a plane curve of appro priate form and to represent any two of the above economic magni tudes by any two geometrical magnitudes determined by the posi tion of points in the curve. Out of the numerous possible methods thus included , the one se lected for the preceding discussion was to representmarginal utility by the Cartesian ordinate and commodity by the area included be tween the curve, the axes of coördinates, and the abscissa drawn from the point. $ 2. In order to show the connection between this system of coördi nates and those of Jevons and of Auspitz und Lieben , the following scheme is presented : Jevons. Auspitz & Liehen . The new curves. = fædy Commodity - -- - = x ; Marginal .... = y; utility Ś -Total , sygda, = ya = Syædy Gain .- .- = Ya — Xa = fyxdy - yfædy utility s - = Sy;də ; — X;Y ; aya = tan 0 = y 30. 32. n có in the theory of value and prices. 34 . 33 . to : 93 X Aire lo x y These curves are shown in figs. 29 and 30 (Jevons), 31, 32 ( Aus pitz und Lieben ), and 33, 34 (new ). The first in each case is for consumption the second for production.* $ 3. If Jevons' curve for consumption becomes a straight line, fig. 35 , its equation is:t X ;+ 99; = m . Using the preceding table substituting for x, and Y; we get in Auspitz und Lieben coördinates : 36 . 35. 37. dya = in , 3 , - dan which integrated gives 299. = 2mx, - + C. Since the curve must evidently pass through the origin, C = 0, and using new constants wemay write : Ya = « X — Bxa", which is a parabola (fig. 36 ). * Jevons used no production curve. The one drawn is inserted to complete the comparison. Fleeming Jenkins? “ Demand and Supply” curves are the same as Jevons save that price replaces marginal utility . + Gossen , Launhardt, Whewell, and Tozer (the last two use no geometric analy sis) employ such a linear supposition, though the meanings of their variables are not identical. # Launhardt's equation . Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations 94 For the new coördinates the substitutions from the table give : Fædy + ay = m , 2C == - 9, which reduces to a straight line parallel to the axis of ordinates (fig . 37). The Auspitz und Lieben curve does not reveal to the eye the spe cial supposition (that commodity and marginal utility change pro portionally ). If we suppose that marginal utility decreases at a con stant rate in relation to constant second differences of commodity, the new diagram reduces to a straight line : 2 - 17 - M = 0, while the other curves would be : and (ya + Ax, + B )' = C (D - x,)* <; = E - Fy; - Gy;'. $ 4. The value of Jevons' diagram consists in the use of a simple and familiar system of coördinates (the Cartesian ) as representing the two chief economic quantities, and is probably the best for elemen tary purposes. The value of Auspitz und Lieben ’s diagram together with a “ derivative ” curve* not shown above consists chiefly in the ease with which maxima are discovered and the clear association of maxima with equality of marginal utilities. It is believed that the third method will, by means of its applicability to the mechanisms of Part I, more clearly reveal the interdependence of the many com modities of many individuals and of their many utilities. $ 5. The properties which are essential to the curve we have adopted are : First. That the curve shall never admit of being intersected twice by a horizontal line (i. e. that it shall not cease to run in a general up and down manner), to express the fact for consumption thatmar ginal utility decreases as quantity of commodity increases and for production thatmarginal disutility increases as the quantity of com modity increases. - -- - d and yyaa ayxaa * Whose Cartesian coördinates are x , and . in the theory of value and prices. 95 Second. That the curve shall approach the axis of ordinates asymptotically and in such a manner that the whole area between it and the axis is finite, to express the fact that marginal utility becomes infinitely minus for consumption of, and infinitely plus for production of finite limiting quantities of commodity .* Third. The curves begin (have commodity equal to zero ) at a finite vertical distance from the origin . (These assumptions are less generally true of production than of consumption , but they have been here employed throughout.) $ 6. It is evident that in comparing the forms of curves for different articles their differences and peculiarities are determined in a most delicate fashion by the form of the curve . . . far more delicately than, with our present statistical knowledge, is necessary. Observe, then , what the abscissa of our curve stands for. An infinitely thin layer ædy is the amount additional demanded (or supplied) in response to an infinitesimal decrease (or increase) dy in marginal utility . The abscissa x is the ratio of the infinitesimal layer ædy to the infinitesimal change of price, dy. It is therefore the rate of increase of quantity demandedt (or supplied ) in relation to change of marginal utility. AM (figs. 2 and 3) is the initial rate. Consulting II, § 2 of this appendix, we see that ae; = f xdy Hence , But Hence da; = wdy y = y; and dy = dy; dæ ; – X . That is the abscissa of our curve is the tangential direction in Jevons' curve, considered with respect to the axis of ordinates. Hence if Jevons' curve be subjected to the condition of being convex, the new curve must have the simple condition that succes sive abscissas diminish , etc., etc . $ 7. Hitherto nothing has been said as to the mode of representing total utility and gain , If y, is the marginal utility (which may be figured in money) at which a consumer actually ceases to buy, y, that at which he would * Cf. Auspitz und Lieben . pp. 7 and 11. + Cf. foot note Ch . IV , § 8 , div . 3 . 96 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations m just begin to buy, then his consumer's rent or gain is (see Ch. I, § 8) G = Syk % yæ dy –y, S % zdy ormeasuring this gain in the given commodity as valued at y, cents (say) per unit, PYiy x dy G ry, a dy . y Jyry " " Yx This may be interpreted by a simple geometrical construction . In fig. 38 OA = Yx and OR = y . 38. Cr. Z . - 22 21 Selecting the point 3 make the evident dotted construction deter mining a point 5. 07 05 Y Evidently: 7375 = 04 = OR = 5 . 70 = 17, . ] Let 3 assume all positions from M to 6. Then 5 will trace a curve 26 . The area described by the moving line 73 is evidently / 91xdy. The area described by the moving line 75 is evidently - 2 ) dy. Ya ly Hence area described by themoving line 35 is the difference of these expressions or G /y ,. That is the area M62 represents the gain measured in commodity. Thus suppose a person buys corn measured by RAM6 and let corn at the valuation RO be the unit of utility. It is only the last layer R6 on which no gain is felt. For any preceding layer 75 the price really paid is OR while the price which it is worth to him is 07. The layer 73 may be considered as lengthened in his eyes by that in the theory of value and prices. 97 ratio 07/0R so that by getting it at less than he was willing to pay, he has gained the element 35 measured in corn. His gain is maxi mum when he purchases such a quantity that its final utility equals its price. Fig. 39 applies to “ producer's rent ” or “ gain,” substituting “ sale ” for “ purchase ” ; “ sell ” for“ buy.” To express the gain in money the area M26 must be multiplied by the price. On each cistern construct the curve 62 (fig. 38) and con sider the area RA26 to move front and back one unit (say one inch ) so as to trace a volume (fig . 40) adjacent to the front cistern and 40. ^ again to move pinches further back so as to trace a volume adjacent to the back cistern . The front volume gives again the total utility measured in com modity . The back volume gives the totalutility measured in money. That is the whole back cistern and its adjacent volume represent the money which if the individual paid he would neither gain nor lose, provided his marginal valuation of it is unchanged by the operation. The cistern portion is the money he actually pays and the outside volume 7 , 10, 12, 9, 8 , 11 is his “ gain .” Likewise for the producer. III. GAIN A MAXIMUM . $ 1. In the case of a single individual distributing a fixed income over various commodities under fixed prices the distribution actually TRANS. Conn. ACAD., Vol. IX . JULY, 1892. tical Irving Fisher - - Mathema 98 ations investig attained and specified in Part 1 yields the maximum total utility , for, since (Ch. IV , $ 2 ): dU dU dU dU da, = dm , PaidB, = dm , Poz.. . therefore : du du du dA, - dB, _ _ AM , (1) Pa - Po = . . . = Pm The numerators are the marginal utilities per unit of commodity. To divide by the price is to make the unit of commodity the dollar's worth. Each fraction is thus the marginal utility per dollar's worth . The equation expresses the fact that the rate of increase of utility from spending more money on any one commodity equals the rate of increase for any other . Hence by a familiar theorem of the cal culus the total utility must be the maximum attainable by any dis tribution of a fixed income. In like manner the individual dis tributes his production so that the marginal disutilities in all modes of producing dollar's worth of commodity are equal so that his total disutility is a minimum . Hence the difference between his total utility and total disutility or his economic gain is a maximum . $ 2. In the distribution of a single commodity over many individuals since : NU AU dU ZU DU AU dA, – dm , · Pai QA = dm . · Pa; . . . ; JA . = im Pa, therefore, du du AU dA dA, dA . (2) DƯ = ZU = . . . . = DU ' dmn dm , dm , that is, themarginal utilities (when the unit of utility is the marginal utility of money for each individual) are equal and the total utility is maximum . In like manner the total disutility is a minimum and gain therefore a maximum . $ 3. The first continuous equation may be divided by dU and the in the theory of value and prices. 99 second by P, and since the first members will become identical we have a common continuous equation : dU dA , dU dU dA , dB, dm , · - = ... = - = etc. dm , · Pa dm , . ? (3) that is, the marginal utilities of all commodities to all consumers are equal when the unit of utility is the marginal utility of money and the unit of commodity the dollar 's worth . Hence the total utility in whole market thus measured is a maximum .* § 4. However it may justly be objected that the marginal utility of money to one person is not equatable to that of another, that is that it is unfair to use the unit of utility for the poor man the high mar ginal utility of his small income and add the smallnumber of such large units in a poor man's gain to the corresponding rich man ’s gain in which the unit of measure is small and the number of units large. If we suppose by some mysterious knowledge an exact equiv alence of utilities were possible between different individuals (see Part II, Ch. IV , $ 2 ) and by some equally mysterious device of socialism we could without changing the aggregate commodities alter their distribution so as to make the whole market utility a maximum our condition would be [ dU _ dU dA = dd = etc . (4) This could be brought about by a change in the relative incomes , taking from the rich and giving to the poor until dU dU dm , — dm , which applied to equation (3) will evidently afford the required (4 ), or by breaking down the condition of uniformity of price and mak ing each man's price inversely as his marginal utility of money, which applied to (3) will evidently yield (4). To interpret equation 4 in the mechanism we may alter the posi tion of the stoppers in fig . 8 until the ordinates in each front and back row are equal. (This will not be when “ incomes are equally divided ” nor when “ gains ” are equal, for persons differ in their power of enjoyment, and it would still be true that those whose * Cf. Auspitz und Lieben , p . 23 and 435 . 100 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations capacities for pleasure were great would consume the most in order to make the aggregate gain in the whole market a maximum ). Or wemay destroy all the levers and re-arrange the rear thicknesses until the front and back ordinates are made equal. In like manner the minimum disutility would be attained if all marginal disutilities were equal. The maximum gain would then result. This is the maximum gain obtainable when the amounts of each commodity consumed and produced are fixed and given . If we are permitted to rearrange these amounts also , we shall secure the maximum gain when the marginal utilities equal the marginal disutilities ; i. e . dUdU dU NA1, A ,* DA,, Under such a socialistic regime more “ necessaries ” and less “ luxuries ” would be consumed and produced than previously . The “ rich ” or powerful would produce more and consume less than previously ; the poor or weak would consume more and produce less. Yet for each the marginal utilities and disutilities would be equal. It is needless to say that these considerations are no plea for socialism , but they serve to clear up a subject sometimes discussed by mathematical economists and reconcile Launhardt's contention* that utility is not a maximum with Auspitz und Lieben 's that it is. The former unconsciously has reference to equation (4) which is not true, the latter to equation (3) which is.f IV . ELIMINATION OF VARIABLES. The four sets of equations, Part I, Ch. IV , $ 10 , can be reduced. TU . Wemay substitute for itsvalue F (A,) and thus eliminate allmar ginal utilities. Moreover we can get an expression for Pa, Po, etc., in terms of commodities. First, if m = n the second set of equa tions are easily solved by determinantst giving :: * Volkswirthschaftslehre under “ Widerholte Tausch . " + Auspitz und Lieben appear to overlook this difference of standpoint. Preface, p . xxv . Burnside and Panton . Theory of Equations, p. 251. . S This equation does not mean that any arbitrary values can be assigned to A2, B ,, etc., and the resulting price of A be so simply expressed ; only when A1, Bı, etc. satisfy all the conditions of Ch .'IV , $ 10 will the price be expressible as the quotient of the two determinants . 101 in the theory of value and prices. - ( KK, B, . .. M ) ( A , B, . . . M ) . K , B, . . ..D M , }L , A , B, . . . M , Į { . -- - -. ... . ...... 'y į A , BB,e . . . My - | K, B , . . . M , - Pa = in which obviously in general a change in A will produce a greater influence on pathen an equal change in B , etc. But it shows clearly that pa is not a function of A alone. Usually n > m . Hence we may use the first m equations of the second set, or in fact any m equations. The resulting determinant quotients must be equal and must equal also the several like determinates for production. The corresponding values of Po, po, ctc., may be found and may be substituted in the fourth set. If wherever A , now occurs in the fourth set, we substitute K . - A , - A , - . . . - A , from the first set, and likewise for B ,, etc., the resulting fourth set is self-sufficient. Wehave thus eliminated ; dU the variables T , etc., Pa, etc., A , B ,, etc., and have gotten rid of the first, second and third set of equations. We can proceed no further, however, until the explicit forms of the functions F ( A ), etc., are given. APPENDIX II. LIMITATIONS OF THE PRECEDING ANALYSIS. $ 1. No pretense is made that the preceding analysis is perfect or ex haustive. There is no such analysis of any phenomena whatever even in physics. The suppositions in Ch. II, § 2 of Part I, are of course ideal. They only imperfectly apply to New York City or Chicago. Ideal suppositions are unavoidable in any science . In fact it is an evidence of progress when the distinction between the ideal and the actual arises.* Even in hydrostatics the assumption of per fect fluidity is never fully realized . The physicist has never fully explained a single fact in the universe. He approximates only . The economist cannot hope to do better. Somewriters, especially those of the historical school are disposed to carp at the introduc tion of a refined mathematical analysis. It is the old story of the ---- - -- - - - -- * See Prof. Simon Newcomb . The Method and Province of Pol. Econ. , N . Am . Rev ., CCXI, IX . 102 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations “ practical” man versus the scientist. A sea -captain can sail his vessel and laugh at the college professor in his elaborate explanation of the process. What to him is all this resolution of forces and velocities which takes no account of the varying gusts of wind, the drifting of the keel, the pitching and tossing, the suppositions which makes of the sail an ideal plane and overlook the effect of the wind on the hull ? There is no need to point the moral. Until the economist is reconciled to a refined ideal analysis he cannot profess to be scientific. After an ideal statical analysis the scientist may go further and reintroduce one by one the considerations at first omitted. This is not the object at present in view . But it may be well to merely enumerate the chief of these limitations. $ 2. In Part I the utility of A was assumed to be a sole function of the quantity of A , and in Part II a function of all commodities con sumed by a given individual. We could go on and treat it as a function of all commodities produced and consumed, treating not net production for each article, but the actual amounts separately produced and consumed by the given individual. Again we could treat it as a function of the quantities of each commodity produced or consumed by all persons in the market. This becomes important when we consider a man in relation to the members of his family or consider articles of fashion as dia monds,* also when we account for that (never thoroughly studied ) interdependence, the division of labor. This limitation has many analogies in physics. The attraction of gravity is a function of the distance from the center of the earth. A more exact analysis makes it a function of the revolution of the earth, of the position and mass of the moon (theory of tides) and finally of the position, and mass of every heavenly body. $ 3. Articles are not always homogeneous or infinitely divisible. To introduce this limitation is to replace each equation involving mar ginal utilities by two inequalities and to admit an equilibrium inde terminate between limits.† As an extreme case we may imagine an article of which no one desires more than a single copy as of a book . The utility of (say) Mill's Pol. Econ. is considerably greater than * See David Wells, Recent Economic Changes, on Diamonds. + Auspitz und Lieben , 117 – 136 and 467. in the theory of value and prices. 103 its cost, but the utility of a second copy is considerably less than its cost. In the aggregate market, however, there will be a mar. ginal person whose utility is very close to the price. A change in price will not alter the amount purchased by everyone, but will alter the number of purchasers.* § 4. Producing, consuming and exchanging are discontinuous in time. The theory of utility when applied to a single act of production or consumption or of sale or purchase, is independent of time, or rather the time element is all accounted for in the form of the utility function.f But an analysis of a number of such acts must take account of their frequency. The manner in which the time element enters has puzzled not a few economists. An example from physics may not be amiss. In the kinetic theory of gases the pressure on the walls of the containing vessel is explained by its continual bombardment by molecules. But an apparent difficulty must be observed. A rebound of a molecule involves the idea of momentum only while that which we wish to explain is pressure or force which is not by any means momentum , but momentum divided by time. How does this time enter ? By regarding not one but many molecules and taking account of the frequency of their collision. The average momentum of each blow divided by the average interval between the blows is the pressure sought. So a produce exchange is a channel connecting production and con sumption . Instead of an even flow of one bushel per second, the machinery of the exchange is such that by an instantaneous blow of a bat, so to speak, a thousand bushes are knocked along. Time is in appropriate to explain the single blow but necessary to explain the many. § 5. The ideal statical condition assumed in our analysis is never satis fied in fact. No commodity has a constant yearly rate of production or con sumption. Industrial methods do not remain stationary. Tastes and fashions change. Panics show a lack of equilibrium . Their explanation belongs to the dynamics of economics. But we have * The analysis of H . Cunynghame in the Ec. Jour., March ’92 , applies to this case . + Cf. Jevons, 63 – 68 . 104 Irving Fisher , Mathematical investigations again a physical analogue. Water seeks its level, but this law does not fully explain Niagara. A great deal of special data are here necessary and the physicist is as unfit to advise the captain of the Maid of the Mist as an economist to direct a Wall street speculator. The failure to separate statics from dynamics appears historically * to explain the great confusion in early physical ideas. To make this separation required the reluctant transition from the actual world to the ideal. The actual world both physical and economic has no equilibrium . “ Normal” + price, production and consumption are sufficiently intricate without the complication of changes in social structure. Some economists object to the notion of “ normal” as an ideal but unattainable state. They might with equal reason object to the ideal and unattainable equilibrium of the sea. The dynamical side of economics has never yet received system atic treatment. When it has, it will reconcile much of the present apparent contradiction , e. g. if a market is out of equilibrium , things may sell for “ more than they are worth ,” as every practical man knows, that is the proper ratios of marginal utilities and prices are not preserved . $ 6. We have assumed a constant population. But population does change and with it all utility functions change. An analysis whose independent variable is populationſ leads to another department of economics . In the foregoing investigation the influence of popula tion was included in the form of the utility function. So also with all causes physical, mental and social not dependent on the quantities of commodities or services. Individuals are not free to stop consuming or producing at any point. Factory operatives must have uniform working hours. The marginal undesirability of the last hour may for some workmen equal, for others exceed or fall short of the utility of its wages. $ 8. No one is fully acquainted with all prices nor can he adjust his actions to them with the nicety supposed ; both these considerations are starting points for separate discussion . * Whewell, Hist. Induct. Sci., I, 72 –3 and 186 . + Marshall, p . 84 . See article of Prof. J . B . Clark . Distribution as determined by a law of rent. Quart. Jour. Econ., Apr. '91, p . 289. in the theory of'value and prices. 105 The “ fundamental symmetry of supply and demand worked out by Auspitz und Lieben should not bind us to the fundamental asymmetry. The symmetry enables us to investigate the general dependence of consumption and production but special investigation of production , e. g. of railroad rates should be independently pur sued . (1.) Production of a commodity always precedes its consumption . (2 .) The maximum advantage in production involves few com modities for each individual, in consumption many. (3.) Increasing social organization intensifies the former fact not the latter. (4.) There are more successive steps in production than consump tion . (5 ) Social organization intensifies this distinction . (6) Owing to (4) and (5 ) service rather than commodity becomes increasingly the unit in production. (7.) Freedom to leave off consuming at any point is greater than for producing. (8.) Social organization intensifies this. (9.) Combination and monopoly are more feasible and frequent in production than in consumption . ( 10 .) In production the distinction of fixed charges and running expenses often plays an important rôle. This deserves a separate treatment. The transportation charges on a steamship are not what it costs to transport an extra ton but it is this quantity plus the pro portionate share of that ton in the fixed charges (interest, insurance , etc ). That is, the marginal cost of service involves the margin of capital invested as well as the marginal cost of running the ship ) (which is purely nominal). This is so in theory of railroad rates but the railroad investor cannot foresee the results of his enterprise as well nor can he change his road when built from one route to another as a steamship can do. To apply the theory to railroads assumes that railroad projectors know what the traffic will be. Con sequently the proper discussion of railroad rates, assuming that the railroads are already built, takes no account of fixed charges but becomes formulated as “ what the traffic will bear." * A complete theory of the relation of cost of production to price in its varying and peculiar ramifications is too vast a subject to be treated here. * See Hadley, Railroad Transportation . 106 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations § 10. It has been assumed throughout this investigation that marginal utility decreases as quantity of commodity increases. This is not always true, e. g. it is obviously not true of intoxicating liquors. A study of the liquor traffic would require a somewhat different treatment from that of most other commodities. Still less is it always true that marginal cost of production always increases as the quantity produced increases. It is clearly not true that it costs more in a shoe factory to produce the second shoe than it costs to produce the first . Yet it is probably quite generally true that at the actual margin reached in business the disutility of extending the business grows greater. When this is not true and when it is not true that marginal utility decreases as quantity of commodity in . creasess an instability is theresult. The matter of instability is one element at the bottom of the present industrial tendency toward trusts and pools. $ 11. There is no isolated market. Not only this but a “ market ” itself is an ideal thing. The stalls in the same city meat market may be far enough apart to prevent a purchaser from behaving precisely as if he stood before two counters at once . The relation of the counters ten feet apart differs in degree rather than in kind from the relation of London to New York. APPENDIX III. THE UTILITY AND HISTORY OF MATHEMATICAL METHOD IN ECONOMICS. $ 1. Mathematics possesses the same kind though not the same degree of value in every inquiry. Prof. B . Peirce,* in his memorable Linear Associative Algebra , says : “ Mathematics is the science which draws necessary conclusions. * * * * * Mathematics is not the discoverer of laws, for it is not induction , neither is it the framer of theories for it is not hypothesis, but it is the judge over both. * * * * * It deduces from a law all its consequences. Mathematics under this definition belongs to every inquiry , moral as well as physical. Even the rules of logic by which it is rigidly bound could not be deduced without its aid. The laws of argu * Amer. Jour. Math ., IV., p. 97. in the theory of value and prices. 107 ments admit of simple statement, but they must be curiously trans posed before they can be applied to the living speech and verified by observation. In its pure and simple form the syllogism cannot be directly com pared with all experience, or it would not have required an Aristotle to discover it. It must be transmuted into all the possible shapes in which reasoning loves to clothe itself. The transmutation is the mathematical process in the establishment of the law ." * I make this quotation for I believe many persons, especially econo mists, do not understand the character of mathematics in general, They imagine that a physicist can sit in his study and with the cal culus as a talisman spin out some law of physics. Some economists have hoped for a similar mysterious use of mathematics in their own science . $ 2. · We must distinguish carefully between what may be designated as mathematics and mathematical method. The former belongs, as Prof. Peirce says, to every science. In this sense economics has always been mathematical. The latter has reference to the use of symbols and their operations. It is this which is to be discussed here. A symbol may be a letter, a diagram , or a model. All three are used in geometry and physics.f By an operation on symbols is meant a rule the formulation of which depends on the mention of those symbols (as the operation of differentiation). To employ mathematical method is to pass from what is given to what is required by the aid of such a rule. To avoid mathematical method is to do it without the rule. Symbols and their operations are aids to the human memory and imagina tion . $ 3. The utility of mathematical method is purely relative, as is all utility. It helps greatly some persons, slightly others, is even a hindrance to some. Before a schoolboy studies “ mechanics ” he is usually given in his arithmetic problems of uniform motion . It would sorely puzzle him if he were compelled to use the formula s = ut. The employ ment of symbols has for him only disutility. But when in * Cf. Grassmann, Ausdehnungslehre, Introduction. + Few are aware how important models sometimes are in the treatment of these sciences. Maxwell's model to represent the relations of volume, entropy and energy in thermodynamics is an excellent example. 108 Irving Fisher — Mathematical investigations “ mechanics ” proper a few years later the sameboy studies “ falling bodies " he finds it helpful to use the formula v = gt which contrasts. with the preceding formula only in that space (s) is replaced by space per unit of time (v) and velocity (1 ) by velocity acquired per unit of time (g). The increased complexity of the magnitudes makes a formula relatively desirable. Yet for someminds the latter formula is of no use. Experience in teaching this very subject has convinced me that there are a few who understand it better without the aid of the formula , but they are just those individuals whose comprehension of the relations involved is the vaguest and the weakest. The formulæ , diagrams and models are the instruments of higher study. The trained mathematician uses them to clarify and extend his previous unsymbolic knowledge. When he reviews the mathe matics of his childhood , the elementary mechanics is to him illumined by the conceptions and notation of the calculus and qua ternions. To think of velocity, acceleration , force,as fluxions is not to abandon but to supplement the old notions and to think of momentum , work, energy, as integrals is greatly to extend them . Yet he is well aware or ought to be that to load all this on the beginner is to impede his progress and produce disgust. So also the beginner in economics might be mystified , while the advanced student is enlightened by the mathematicalmethod . $ 4. The utility of a mathematical treatment varies then according to the characteristics of the user, according to the degree of his mathe matical development and according to the intricacy of the subject handled . There is a higher economics just as there is a higher physics, to both of which a mathematical treatment is appropriate. It is said that mathematics has given no new theorems to economics. This is true and untrue according to the elasticity of our terms. The challenge of Cairnes might be answered by a counter challenge to show the contents of Cournot, Walras, or Auspitz und Lieben in any non -mathematical writer. If I may venture a speculation, those who frown on the mathe matical economistbecause he “ wraps up his mysterious conclusions in symbols ” seem to me in some cases to point their finger at those “ conclusions ” which when “ unwrapt ” of symbols they recognize as old friends and lustily complain that they are not new ; at the same time they seem to ignore completely those “ mysterious ” conclu in the theory of value and prices. 109 sions which are new because they think the former and admitted theorems exhaust all that is important on the subject. Why should the mathematician be obliged to vindicate the exercise of his science by overturning economics or by deducing some“ laws” more funda mental than those already admitted ? Elementary physics is the fundamental physics and it can be taught with little or no mathematical symbols. Advanced physics is relatively less popular while more mathematical. By actual count Ganot's elementary physics of 986 pages contains a formula for every three and one-third pages. The chapter on electricity and magnetism of 320 pages, a formula for every 44 pages, while the profound treatise.of Mascart and Joubert on Electricity and Mag netism , vol. I, of 640 pages, contains 31 formulæ for each page or 15 times as many per page as the same subject in Ganot. Similarly in economics, mathematical treatment is relatively use ful as the relations becomerelatively complicated . The introduction of mathematical method marks a stage of growth - perhaps it is not too extravagant to say, the entrance of political economy on a scien tific era . $ 5. Has the mathematical method attained a firm footing ? Before Jevons all the many attempts at mathematical treatment fell flat. Every writer suffered complete oblivion until Jevons unearthed their volumes in his bibliography. One chief reason for this is that these writers misconceived the application of mathematics. I think this was true even of the distinguished Whewell. Jevons thinks it is so of Canard though his work was crowned by the French institute. The second reason for this oblivion is that the world was not pre pared for it. The movement was too advanced and premature. Cournot certainly ,Gossen possibly, now exert considerable influence on economic thought. Marshall,whose recentbook is acknowledged to be to modern economics what Mill's was to the economics of a generation ago repeatedly expresses his admiration for and obliga tion to Cournot. Thus the mathematical method really began with Jevons in 1871. Up to this time pol. econ. had been the favorite field for those per sons whose tastes were semi-scientific and semi-literary or historical. But the scientific and literary temper are seldom equally balanced and as might have been expected after once beginning to divide they have steadily differentiated. On the one extreme is the histori 110 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations cal school of Roscher and Leslie, on the other the mathematical, deductive, or so-called Austrian school of Jevons, Menger and Walras, while the “ orthodox ” economists the legitimate successors of Adam Smith , Ricardo andMill constitute the central body from which both have split. This cleavage is, however, largely a division of the field of research rather than opposed theories or methods on the same field . The mathematical economics apparently has its warmest adherents in Austria, Italy and Denmark. France occupies the next position , while England, America and Germany have their individual enthu siasts but are still restrained largely by classic traditions. Prof. Pantaleoni thinks “ the most active movement in Italian pol. econ, is that of the new school styled rather inexactly the “ Aus trian,"* while Graziani says that the utility theory of value “ seems to close the evolutionary cycle of Italian thought.” * In England, Prof. Edgeworth, noted for his enthusiasm on mathe matical economics, has recently been elected to the chair of pol. econ. at Oxford, while Prof. Marshall is carrying forward the same movement at Cambridge. There has been a great increase in mathematico-economic litera ture since 1871. Just two decades have passed by since Jevons' epoch-making books appeared. Of the mathematico-economic writingst appearing in this period which here come to my notice, the number in the first decade was 30, representing 12 writers, while in the second decade it was 66, representing 23 writers. From all apparent evidence the mathematicalmethod has come to stay. $ 6. We can see why this is so if we glance at the work which the mathematicalmethod has already accomplished. It is perhaps fair to credit the idea of marginal utility to mathematicalmethod. This idea had five independent origins with Dupuit, Gossen, Jevons, Menger, and Walras. All except Menger presented this idea and presumably attained it by mathematical methods. No idea has been more fruitful in the history of the science. This one achievement is a sufficient vindication of the mathematical method . * Article on Economics in Italy , by Prof. Ugo Rabberio , Pol. Sci. Quart., Sept., 1891, pp. 439-473 . + I have not even included here Menger, Böhm -Bawerk and other writers of the Austrian school, who in spite of a mathematical tone have omitted to use math ematical symbols. in the theory of value and prices. 111 To pass in review all that has been done in expanding and apply ing the idea of marginal utility (and most of this expansion has been purely mathematical) would not be possible here, nor would it be possible to state all the other notions which have grown out of a mathematical treatment. It has corrected numerous errors and con fusion of thought. This correcting function has really been the chiefmission of mathematics in the field of physics though few not themselves physicists are aware of the fact. In fact the ideas of marginal utility and disutility may be re garded as corrections of two old and apparently inconsistent theories of value — the utility theory and the cost of production theory. Utility was first thought of as proportional to commodity. (That this was never explicitly assumed is a splendid illustration of how without a careful mathematical analysis in which every magnitude has definite meaning, tacit assumptions creep in and confuse the mind ). It was next pointed out that utility could not explain price since water was useful. So “ utility ” and “ scarcity ” were jointly privileged to determine price. It was Jevons clear and mathemat ical exposition of utility which showed the shallowness of the for mer discussion and brought to light the preposterous tacit assump tion , unchallenged because unseen , that each glass of water has an inherent utility independent of the number of glasses already drunk. Jevons laid emphasis on demand . Many who accepted his work were still applying the analogous errors to supply. Ricardo* had indicated the idea of marginal cost. But even Mill did not perceive its extension beyond agricultural produce. Considerable credit belongs to Auspitz und Lieben for working out the legitimate con sequences and showing by a beautiful mathematical presentation that the marginal utility theory and the marginal cost theory are not opposed but supplementary. In fact the “ margin ” itself is determined by the condition that the utility and the cost of final increments shall be equal (when measured in money). Mathematical method is to be credited with the development of the ideas of consumers' and producers' rent or gain so ingeniously applied by Auspitz und Lieben and so conspicuous in the orig inal article of Prof. J . B . Clark on the law of the three rents. t The intimate and mathematically necessary relation between the equality of marginal utilities and disutilities and the maximum sum of consumers' and producers' rent, a theorem emphasized by Auspitz und Lieben, and Edgeworth , is of course due to the mathematical instrument. * Pol. Econ., Ch. 2. + Quart. Jour. Econ ., April, 1891. 112 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations Mathematical method is making a new set of classifications based on mathematical properties. Thus the classification by Auspitz und Lieben of all commodities into three groups* is, I believe, a new one, and one suggested by, and readily discussed by the use of their diagrams. The classification of capital into free and sunk is one which is emphasized by the mathematicalwriters, as Marshall, and is bearing fruit.t I believe therefore that mathematical method has made several real contributions to economics, and that it is destined to makemore. To verify this statement I would refer the reader to the books men tioned in the bibliography among recent writers, especially Walras, Auspitz & Lieben , Marshall, Edgeworth , Wicksteed and Cunyng hame ; also , if it is proper to include those writers, who while avoiding mathematical language are interpreting and extending the same ideas, Menger, Wieser, Böhm -Bawerk, Clark and Hobson . $ 7. It may not be amiss to present a list of quotations from those who have pursued or admired the mathematical path : Whewellf says : [Mathematical method in mechanics saves scien tists three errors, viz :] “ They might have assumed their principles wrongly, they might have reasoned falsely from them in conse quence of the complexity of the problem , or they might have neglected the disturbing causes which interfered with the effect of the principal forces. * * * It appears, I think, that the sciences of mechanics and political economy are so far analogous that some thing of the same advantage may be looked for from the application of mathematics in the case of political economy.” Again :S “ This mode of treatment might be expected to show more clearly than any other within what limits and under what conditions propositions in political economy are true.” Cournot: | L' emploi des signes mathématiques , est chose naturelle toutes les fois qu'il s'agit de discuter des relations entre des gran deurs ; et lors même qu'ils ne seraient pas rigoureusement nécess aires,s'ils peuvent faciliter l'exposition , la rendre plus concise,mettre · sur la voie de développements plus étendus, prévenir les écarts * Page 46 . + See Cunynghame, Geom . Meth . of treating exchange value, monopoly , and rent. Econ . Jour. , March , ’92, p . 35 . | Cambridge Philosophical Transactions, 1830, p . 194 . S Cambridge Philosophical Transactions, 1856, p . 1 . || Principes math . de la théorie des richesses, 1838. Preface, p . viii. in the theory of value and prices. 113 d'une vague argumentation , il serait peu philosophique de les rebuter, paree qu 'ils ne sont pas également familiers à tous les lecteurs et qu 'on s'en est quelquefois servi à faux.” Gossen :* Was einem Kopernikus zur Erklärung des Zusammen seins der Welten im Raum zu leisten gelang, das glaube ich für die Erklärung des Zusammenseins der Menschen auf der Erdoberfläche zu leisten. * * * Darum ist es denn eben so unmöglich, die wahre Nationalökonomie ohne Hülfe der Mathematik vorzutragen , wie dieses bei der wahren Astronomie, der wahren Physik, Mechanik u . S. W .” Jevons:f “ I have long thought that as it deals throughout with quantities, it must be a mathematical science in matter if not in language. I have endeavored to arrive at accurate quantitative notions concerning utility, value, labor, capital, etc., and I have often been surprised to find how clearly someof the most difficult notions, especially that most puzzling of notions value, admits of mathematical analysis and expression.” Walras:f “ Je crois bien que les notations qui y sont employées paraitrout tout d'abord un pen compliquées; mais je prie le lecteur de ne ponit se rebuter de cette complication qui est inhérents au sejet et qui en constitue d'ailleurs le seule difficulté mathématique. Le système de ces notations une fois compris le systeme des phé nomènes économiques est en quelque sorte compris par cela même.” Newcomb :S “ To ultimately expect from pol. econ. results of such certainty and exactness, that it can present the legislator with numerical predictions like those we have described is by no means hopeless.” * * * * “ Mathematical analysis is simply the application to logical deduction of a language more unambiguous,more precise, and for this particular purpose, more powerful than ordinary lan guage.” Launhardt:|| “ Es ist ja die Mathematik nichts anderes als eine Sprache, welche in strenger Folgerichtigkeit die Beziehungen mess bare Dinge zu einander darstellt, was durch die gewohnliche Sprache entweder gar nicht oder doch nur in weitschweifiger ungenauer Weise erreicht werden kann." * Menschlicher Verkehr. Preface, p. v. + Preface to first edition , p . vii. # Econ. pol. pure, 1874 , Preface, p. VI. $ Themethod and province of pol. econ . [Review of Cairne's logical method in pol. econ .), N . Amer . Rev., No. CCXLIX , '1875 , p . 259. | Volkswirthschaftslehre : Preface, p. v. TRANS. Conn . ACAD., VOL. IX . JULY, 1892. 114 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations Wicksteed :* “ The diagrammatic method of studying economics may be regarded from three points of view : (I)many teachers find in it a stimulating and helpful appeal to the eye and use it as a short and telling way of making statements and registering results. ( II) a few students treat it as a potent instrument for giving pre cision to hypotheses in the first instance and then for rigorously analysing and investigating the results that flow from them . (III) a very few investigators (among whom I think we must rank Jevons), have hoped ultimately to pass beyond the field of pure hypotheses and analysis and to build up constructive results upon empirical curves of economic phenomena established by observa tion .” Foxwellt [speaking of the mathematics of Jevons and Marshall ] : “ It hasmade it impossible for the educated economist to mistake the limits of theory and practice or to repeat the confusion which brought the study into discredit and almost arrested its growth .” Auspitz und Lieben : f “ Wir haben uns bei unseren Untersuch ungen der analytischen Methode und namentlich der graphischen Darstellung bediehnt, nicht nur weil sich diese Behandlungsweise überall, wo sie überhaupt anwendbar ist, und namentlich in den naturwissenschaftlichen Fächern glänzend bewährt hat, sondern hauptsächlich auch darum weil sie eine Prazision mit sich bringt, welche alle aus vieldeutigen Wort-definitionen entspringender Miss verständnisse ausschliest.” Edgeworth : $ * * * “ the various effects of a tax or other impedi ment, which most students find it so difficult to trace in Mill's labori ous chapters, are visible almost at a glance by the aid of the mathe matical instrument. It takes Prof. Sidgwick a good many words to convey by way of a particular instance that it is possible for a nation by a judiciously regulated tariff, to benefit itself at the expense of the foreigner. The truth in its generality is more clearly contemplated by the aid of diagrams. * * * * There seems to be a natural affinity between the phenomena of supply and demand, and some of the fundamental conceptions of mathematics, such as the relation between function and variable * * * and the first principle * On certain passages in Jevons' “ Theory of pol. econ.” Quart. Jour. Econ., April, '89, p . 293. + The Economic Movement in England , Quart. Jour. Econ ., Oct., '88. † Untersuchungen. Preface, p . xiii. S Address before Brit . Assoc, as president of the section on economic science and statistics. Published in Nature, Sept. 19 , '89, p . 197. in the theory of value and prices. 115 of the differential calculus ; especially in its application to the determination of maxima and minima.” [It seems to ] “ supply to political economy what Whewell would have called appropriate and clear ' conceptions. * * * Algebra and geometry are to ordinary language in political economy somewhat as quaternions are to ordinary algebraic geometry in mathematical physics ” (Quotes Maxwell on quaternions : “ I am convinced that the introduction of the ideas as distinguished from the operations and methods * * * will be of great use.” ) Again :* “ I do not mean that the mathematical method should form part of the curriculum as we make Greek obligatory for the students of philosophy. But may we not hope that the higher path will sometimes be pursued by those candidates who offer special subjects for examination .” Marshall :f “ It is not easy to get a clear full view of continuity in this aspect without the aid either of mathematical symbols or diagrams. * * * * experience seems to show that they give a firmer grasp of many important principles than can be got without their aid ; and there are many problems of pure theory, which no one who has once learnt to use diagrams will willingly handle in any other way. The chief use of pure mathematics in economic questions seems to be in helping a person to write down quickly, shortly and exactly , some of his thoughts for his own use : and to make sure that he has enough , and only enough , premises for his conclusions (i. e. that his equations are neither more nor less in number than his unknowns). But when a great many symbols have to be used, they become very laborious to any one but the writer himself. And though Cournot's genius must give a new mental activity to everyone who passes through his hands, and mathematicians of calibre similar to his may use their favorite weapons in clearing a way for themselves to the center of some of those difficult problems of economic theory , of which only the outer fringe has yet been touched ; yet it is doubtful whether any one spends his time well in reading lengthy translations of economic doctrines into mathematics, that have not been made by himself. A few specimens of those applications of mathematical language which have proved most useful for my own purpose have, however, been added in an Appendix.” * An introductory lecture on pol. econ . delivered before the University of Oxford , Oct. 230, 1891, published in Economic Journal, Vol. i, No. 4, p. 629 . + Prin . of Econ . Preface to first Ed., p . xiv ; in 2d ed . 116 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations Cunynghame:* “ But curves play in the study of pol. econ. much the samepart as the moods and figures play in logic. They do not perhaps assist in original thought, but they afford a system by means of which error can be promptly and certainly detected and demonstrated . And as in logic so in graphic pol. econ. the chief difficulty is not to solve the problem , but to state it in geometrical language.” Contrast with the preceding the following statements from a few who can see nothing good in mathematicalmethod : A writer in the “ Saturday Review ” (Nov. 11, 1871), quoted by Prof. Edgewortht says of Jevons : “ The equations, * * * assum ing them to be legitimate, seem to us to be simply useless so long as the functions are obviously indeterminable.” [Mathematics studies relations as well as calculations. Numerical indeterminability is common even in mathematical physics.] Cairnes:f “ Having weighed Prof. Jevons's argument to the best of my ability, and so far as this is possible for one unversed in mathematics, I still adhere to my original view . So far as I can see, economic truths are not discoverable through the instrumentality of mathematics. If this view be unsound , there is at hand an easy means of refutation - the production of an economic truth , not before known, which has been thus arrived at ; but I am not aware that up to the present any such evidence has been furnished of the efficiency of the mathematical method . In taking this ground, I have no desire to deny that it may be possible to employ geometrical diagrams or mathematical formulæ for the purpose of exhibiting economic doctrines reached by other paths, and it may be that there are minds for which this mode of presenting the subject has advan tages. What I venture to deny is the doctrine which Prof. Jevons and others have advanced — that economic knowledge can be ex tended by such means ; that mathematics can be applied to the development of economic truth , as it has been applied to the devel opment of mechanical and physical truth ; and, unless it can be - - - -- - * Geometrical methods of treating exchange value, monopoly and rent. H . Cunynghame. Econ . Jour., March, '92 , p. 35 . + Math. -Psychics, p . 119. # The Character and Logical Method of pol. econ . New York, 1875 . Preface. See also, p. 122 ; also : Some leading principles of pol. econ . newly expounded. Preface . in the theory of value and prices . 117 shown either that mental feelings admit of being expressed in pre cise quantitative forms, or, on the other hand, that economic phe nomena do not depend upon mental feelings, I am unable to see how this conclusion can be avoided.” [ There are examples in Cournot, Walras, Auspitz und Lieben , Marshall, etc., which I think are fair instances of the “ production of an economic truth, not before known.” It is admitted, however, that each of these truths could have been discovered without “ mathematical method ” by some remarkably clear headed reasoner. But the same is true in physics. The deduction used in every physical truth could be reasoned out without diagrams or formulæ . A railway will best convey a man from New York to San Francisco though it is perfectly possible to walk . Cairnes certainly has an erroneous idea of the use of mathe matical method in physical investigations. Mathematics afford the physicist a complete and precise view of his subject, and this con dition of mind permits and facilitates his discovery. The discovery is only indirectly due to mathematics though it might never have been madewithout it. Cairnes apparently thinks that physical truth has been discovered by the manipulation of equations. The history of physics will not bear him out. So far as I know only one physi cal discovery was made in that way — a discovery in light. See the quotation from Peirce at the beginning of this appendix .] Wagner * [in reviewing Marshall's Prin. of Econ. ]: “ I do not believe that this mode of treating the subject has an independent value of its own for solving our problems. Indeed Marshall himself admits as much [does he ? Cf. preceding statement of Marshall.] * * * He has used diagrams and formulæ only for purposes of illustration and for greater precision of statement." [Diagrams and formulæ are never used for any other purpose yet they surely have an independent value in (say) physics. Cf. $ 1.] Ingram :f “ There is not much encouragement to pursue such researches, which will in fact never be anything more than academic playthings, and which involve the very real evil of restoring the metaphysical entities previously discarded .” Also , “ Units of animal or moral satisfaction, of utility and the like are as foreign to positive science as a unit of dormative faculty would be.” [See Part 1, Ch. I]. Also :8 “ Mathematics can indeed formulate ratios of exchange when * Quart. Jour. Ec., April. '91, p. 327. | Ency. Brit., 9th ed . Vol. xix, p. 399. Ency. Brit., 9th ed. Vol. xix , p . 386 . & Hist. Pol. Econ., New York, 1888, p. 182. 118 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations they have once been observed ; but it cannot by any process of its own determine those ratios; for quantitativeconclusions imply quan titative premises and these are wanting. There is then no future for this kind of study, and it is only waste of intellectual power to pursue it.” [What a “ therefore ” ! Why require mathematics to predict prices in order to be admitted into good society with the his torical school ? No mathematical economist has ever tried to do this. Dr. Ingram does not discuss what mathematics has done or attempted, but complains loudly that it cannot do everything and therefore has no future.] Rabberio* in speaking of Prof. Pantaleoni's Principi di Economia Pura says: “ As a monument of abstract logic, it bears fresh witness to the unusual qualities of the author's genius; but it is based on a method which , frankly speaking, I consider dangerous. In the face of pressing practical problems of every kind, both in production and in distribution , economic thought is drawn off into the field of bar ren abstractions. Under an attractive semblance of mathematical accuracy these abstractions conceal much that is really false ; for they do not correspond in the least to the complexity of concrete facts. While they distract the student with an imaginary logical construction, they lessen his interest in that positive study which tells us what is, whereas logic by itself gives us only what is thought. Thus in last result they deprive economic science of that great practical importance which it should have in society.” [ I am not acquainted with Prof. Pantaleoni's book nor with any Italian writer. As to the criticism on mathematical method, however, I may say that experience in other sciences shows that “ in face of many practical problems” it is wisest to “ draw off thought ” for a time to pure theory. Before solving the problems of cannon pro jectiles it is best to solve the problem of projectiles in general. Before an engineer is fit to build the Brooklyn bridge or to pro nounce on it after it is built it is necessary to study mathematics, mechanics, the theory of stress and of the natural curve of a hang ing rope, etc., etc. So also before applying political economy to railway rates, to the problems of trusts, to the explanation of some current crisis, it is best to develop the theory of pol. econ, in general. When these special “ practical problems” are examined the mathe matical instrument will, I believe, often be the one to get the best results. I am far from denying, however, that some mathematical econo mists have exhibited a “ false accuracy.” It has been due to * Economics in Italy, Prof. Ugo Rabberio , Pol. Sci. Quart., Sept. 1891, p . 462. in the theory of value and prices. 119 making special assumptions not with the purpose of facilitating economic investigation but for permitting algebraic transformation. A writer who intentionally parades his mathematics really does the cause of mathematical economics much harm . I venture to think that Launhardt's Volkswirtschaftslehre which contains some excel lent things would have exhibited these excellencies better if the author had contented himself with solving problems in all their generality ]. $ 9. I cannot refrain from venturing an opinion the application of which may not apply to all of those writers just quoted but which certainly applies to many : Mathematics is looked upon as an intruder by those students of economics who have not had the mathematical education to understand and make use of them , and who are unwilling to believe that others enjoy a point of view unattainable by themselves. A friend of mine much interested in economics asked mewhat was the service of mathematics in the subject. On hearing my reply be said : “ Well, I don't like to admit that I can 't understand economics as well as those who have studied highermathematics.” Thus part at least of the opposition to mathematical method is a mere incident to its novelty. It must be remembered that the character of economists is itself a variable and from generation to generation those choose or reject the pursuit of economics according to what it is at the time of choice. It may not be rash to expect that the next generation of the theoretical (as distinct from histori cal) economists will have fitted themselves by mathematical training for this mode of treating their theme, and that they will be such men as by natural aptitude can so fit themselves. $ 10 . The effort of the economist is to see, to picture the interplay of economic elements. The more clearly cut these elements appear in his vision , the better; the more elements he can grasp and hold in mind at once, the better. The economic world is a misty region . The first explorers used unaided vision . Mathematics is the lantern by which what before was dimly visible now loomsup in firm , bold outlines. The old phantasmagoria disappear. We see better. We also see further. 120 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations APPENDIX IV . BIBLIOGRAPHY OF MATHEMATICO - ECONOMIC WRITINGS. $ 1. A bibliography of mathematico-economic writings was constructed by Jevons and extended * by his wife up to 1888. This list con tains a number of works mathematical in tone only . I have selected out of the whole number (196 ), those 50 which are either undoubt edly mathematical or are closely associated logically or historically with the mathematical method . Thus Menger, though his writings are not explicitly mathematical, is included for he founded the “ Austrian School” which has ever since been allied with the mathe matical method. In this selected list the references are much abbre viated and only the first edition of each work is cited. The second list is intended to be an extension of that of Jevons up to the present date. I shall be indebted for information as to inac curacies and omissions. A star has been placed opposite those writ ings in which mathematical method is employed only occasionally or whose mathematical character is not explicitly expressed in symbols or diagrams. In the case of Italian and Danish writings, with which I am wholly unacquainted and in thecase of a large number of others which I have not been able to see and examine, I have been guided by book notices or the wording of the title. The list in Jevons' appendix and the second list here given may be taken as a reasonably complete bibliography of mathematico economic writings in the broadest sense, while the unstarred writings in the abridged list of Jevons here quoted together with the un starred writings in the second list represent the economic literature which is strictly and avowedly mathematical. The distinction between these two classes is tolerably wellmarked. $ 2. SELECTED FROM JEVONS. 1711 CEVA - De re nummaria quoad fieri potuit geometrice Nactata . 1765 BECCARIA — Tentativo analitico sui contrabandi. Etc. 1801 CANARD — Principes d'economie politique. 1824 THOMPSON - Instrument of Exchange. 1826 von THÜNEN — Der isolirte Staat, etc. * Pol. Econ ., Appendix I to third edition , 1888. in the theory of value and prices. 1829 1838 1838 1840 1840 1844 121 WHEWELL — Mathematical Exposition of some Doctrines of Pol. Econ. COURNOT- Recherches sur les principes math . de la théorie des richesses. TOZER — Math. Investigation of the Effect of Machinery, etc. ANONYMOUS — On Currency. TOZER — On the Effect of the Non -Residence of Landlords, etc. DUPUIT — De la mesure de l'utilité des travaux publics. 1844 HAGEN - Die Nothwendigkeit der Handelsfreiheit, etc. 1847 1849 1850 - 1850 BORDAS — De la mesure de l'utilité des travaux publics. DUPUIT - De l'influence des péages sur l'utilité des voies de communication. LARDNER — Railway Economy (chapter xiii). WHEWELL — Mathematical Exposition of Certain Doctrines of Pol. Econ. 1854 GOSSEN - Entwickelung derGesetze des menschlichen Verkehrs, etc. 1856 1863 1864 1867 1870 1871 1871* 1872 1873 BENNER - Théorie mathématique de l'economie politique. MANGOLDT- Grundriss der Volkswirthschaftslehre. FAUVEAU _ Considérations math . sur la théorie de l' impôt. FAUVEAU — Considérationsmath , sur la théorie de la valeur. JENKIN — The Graphic Representation of the lawsof Sup. and Demand , etc. JEVONS — The Theory of Political Economy. MENGER – Grundsätze der Volkswirthschaftslehre. LAUNHARDT– Kommerzielle Trassirung der Verkehrswege. POCHET - Géométrie des jeux de Bourse. 1874 WALRAS - Principe d'une théorie math . de l'échange . 1874 WALRAS - Éléments d 'économie politique pure. 1874 * LETORT—- De l'application des math , à l'étude de l'econ . pol. 1875 * DARWIN — The Theory of Exchange Value. 1875 * BOCCARDO — Dell' applicazione deimetodi quantitativi, etc. 1876 WALRAS - Equations de l'échange, etc. 1876 WALRAS - Équations de la capitalisation . 1876 WESTERGAARD - Den moralske Formue og detmoralske Haab. 1878 * WEISZ — Die mathematische Methode in der Nationalökonomie. 1879 WALRAS - Théorie math . du billet de banque. 1881 EDGEWORTH ---Mathematical Psychics. 1881 WALRAS — Théorie math. du bimétallisme. 1883 LAUNHARDT— Wirthschaftliche Fragen des Eisenbahnwesens. 1884 * WIESER - Hauptgesetze des wirthschaftlichen Werthes. 1885 LAUNHARDT— Math. Begründung der Volkswirthshaftslehre. 1886 GROSSMAN — Die Math . im Dienste der Nationalökonomie. I Lieferung. 1886 * NEWCOMB— Principles of Political Economy. 1886 * BÖHM -BAWERK — Theorie des wirtschaftlichen Güterwerts. 1886 ANTONELLI Teoria math . della economica politica. 1886 GROSSMAN - Die Math . im Dienste der Nationalökonomie. II Lieferung. 1887 VAN DORSTEN - Math , onderzoekingen op het-gebied Staathuishoudkunde. 1887 WESTERGAARD — Math . i Nationalökonomiens Tjeneste. 1887 PANTALEONI— Teoria della pressione tributaria, etc. 1888 WICKSTEED — The Alphabet of Economic Science. TRANS. Conn. ACAD., Vol. IX . JULY, 1892. Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations 122 $ 3. ION OF JEVONS' BIBLIOGRAPHY. EXTENS 1867 WITTSTEIN -- Mathem . Statistik . Hanover . 1882 PANTALEONI (M .)/ La Traslazione dei Tributi. Rome. Paolini . 1884 SCHROEDER (E . A .)— Das Unternehmen und der Unternehmergewinn vom historischen , theoretischen und praktischen Standpunkte. Wien . 92 pp. 1884* SAX (E .)- -Das Wesen und die Aufgabe der Nationalökonomie. 1887* Sax (E .) - Grundlegung der theoretischen Staatswithschaft. 1887 PIOARD (A .) Traité des Chemins de fer. 4 vols. Paris : Rothschild . 1888 EDGEWORTH ( F . Y .)- New method of measuring variations in general prices. Jour. Stat. Soc. London , p . 347. 1888* Sax (E .) Die neusten Fortschritte der nationalökonomischen Theorie. Vortrag gehalten in Dresden märz. Leipzig : Duncker & Humblot. 8vo. 38 pp. 1888 * MENGER (C .) — Contribution à la théorie du Capital. [ Trans, from Jahrb . für Nat. Oek., by C. Secrétan .] Rev. d' Écon . Pol., Dec. '88. 1888* SALERNO (Ricca)— Manuale di Scienza delle Finanze. Florence. Barbera . 1888 HADLEY (A . T.)— Railroad Transportation, its History and its Laws. New York and London . 269 pp . (Appendix II.) 1888 GOSSEN (H . F .)- Entwickelung der Gesetze des menschichen Verkehrs. New edition .] Berlin : Prager. 8vo . 286 pp. 1888 * MENGER (C .)— Zur Theorie des Kapitals. Jahrb. Nat. Oek ., 17 Heft 1. 1889 PANTALEONI (M .)— Principi di Economia Pura. Florence. Barbera . 1889 AUSPITZ UND LIEBEN - Untersuchungen über die Theorie des Preises. Leipzig : Duncker & Humblot. 555 pp. 1889* ZUCKERKANDL (R .)- Zur Theorie des Preises mit besonderer Berück sichtigung der geschichtlichen entwicklung der Lehre. Leipzig. 348 pp. 1889* WIESER (F . von )- Der natürliche Werth . Wien . 237 pp. 1889* BÖHM -BAWERK (E.)- Kapital und Kapitalzins. Translated into English by Wm. Smart. 1890 . London and New York : Macmillan . 1889* LEHR (J.)— Wert, Grenzwert, und Preise. Jahrb. Nat. Oek., 19 Heft 1. 1889 SUPINO (C .)— La Teoria del Valore e la Legge del minimo mezzo . Giorn . degli Econ . Aug. '89. 1889 WALRAS (L .)- Théorème de l'Utilité maxima des Capitaux Neufs. Rev. d'Econ . Polit., June '89. 1889* MACLEOD (H . D .)— The Theory of Credit . Vol. I. London : Longmans & Co. 8vo. 342 pp. 1889 ST. MARC (H .)— Les Procédés d ’Analyse Graphique à l'Exposition Uni verselle. Rev. d'Écon . Polit., Aug. '89. 1889 VIRGILII (F .)- La Statistica Storica e Mathematica . Giorn . degli Econ ., Aug. '89, concluded Oct. '89. 1889 * HEARN (W . E .) – Plutology ; or, The Theory of the Efforts to satisfy Hu man Wants. [New edition .] Melbourne : Robertson . 8vo. 486 pp . 1889* KOMARZYNSKI (J.)— Der Werth in der isolirten Wirthschaft. Wien . Manz. 8vo . 105 pp. 1889 Rossi (G .) - La Mathematica applicata alla Teoria della Ricchezza Sociale : Studî Bibliografici. Storici, e Critici. Vol. I, fasc. 1. Reggio Emilia Artegianelli. 8vo . 103 pp., 4 charts. in the theory of value and prices. 123 1889 * BöHM -BAWERK (E . von )-- Une Nouvelle Théorie sur le Capital. Rev. d ' Écon . Pol., April, 1889. 1889* Böhm -BAWERK (E . von )— Kapital und Kapitalzins. Zweite Abteilung : Positive Theorie des Kapitals. Innsbrück . 8vo. 1889* CLARK (J. B .) - Possibility of a Scientific law of Wages. [Publ. of Am . Econ. Assoc.] Baltimore. 8vo. 32 pp. 1889 WICKSTEED (P. H .)— On certain Passages in Jevons' “ Theory of Political Economy.” Quart. Jour. Econ., April, '89, p. 293. 1889 EDGEWORTH (F . Y .)— On the application of Mathematics to Pol. Econ . Journ . Stat. Soc. London , Dec. '89. 1890 * DIETZEL - Die Klassische Werttheorie und die Theorie vom Grenznutzen . Conrad 's Jahrbuch N . F . Band 20. pp . 561-606 . 1890 * MACLEOD (H . D .)— The Theory of Credit. Vol. II, Part I. London : Longmans. 8vo. 1890 MARSHALL ( A .)— Principles of Economics. Vol. 1, 1st ed . London : Macmillan . 770 pp . Mathematical Footnotes and Appendix. ] 1890 PANTALEONI (M .)- Principidi Economia Pura. Florence : Barbèra . 16mo. 376 pp. 1890 JURISCH ( K . W .) — Mathematische Diskussion des Eutwickelungsgesetzes der Werterzengung durch industrielle Produktionsgruppen . Viertelj. f. Volksw . 27 Band 3, 1. Second paper, same title, 27 Band 3, 2 . 1890 VAUTHIER (L . L .) Quelques Considérations Élémentaires sur les Construc tions Graphiques et leur Emploi en Statistique. Journ . de la Soc. Sta tist., June, ’90 . 1890 * AUSPITZ (R .)- Die klassische Werttheorie und die Lehre vom Grenznutzen . Jahrb. Nat. Oek . 21 Heft 3 ; reply to Dietzel, same journal, 20 Heft 6 . 1890* ZUCKERKANDLE (R .)— Die klassische Werttheorie und die Theorie vom Grenznutzen . Jahrb. Nat. Oek . 21 Heft 5. Reply to Dietzel. 1890 Colson (G .)- Transports et Tarifs . Précis du Régime, Lois Économiques de la Détermination des Prix de Transport, Tarifs de Chemins de Fer, etc. Paris : Rothschild . 8vo. 479 pp . 1890 LAUNHARDT (W .) - Theorie der Tarifbildung der Eisenbahnen. Berlin : Springer. 8vo . 84 pp . 1890 WESTERGAARD (H .) - Die Grundzüge der Theorie der Statistik . Jena : Fischer. 8vo . 286 pp . 1890 Cossa (E .) — Le Forme Naturali della Economia Sociale. Milan : Hoepli. 1890 MARSHALL (A .)- Principles of Economics. Vol. I, 2nd ed. London : Macmillan . 770 pp. [Mathematical Footnotes and Appendix.] 1891* HOBSON ( J. A .)- The law of the three rents. Quart, Jour. Econ ., April, 1891, p . 263. 1891* CLARK (J. B.)— Distribution determined by a law of rent. Quart. Jour. Econ ., April, 1891, p . 289 . 1891 EDGEWORTH (F . Y .)- Osservarioni sulla Teoria matematica dell' Economia Politica con riguardo speciale ai Principi di Economia di Alfredo Mar shall. Giorn . degli Econ ., March , '91. 1891 * SMART (W .)- An Introduction to the Theory of Value on the lines of Menger, Wieser and Böhm -Bawerk . London and New York : Macmillan. 16mo. 88 pp. 124 Irving Fisher - Mathematical investigations, etc. 1891* CLARK (J. B.) — The statics and the dynamics of Distribution. Quart, Jour. Econ., Oct. '91, p. 111. 1891* WIESER (F .)- The Austrian School and the Theory of Value. Economic Journal, March , '91. 1891* BöHM -BAWERK (E. von)— The Austrian Economist. Annals of Am . Acad . of Polit . Sci., Jan . '91. 1891 EDGEWORTH (F . Y .)— La ThéorieMathematique de l'Offre et de la Demande et le Coût de Production . Rev. d 'Écon . Polit., Jan. '91. 1892* BÖHM -BAWERK (E . von )- Wert, Kosten und Grenznutzen. Jahrbücher für Nationalökonomie und Statistik , Dritte Folge, Dritter Band, Drittes Heft, pp. 321–378. 1892 BILGRAM (H .) — Comments on the “ Positive Theory of Capital ” ſof Böhm -Bawerk ). Quart. Jour. Econ ., Jan . ’92, pp. 190 – 206 . 1892 GROSSMAN (L .)- Die Mathematik in Dienste der Nationalökonomie unter Berücksichtigung auf die praktische Handhabung der Finanzwissenschaft und der Versicherungstechnik (schluss Lieferung). Vienna . 1892* WIESER (F. von)— The Theory of Value. A reply to Prof. Macvane. An nals of Am . Acad . of Pol. and Soc. Sci., March, '92. 1892* SELIGMAN (E . R . A .)- On the Shifting and Incidence of Taxation. Publ. of Amer. Econ . Asso., Vol. VII, Nos. 2 and 3. 1892* PATTEN (S. N .) — The Theory of Dynamic Economics. Publ. of Univ. of Penn ., Pol. Econ , and Public Law Series, Vol. III, No. 2 . Phila . 8vo. 153 pp. 1892* BÖHM -BAWERK (E.)- Wert, Kosten , und Grenznutzen . Jahrb . Nat. Oek ., 3, Heft 3. 1892 CUNYNGHAME (H .)— Geometricalmethods of treating Exchange-value, Mo nopoly, and Rent. Econ . Journ., March , '92. 1892 PARETO (V .)— Considerazione sui Concipi Fondamentali dell' Economia Politica Pura. Giorn . degli Econ ., May, '92 . 1892 PARETO (V .).- La Teoria dei Prezzi dei Signori Auspitz e Lieben e la Osser vazioni del Professore Walras. Giorn . degli Econ ., March , ’92. 1892* VOIGT (A .)— Der Oekonomische Wert derGüter. Zeitschr. f. Ges. Staatsw ., 48, Heft 2. 1892 WALRAS (L .)— Geometrical Theory of the Determination of Prices. Annals Amer. Acad . Polit. and Social Sci., Phila., July, '92. Translated under the supervision of Irving Fisher. Part I was published in French in the Bulletin of Soc. of Civil Eng. of Paris, Jan. 1891, and Parts II and III in the Recueil inaugural of Univ. of Lausanne, July ( ) ’92. 1892 FISHER (I.)— Mathematical Investigations in the Theory of Value and Prices Transactions of the Connecticut Academy of Arts and Sciences. Vol. IX , pp. 1- 124. HDI HB OAMB V