Full text of The Four Kinds of Economic Value
The full text on this page is automatically extracted from the file linked above and may contain errors and inconsistencies.
THE FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE LONDON: HUMPHREY MILFORD OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS THE FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE CORREA MOYLAN WALSH CAM BRIDGE HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS 1926 COPYRIGHT, 1926 BY CORREA M. WALSH PRINTED AT THE HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS CAMBRIDGE, MASS., U. S. A. CONTENTS I. Introduction ................................................. 3 II. History of their developm ent...................... 4 III. The first recognition of them as coordinate species................................................... 11 IV. D efinitions..................................................... 15 V. Their proper o rd er......................................... 20 VI. Their objectivity............................................. 22 VII. Their re la tiv ity ...................................... 25 VIII. Their comparableness ................................. 27 IX. Their variability...................................... 34 X. Our attitude toward their variations. . . . 41 XI. Their knowableness............................... 46 XII. The measurement of the first three........ 49 XIII. The measurement of exchange-value . . . . 56 XIV. The question of cau ses............................ 62 XV. The causes of the first th ree.................... 64 XVI. The cause of exchange-value ■— Ricardo’s T heory.................................................... 71 XVII. Its inconsistency....................................... 82 XVIII. On labor-cost........................................... 96 XIX. General exchange-values according to com parative social esteem -values................100 XX. Their divergence in the course of time . . . 107 XXI. Practical uses of the measurements..........115 XXII. In which kind ought money to be stable? . . 126 x . $ THE FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE THE FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE I INTRODUCTION E v e r y science needs to classify its subject-matter. Chemistry deals with the substances in the material world, and it tries to analyze them into their elements. Physics deals with the forces of nature, and discovers and investigates many such. And when the species and varieties are found, they need to be named in order to distinguish them from one another and from the genus to which they belong. The generic term itself is prop erly used only when all its species and varieties are included: when these are referred to specially, their distinctive names should be used. In the natural history sciences the subdivisions are innumerable, and many technical terms have to be invented. In the intellectual and moral sciences the subdivisions are comparatively few. The purpose of this paper is to show that, just as in ethics virtue is the main theme and there are several kinds of virtue, and just as in metaphysics causation is the main theme and there are several kinds of causes, so in economics value is a main theme and there are — and it should be recognized that there are — sev eral kinds of value. Rather curiously, the ancient phil osophers had four (cardinal) virtues and four causes, and modern economists have analyzed value into four kinds. These are use-value, esteem-value, cost-value, and exchange-value. II HISTORY OF THEIR DEVELOPMENT A l r ea d y in antiquity Aristotle distinguished between the utility of an article when put to its intended use, as of a shoe being worn, and its utility in procuring for its owner something else in exchange for it. In modern times Locke applied the same distinction to value, and called the one “ intrinsic value” and the other “ market able value.” Before him, Petty made another division, to the effect that things should be valued by “ land and labor,” land standing for its material produce, and labor for cost. Later, Turgot made another division into “ valeur estimative” and “ valeur échangeable.” Then all the kinds were exhausted. Meanwhile, other economists were using the term “ value” in one or an other of these senses, or in more than one. Later comers, confining themselves to dichotomy, could only repeat what had already been done, at best with improved terms. Thus Quesnay and Adam Smith followed Locke, the former speaking of “ valeur usuelle” and “ valeur vénale,” the latter making the division into “ value in use” and “ value in exchange,” or, translating Turgot’s term, “ exchangeable value.” In his comprehensive survey of the subject Adam Smith could not confine himself to these two kinds of value. The other two kinds obtruded themselves. Un fortunately, instead of assigning them coordinate posi tions, he subsumed the one under exchange-value and went outside the concept of value to get a term for the other. He conceived of exchanges as taking place, not only between goods and goods, but between goods and FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 5 labor. What the Roman law said of contracts,1 he said of exchanges. When the owner of a commodity A ex changes it for a commodity B, Adam Smith said that to this man the “ exchangeable value,” or simply the “ value,” of A is B, but the “ price” of B is A. Here, to the other party, the “ value” of B is A, and the “ price” of A is B, so that, in such an exchange, “ value” and “ price” are practically the same thing viewed from opposite sides. Not so, when a commodity is supposed to be exchanged for labor. This alleged exchange is of so peculiar a nature that something new is introduced. When A is given for a day’s labor, and a day’s labor is given for A, Adam Smith now said that the “ real ex changeable value,” or simply the “ real value,” of A to its owner is the day’s labor he obtains for it, while the “ real price” of the day’s labor is A; but to the laborer the “ real price” of A is the same day’s labor he has given to obtain it, and the “ real value” of his day’s labor — this is the logical sequence, but it was omitted — would be A. “ Equal quantities of labor at all times and places may be said to be of equal value to the laborer.” This obviously is not exchange-value, since no reference is made to any exchange. A laborer may be said always to set the same estimation upon his labor: this can be only esteem-value. When a laborer ex changes his (by himself) equally prized labor, he may at one time and place get more of A for it than at others, and therefore, to him, according to a logical deduction from Adam Smith’s use of his terms, while the “real price ” of A has decreased, since the original quantity of A is obtained with less labor, the “ real exchangeable 1 Do ut des, do ut facias, facio ut des. The fourth, facto ut facias, our “ log rolling,” did not interest him. 6 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE value” of his labor would have increased. On the other side, as the employer now gets less of the laborer’s labor for the original quantity of A, A is conceived by him as having fallen in “ exchangeable value.” Adam Smith took the employer’s standpoint, and used labor as his measure of “real value” ; which in volves a strange inconsistency, since labor is invariable only to the laborer. He did, however, try to take a broad and philosophic view of the case. Labor, he said, is “ the first price” — also “ the ultimate price” — that is paid for everything. This idea he may have got either from Hobbes, who had spoken of commodities which God “ for labor selleth to mankind,” or, more likely, from Turgot, who had alluded to a commerce between man and Nature, who exacts from him labor as the price he must pay for what she yields.2 Yet even so, this price is paid only by laborers, and when those who have engrossed the sources whence Nature yields and, having acquired some of the produce, “ buy labor” with it, they do not buy what is always of the same value to themselves, but only what is of the same value (esteem-value) to the laborers. The laborers’ standard cannot be properly made the employers’ standard. All this refers to value “ at all times and places.” As for the comparative values of different commodities “ at the same time and place,” these Adam Smith ex plained by the labor-costs of producing them, mixed in with rent and profit. In other words, their exchangevalues are according to the prices, paid in labor, at which they are sold by Nature. These prices are now 2 Hobbes, Leviathan, chap. 24. Turgot, Valeurs et Monnaies, ed Daire, pp. 82-83. The idea dates back to the comic poet Epicharmus, as quoted in Xenophon’s Memorabilia, II. i. 20. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 7 more properly called costs.3 Adam Smith showed not so much interest in this as in the other question. This idea of an exchange of commodities and labor, — not to stop at that between laborers and Nature, — which underlies Adam Smith’s conception of value, is a tremendous blunder, and has been a far-reaching cause of error ever since his day. It is utterly improper, being only metaphorical, since no such exchange is made in reality. An exchange is a mutual transfer of two objects. Labor cannot be transferred, but only the result of labor — the work done. When we work to produce something, we do not give any labor, we merely do something, and it is done. When we hire laborers to do something for us, we do not receive their labor, and we do not care a rap for their labor: what we want is the work done, and that is all we get. Labor itself is not a commodity: it is rather a discommodity. A very mischievous misuse of words is it to speak of laborers “ selling” their labor. It gives them the impression that all they have to do is to perform for a certain time cer tain operations called labor, and thereby they are ful filling their side of the contract and need not concern themselves about the thing they are really giving in return for their pay — the thing produced. What la borers really give is evident in piece-work. In time contracts, it should require little analysis to see that the essence of the exchange is the same. Manufacturers use the latter method for convenience, and, if they choose, may talk of “ paying for labor.” There is no 3 “ Price,” in the improper wide sense, is what in an exchange one gives and another receives; “ cost” is what one gives up for a thing and nobody else receives. This refers to the real thing involved in this operation. In socalled money-costs, of course, the money element is transferred. 8 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE special convenience in this phraseology for the econo mist, and to him even more than to the workman it is misleading, since it is not a true statement of the things with which he deals. Fortunately, however, Adam Smith’s other mistake of disguising cost-value under the misused name of “price” was not continued by many of his successors. The next great English economist, Ricardo, confined “ price” to its usual reference to money. But Ricardo fell into a confusion parallel to Adam Smith’s confusion of esteem-value with exchange-value, for he confounded exchange-value with cost-value. He accepted the im perfect division of value into use-value and exchangevalue, and, like Adam Smith, maintained about “ value” or “ real value” a doctrine which is properly applicable neither to use-value nor to exchange-value; only it was a different doctrine from Adam Smith’s, and as Adam Smith’s was applied to an unnamed esteem-value, Ricardo’s was applied to an unnamed cost-value. For Ricardo held, like Adam Smith, that the “ value,” even the “ exchangeable value,” of a commodity is not ac cording to “ the abundance of other commodities for which it will exchange,” but is according to “ the sacri fice of toil and labor required to produce it” ; and this he held not only of the value of one thing compared with the values of others at the same time and place, in which he differed from Adam Smith only in some de tails, but — and here is where he chiefly differed from Adam Smith — he held it of the value of the same thing at all times and places. The doctrine he advocates is nothing but a doctrine of cost-value, while the doctrine he rejects is the proper conception of exchange-value. Yet, having only the one term “ exchangeable value,” FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 9 since use-value has been passed by, he thus rejects from exchange-value what belongs to it and tries to fasten upon it what belongs to another kind of value. But the force of words is too strong, and, at least when speaking of contemporary things, he several times defined the “ value” of a commodity as the quantity of other com modities for which it will exchange. For this kind of value, really exchange-value, he now had no distinctive term, because the term properly belonging to it he had misapplied to something else. Ricardo was opposed by Malthus, who returned to Adam Smith’s use of “ value,” even of “ exchangeable value,” for esteem-value, and was followed by McCul loch, who continued the use of “ value,” even of “ ex changeable value,” for cost-value. Thus Malthus maintained that the variable quantity of goods paid for the same quantity of labor, and McCulloch that the variable quantity of goods produced by the same quan tity of labor, has constant value. English academic economists for long were divided between these two opinions, and some have held both without being clearly conscious of what they were doing; while many out siders have tried to stick to the obvious meaning of exchange-value, or did so merely because they did not go deeply into the subject. Prominent among those who took exchange-value in its literal sense were Joseph Lowe and Poulet Scrope; but their views attracted little notice at the time, and had no influence. On the continent, in France, Say did not employ any word corresponding to use-value, and used “ real price” for cost-value, confining “ value” to exchange-value, but at times extending it to cover also cost-value. Like him French economists have mostly followed Ricardo in 10 POUR KINDS OP ECONOMIC VALUE paying more attention to cost-value than to esteemvalue. In Germany the dichotomy into use-value and exchange-value long held sway, but more attention was paid to esteem-value. This, however, was treated dif ferently from the way it was treated in England (except by Mill); for it was generally subsumed under usevalue, which, therefore, by this attachment to esteemvalue, was brought more into the foreground.4 4 References to the opinions of these many writers may be found in my The Fundamental Problem of Monetary Science, Part I, chaps. 3-7. I ll THE FIRST RECOGNITION OF THEM AS COORDINATE SPECIES A t last, in the third and fourth quarters of the nine teenth century, Roscher and Jevons put the several kinds of value on a coordinate footing, although each made an incomplete division. Roscher divided economic value into use-value, cost-value, exchange-value; and Jevons divided it into use-value, esteem-value, exchange-value. Jevons rejected cost-value altogether; but Roscher had to think of esteem-value, and he did so by extending the meaning of use-value to cover it .1 Still, from these two divisions the complete four-fold division plainly emerges. Unfortunately, contemporary and later economists have shown little inclination to adopt this classifica tion, much less to employ these terms. Walras, who shares with Jevons and Menger the claim to be a founder of present-day economics, used only the two terms “ value” and “ exchange-value,” which he at times assimilated and at times differentiated, while the subject of his inquiry mostly was esteem-value, for which he 1 Jevons did not use the above terms. He divided “ value” into value in use, esteem, and -purchasing power or ratio of exchange, in the 2d edition of his Theory of Political Economy (1879), p. 87. Roscher, Die Grundlagen der Nationaloekonomie, §§ 4, 5, used Gebrauchswert, Kostenwert, and Tauschwert, which are immediately rendered by use-value, cost-value, and exchange-value (“ exchange value” having been introduced by DeQuincey, who also men tions “ cost value” as being in use), upon whose model the term esteem-value is readily constructed. Roscher followed Ricardo in maintaining that ex change-value is regulated by cost-value. 12 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE had no name except “rarity,” strangely employed. And the Austrian school, following Menger, have be clouded the matter by introducing a variety of long terms drawn from metaphysics and psychology. Take Bohm-Bawerk’s, for example. His “ value in the ob jective sense” is use-value strictly confined to intrinsic utility; his “ value in the subjective sense” is esteemvalue; his “ objective exchange-value” is simply ex change-value; while his “ subjective exchange-value” is nothing but esteem-value over again, confined to things like paper-money that are useful only in exchanges. Twenty-five years ago I recommended the use of the four simple terms. My advice was proffered in the belief expressed by the astronomer-statistician Quetelet, that “ it is conducive to the progress of enlightenment to substitute precise ideas for vague notions.” 2 It was in strict accordance with the precept of the logician Mill, who wrote that “ whatever we have occasion to think of often, and for scientific purposes, ought to have a name appropriate to it.” 3 Shortly afterward similar 2 Lettres sur la Théorie des Probabilités, p. 61. 3 Logic, III, vi, § 1. In his Political Economy Mill did not observe his own precept. He there said : “ The word Value, when used without adjunct, always means, in political economy, value in exchange” ; III, i, § 2; and cf. viii, § 2. This implies that the only proper meaning of “ value” in economics is exchange-value. But Mill himself, in his Summary, vi, 1, 2, spoke of “ cost value” and of “scarcity value” (= esteem-value), and in distinction used the full term “ exchange value.” A follower of his, H. Passy, in the Dictionnaire de l’Économie 'politique, art. “ valeur” (ii, 810), made another recommenda tion, on a line with Mill’s intention; which was that we should use “ value” only in the sense of exchange-value, and for the other meanings we should use other term s— “ utility” for use-value, “ cost” for cost-value (and ac cordingly “ esteem” for esteem-value, as Jevons afterward did). But then another generic term to embrace them all would be needed, which is lacking. Also it requires that precedence be given to one of the kinds, on which agree ment does not exist. Some economists (e. g., Carreras, Loria) would confine FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 13 advice was given, at least indirectly, by the Danish writer of French works, Christian Cornélissen ; 4 but unfortunately he has only Roscher’s three terms — use-value, labor- or production-value for cost-value, and exchange-value. More recently, in England, Mr. G. B. Dibblee, in The Psychological Theory of Value, teaches what he calls “ the multiple explanation of value,” but fails to employ or to recommend appropriate terms. The values he deals with are likewise only three — those of Jevons, with esteem-value in the place of cost-value. Both these writers suffer for not making the complete classification. The latter also reverts, as the title of his work betrays, to the old fault of seeking a single theory of value. These are the only writers whom I know of, outside the German-speaking coun tries, who attempt to distinguish between the several kinds of value. Meanwhile, the harm done by the old mistake of endeavoring to get on with only one concept of value is well shown by the falling-out of two such men as Professor Irving Fisher and Dr. B. M. Ander son. The former, in The Purchasing Power of Money, has no use for any kind of value but exchange-value. The latter, in The Value of Money, has only one value, “ value” to cost-value; others {e.g., Menger) would confine it to esteemvalue; still others (e. g., Gossen) would confine it even to use-value, all em ploying “price ” for exchange-value. It is now too late to adopt this recom mendation. “ Value,” not only in popular usage, but in that of economists in general, has acquired these various meanings, which cannot be taken out of it. The only course remaining is to distinguish them by specific terms, under “ value” as the genus. 4 His words are: “ Je suis convaincu que . . . on aurait pu s’épargner beaucoup de malentendus et d’erreurs, si l’on avait mieux distingué la nature de la valeur sous ses diverses formes et évité de désigner par le même terme général et par conséquent vague de ‘valeur’ des notions tout à fait diffé rentes.” Théorie de la Valeur, (1902), p. 21; 2d ed. (1919), p. 35. 14 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE which he calls social, psychological, absolute, and which appears to be esteem-value, though he rejects the prevalent theory of this kind of value and does not elaborate a theory of his own. Consequently he has been unable to appreciate Professor Fisher’s posi tion. Rather curiously, Dr. Anderson conceives of all value as “ social value,” and this he divides into three genera — moral value, legal value, and economic value. Strange, then, that economic value has no subdivision! IV DEFINITIONS “ Value ” is one of those familiar words which it is diffi cult to define, for the very reason that they are so well understood without definition. For the same reason, its definition is not so important as are the definitions of its species. Value in general has a very wide range of meanings in ordinary speech, and it is used even in several arts and sciences, as in morals, music, painting, and mathematics. Economic value, 1 in its generic sense, is a quality or power in, or somehow connected with, appropriable things with reference to the well being and activity of the persons who do, or who would if they could, appropriate them. The nature of this quality or power is stated in the specific definitions. Use-value is a thing’s power to serve our ends. Esteemvalue is its power to make us desire to possess it. Costvalue is its power to impose upon us effort to acquire it. Exchange-value is its power to procure other things in its place. The first is a power to preserve us alive and provide the basis of a “ good life” in the Greek sense. The second is a power to cause us to strive for the acqui1 From a Latin noun and the past participle of the corresponding verb, the Italian language has two words, valore and valuta, the former properly referring to exchange-value and the latter to esteem-value. The French gets its single valeur from the former, and the English its single value from the latter; which single terms have to do double duty, and are perfectly equiva lent. Even the Italian valore has been extended to the wider service, valuta being relegated to a few technical uses. (In English, worth is hardly employed in economics with any distinctive sense, any more than “ work” differs from “ labor.” This word, like the German Werth, originally combined the ideas of utility and honor, and was therefore applicable also to persons. It thus covered the two ideas of use-value and esteem-value.) 16 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE sition of the desired thing by means of the labor which goes to the making of the third kind, and to keep it when we have it so as to avoid the trouble or sacrifice of re placing it. The fourth is its power enabling us, by relinquishing our possession of it, to obtain another or other things for which at the time we have a greater desire, or, in other words, upon which we set a higher esteem-value. The last is especially the kind which permits the increase of wealth. In economics, therefore, it is the most important kind of value. It is the one kind which no economist has ever ignored. On the other hand, the least important kind of value in economics is use-value, because of its slight differen tiation from usefulness or utility, which is a physical quality in things in conjunction with physiological qualities in us. In this first sense, the most valuable thing in the universe for us is air, as without air we can live only a few minutes. Air, in a way, may be said to be appropriated when we breathe it into our lungs, and for this reason it seems allowable to speak of it as hav ing use-value. But no one thinks of calling the sun, moon, and stars “ valuable,” — although they cer tainly are very useful to us, — since they can in no way whatever be appropriated. As for air, it ordinarily has none of the other kinds of value; for, having it always around us, we do not feel any want of it, do not there fore desire it, do not need to exert ourselves to acquire it, cannot lose it, cannot exchange it. It may, however, have them in special circumstances. Thus, when a per son who cannot swim falls overboard at sea, at once air becomes to him an object of the intensest esteem-value, impelling him to put forth all his efforts to acquire it alone as the one thing in the world he then wants. And FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 17 to the professional diver, as to the miner, air has costvalue. If someone like TEolus could put the winds into bags, he might sell them at high prices. Luckily this cannot be done. But well-aired rooms command a higher rent than otherwise equally good but badly ventilated rooms, and therefore the air in those rooms may be said to have exchange-value. So light in open places by day has no value; by night, and in dark places, it becomes endowed with all the values. Heat also loses and gains them. The next most valuable thing, according to its usevalue, is water, without which we can live only a few days. Not so abundant as air, nor so easily acquired, it ordinarily has some esteem-value, though it may be without any to a person lying on the brink of a brook. It has esteem-value, because, not being always at hand, we sometimes feel the want of it, desire it, and then have to go after it, put forth some effort to get it, and take some pains to keep it till we consume it. It then has cost-value, as especially to people in a city, who have to build and maintain reservoirs and aqueducts. In some arid regions it has exchange-value, as is evidenced by itinerant water-venders, and by the sale of water for irrigation. But, ordinarily, though its use-value is great, its other values are small. When we do not distinguish between the different kinds of value, this is a paradox, which has been descanted on by poets and philosophers from Pindar and Plato down. When we recognize the different kinds, the paradox ceases. After these two things, with the exception of land, which properly has no cost-value, and possibly of a few minor articles, such as ambergris, which is found only accidentally, everything useful to mankind has all the 18 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE four kinds of value. It is not correct to except things that are not ordinarily for sale, such as public buildings, parks, and monuments, Roman and Greek Catholic churches, entailed estates, and so forth, and to say that these have no exchange-value. They lack exchangevalue only while held, and differ from other capital goods only in being held longer. As for money, its use-value resides in its serving as a medium of exchange and as a measure of value not only at the same time and place but at different times and places. It has esteem-value, as is obvious, otherwise there could be no misers. It has cost-value, though in the case of paper money this is small. It has exchangevalue as its very essence. The use of a thing for obtain ing other things we have seen Aristotle treat as a second ary use. This is true of commodities, but not of money. Money’s use to procure other things, either at once or at a later time, meanwhile serving, whether hoarded or loaned, as a store of value, is its only, hence its pri mary use.2 This is its use to individuals. To the public at large, in political economy, money is one of the most useful of things. Perhaps, besides air and water and the land on which we live, it is the only one kind of ma terial things that is indispensable for the development 2 Because money is not used as consumable goods are used, Rau said that money has no use-value, Volkswirthschaftslehre, §§ 64, 265. Similarly BohmBawerk, Positive Theorie des Kapitales, 4th ed., i, 205. This comes merely from their arbitrarily confining “ use-value” to the first of Aristotle’s kinds of use. In a way money is consumed, as its individual pieces wear out and have to be replaced. So our individual houses wear out and have-to be re placed, but houses as a whole class will probably last as long as mankind, and money as a whole class also. The only difference is that it is the whole people who consume and through their government replace their money, while it is individual persons who consume and replace their own houses. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 19 of civilization. Of course, food is indispensable for our very existence, as we can live without food only a few weeks; also shelter, without which, at least in tem perate zones, we could live only a few months. But no one kind of food or of shelter is indispensable. Y THEIR PROPER ORDER order in which the kinds of value have been named is the right one. Say, apparently, would have put costvalue even before use-value; for he affirmed that it is labor that gives utility to a thing, instancing that coal under ground is useless and becomes useful only when labor has brought it to a furnace. It would seem plain, however, that all that labor does with regard to utility is to bring a useful thing from where it cannot to where it can be used. The same labor, if it brought sand to a furnace, could not put utility into it. Use-value exists first, and next comes, not yet cost-value, but esteemvalue. This is different from use-value in that esteem in us for a thing, of which the esteem-value in, or of, the thing is a reflection, is produced by something else in addition to the thing’s utility, which other cause is its condition of being scarce, or in not so great abundance as to satisfy our need of it entirely. “ The rare,” said Plato, “ is esteemed” or “ valuable” — it has esteemvalue.1 The utility of a thing remaining the same, we desire the thing more if we have less of it, and less if we have more of it. Obviously esteem-value is very dif ferent from use-value, though it could not exist without it. In fact, all the other kinds of value are based upon, and presuppose, use-value, that is, utility and appro priableness. Having esteem-value, a thing may impel us to exert ourselves to acquire it, and thereby it becomes endowed T he 1 Euthydemus, 304B. The Greek language had two words for “ value” : Ti/xi) for esteem-value, and for exchange-value. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 21 with cost-value. Cost-value thus comes after, and pre supposes, esteem-value. Another way of acquiring a thing is by giving in exchange for it something we already possess. This involves exchange-value in the two things. Thus exchange-value also follows, and pre supposes, esteem-value. But exchange-value does not necessarily presuppose cost-value, nor does cost-value necessarily presuppose exchange-value. Exchange-value is here placed last because of its greater importance. What we need to bear in mind is that both are de pendent on esteem-value. “A thing,” said Condillac, “ has not value because it costs, but it costs because it has value.” 2 This reminds one of Socrates’s question whether certain things are holy because they are be loved of the gods, or are beloved of the gods because they are holy. It is of the utmost importance to get the right sequence of cause and effect between many such couples that are closely bound together. A fuller ex amination of the causes of the various kinds of value must be postponed. 2 Le Commerce el le Gouvernement, I, chap. 1. If for “ value ” in both parts of this sentence be substituted the specific values, the same in both, the prop osition is true except obviously in the case of cost-value, though it has been questioned also in the case of exchange-value. The sentence is a good illus tration of the need of using the specific terms, as different meanings may be slipped, almost unconsciously, into the same word in the two parts. VI THEIR OBJECTIVITY E x c h a n g e - v a l u e has several peculiarities differentiat ing it from the other kinds, which we shall come upon as we proceed. Here already appears an important one. Things may have the first three kinds of value to a man alone in the world, but they can have exchange-value only to men in society. The things a man has with him when he alights in a wilderness there lose all exchangevalue, while the other values of some increase and of others decrease. Because of this fact, it has been maintained that exchange-value cannot be a quality of things, for the rea son that, if it were, it would exist in them always and everywhere. The same denial of objectivity has been extended even to all values in general, because the other kinds also come and go in different circumstances — because, in short, of their variability, which will be examined presently. Value, it has been asserted, not only is subjective, but it is only subjective; and a couple of writers have declared that it signifies merely “ a state of mind.” This opinion is not borne out by facts in the case of other unimpeached and unimpeach able qualities of things. The weight of one body re quires the existence of other bodies, and in definite relations. Take a stone from the surface of the earth and place it at the center, or at a central point in interstellar space, and it would lose all its weight. Heat notoriously changes with position. Colors do not exist without light. The taste of food exists only when one puts it into his mouth. All qualities have a subjective 22 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 23 as well as an objective side. They exist first in us as sensations, or as conceptions worked up from sensa tions, of which we conceive causes to exist in the out side things which occasion them; which causes we call by the same names. There is no reason why value, or in particular exchange-value, should be treated dif ferently from the other qualities of things. Whether the outside causes exist or not, is a question for meta physicians. A German economist has said that value is not a property of things in themselves.1 Well, Kant said that weight, heat, color, and the like, even size, mass, and motion, are not properties or states of things in themselves. We may accept both statements, or neither. Or we may cling to Descartes’s distinction between primary and secondary properties. Then all the kinds of value, not even excepting the first, would have to be regarded as secondary properties. If prop erties are not in the substances, we at all events, in our conception of them, put them into phenomenal things, and get along as well. Thus it does not matter how a quality gets into things, when we are all agreed that it is there. If many people living together put exchangevalue into certain things, any one person, living among them, may find it there and take advantage of its pres ence, and if he be an economist, he may study it as he finds it .2 Psychological explanations are for psycholo1 A. Wagner, in his rewriting of Rail’s work, § 33. 2 Cf. Walras : “ Le fait de la valeur d’échange prend donc, une fois établi, le caractère d’un fait naturel, naturel dans son origine, naturel dans sa mani festation et sa manière d’être.” Eléments d’Economie politique pure, § 28. Yet this did not preserve him from asserting that exchange-value is only sub jective, only in us, and that the money-unit has no value, — § 144 (§ 146 of the 4th ed.),— a position which, needless to say, he could not maintain. Besides his defective nomenclature, this is the one flaw in Walras’s otherwise almost perfect work — and it seems to spring from his defective nomencla ture. 24 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE gists. Economists are concerned with economic facts, and with the interplay of economic facts. Exchangevalue is now, in civilized peoples, an immense power. By means of a little letter of credit, carried in his pocket, a man can travel round the globe. The fact that if, by mishap, he strands on a desert island, or one inhabited only by savages, the exchange-value of this letter van ishes, in no wise militates against the fact that it exists when and where it does exist. Similarly in the case of the other kinds of value. All values, like all qualities, exist only under the conditions that make them exist; and they exist as objective attributes, no matter how subjective some of their causes may be. VII THEIR RELATIVITY value is relative. The first three kinds are relative, each to something outside its own kind. Use-value is relative to the usefulness or utility of things; esteemvalue, to our desires for them; cost-value, to the costs of producing them. But the exchange-value of one thing is relative to the exchange-values of other things: exchange-value may be said to be interrelative. Here is another clean-cut distinction between exchangevalue and all the other kinds. In an unprecise way of speaking, the others may be described as absolute, since each of them in one thing is independent of, or out of relation to, the similar values in other things, or nearly so, not being quite so, as we shall see, in the case of articles that have substitutes. The rise or fall of one thing in any of these values does not involve any change, much less any inverse change, in the corresponding values of other things. It is possible to conceive of all use-values rising or falling together, of all esteem-values rising or falling together, of all cost-values rising or fall ing together — and, in fact, the last two values are apt to vary in greater or less agreement. But all exchange-values cannot rise or fall together, because the variation of one thing in exchange-value means a variation of its exchange-value in some other thing or things, and it involves an inverse variation of the exchange-value of that or those things in it; and so all along the line. At best, it is only the totality of all exchange-values that is absolute, like the totality of all energy, which in the physical world is the only kind of A ll 26 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE force that is conserved.1 Strictly speaking, all we have a right to say is that the first three values, taken singly, are less relative than the fourth, none being really abso lute. In this respect they still resemble all other quan titative properties of things — size, weight, strength, and the rest. We have no absolute length, no absolute weight, no absolute force. The units of these quantities are arbitrarily selected portions that seem to us to re main constant relatively to all other similar quantities taken together over against them. 1 See my The Measurement of General Exchange-Value, chaps. 3 and 13. VIII THEIR COMPARABLENESS B e in g rela tive, all valu es in v o lv e com parisons. First, they contain comparable elements. We desire things because of their utility, and so there must be some relation, permitting of comparison, between desire and utility. We labor to produce things because of our desire for them, and so there must be some comparable ness between labor and desire. We exchange one thing for another because we desire the latter more than the former. Here the comparison is between desire and desire. Secondly, the different kinds of value are comparable with one another. Esteem-value follows desire, and so, like it, is comparable with utility, and through it with use-value. Cost-value follows labor, and so, like it, is comparable with desire, and through it with esteemvalue. Exchange-value, involving comparison of two desires, involves comparison of two esteem-values, and possibly of two cost-values, or of cost-value with esteemvalue. Cost-value and exchange-value have nothing to do with use-value except through esteem-value. In the relationship between desire and utility, or be tween esteem-value and use-value, it may be said that our desire for a thing and its esteem-value are, in a way, according to its utility. But almost everything has various utilities, some greater and some less, which may be arranged in a descending or ascending scale; and we always put a thing to its greatest use first, and as we acquire more of it, we put it to its less use next, and so on down the scale; or as we use it up, or lose some of it 28 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE (or cannot renew it), we cut off the least use first and retrench backward up the scale. Now, desire for a thing operates in two ways: to keep what we have, and to acquire more. Our concern to keep a thing is to keep the last and least use we put it to, since that is what we should first give up if we lost any of it. Our desire to get more of it reaches beyond the last and least use to the next one below. These two halves of our desire, therefore, go in opposite directions from a point which is, so to speak, the end of the last and least use we make of the thing. The amount of utility at this point, then, is what determines or regulates the amount of our desire for the thing, and according to this is the thing’s esteemvalue — to each of us, individually. But the thing’s use-value is the sum of all its uses behind and above that last and least use —■ the total of its uses to each of us as we are able to use it; and to mankind at large use-value is, of course, the sum-total of all its uses. Hence usevalue is always greater than esteem-value. This is why a thing’s esteem-value is so strangely to a first view — paradoxically, till it is explained — divergent from, and always below, its use-value, the divergence being in some proportion with the thing’s abundance.1 The relationship between labor and desire, or between cost-value and esteem-value, is of an opposite nature. 1 Let us not hesitate to say this of precious things. A diamond of the size of a drop of water is immensely more useful than that drop of water: its use-value as well as its esteem-value is greater. "When a rich man buys a diamond at a high price, he gets what is more useful to him than the sum of money he gives for it. And all the diamonds in the world are immensely more uesful to mankind than an equal quantity of water. It is only an enormously greater quantity of water that is more useful than diamonds. As a fact, man kind spends much more for water than for diamonds. But the esteem-value of diamonds is probably very close to their use-value, while the esteem-value of water is immeasurably far below its use-value. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 29 The ultimate cost of things is the exertion of effort on our part to produce them, and this effort is disagreeable. Some economists speak of labor as a “ disutility.” We desire to acquire things, and dislike the necessary effort. We want more of the thing, and less of the labor. How such dissimilar feelings as a like and a dislike can be compared may be a problem for psychologists; but for economists it is a matter of commonest experience.’ Every day people say, “ This is worth the trouble,” “ That is not worth the trouble.” Now, what is worth the trouble they will produce, and we interpret this as show ing that their desire for it is greater than their dislike of the labor, by a difference which may be more or less, but which must exist, as otherwise there would be no motive for the exertion. What is not worth the trouble they will not produce; which similarly shows that their dislike of the labor is greater than their desire for the thing, also by a larger or smaller difference. If the two opposites be exactly equal, one is not in the predicament of Buridan’s ass, because no action is required here, and no production is the result. Mathematical economists easily dispose of the matter by giving utility a plus sign and disutility a minus sign, and requiring the former absolutely to exceed the latter, if production is to take place. Here we have considered the thing produced as a single indivisible article. But economics deals prin cipally with kinds or classes of things, which contain a larger or smaller number of individuals and admit of more or less. Now, we have seen that the more we pos sess of a kind of thing, the less is our desire for it, or, we may say, the less is our liking for it. Our liking for a thing, in fact, decreases every time we use it, the longer 30 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE we use it, only to be reinvigorated after rest. But this is another matter. The case of labor is precisely the opposite. The longer we have to work at a stretch for a thing, the more our dislike of the labor grows. Our desire for a thing may sink to nothing, with satiety. Our dislike of labor may rise till it becomes unbearable and we must stop. So in the case of our daily toil. A poor people, — poor because of barren soil from which they must eke out their sustenance, or poor because of inefficient labor, or the robbery of neighboring peoples, or of a military caste amongst themselves, — because of their greater need, must work more hours than a rich people, who in their greater affluence have less desire for more, and in whose case, therefore, the rising dislike of labor meets the falling desire at a lower point. In this sort of comparison, however, we are here not so much interested as in another. The producers of an article generally, because of different situations or different skill, produce it at different costs of labor. Just as the consumers put their acquisitions first to the greatest use, so the producers first choose the places where their labor will be the least. The same producer may also produce different portions of his produce at different labor-costs. For him the cost-value of his whole product may be reckoned as the average cost. But to the people at large, who get it from producers other than themselves, the cost-value is according to the cost of the portion ordinarily produced at the greatest cost, because the portions produced with less labor the producers are able to estimate, in their trades with the consumers, at the cost-value of what is pro duced and disposed of at the greatest cost; wherefore the people at large must estimate cost-value at the FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 31 greatest cost at which they reward producers for pro ducing the thing. Thus, just as esteem-value is de termined by the last and least use, so cost-value is determined by the last and greatest cost. If the esteemvalue, falling with increased quantity possessed, and the cost-value, rising with increased quantity produced, come close together, the process must stop; for costvalue to the community, just as to the individual, can not be so great as esteem-value. In the case of an exchange the relation stated is ob vious; for unless each party gets something he desires more than what he gives, he has no motive to make the exchange. And accordingly in an exchange the esteemvalue of what each party gets is to him greater than the esteem-value is to him of what he gives. But the two articles exchanged have equal exchange-value; for this is the essence of the idea of exchange-value. Unequal esteem-values precede an exchange; equal exchangevalues are the consequence. Exchanges, however, of similar articles of one kind for similar articles of an other kind are of frequent occurrence, and so, within a region of more or less extent called a market, and during a period of more or less length, a prevalent rate of ex change becomes established, and it is this rate which determines equal exchange-values. When in an indi vidual exchange the one party takes advantage of the ignorance of the other party and gets more than the prevalent rate warrants, he is said to “ get the better” of the other, in “ an unfair bargain,” and the exchangevalues of the articles exchanged are said to be unequal, because such an exchange does not fix the prevalent rate. But when both parties, equally alert, depart from it, this is a sign that it is no longer prevailing. 32 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE It is exchanges that bring cost-values into confronta tion with esteem-values. For the producers of an article generally produce much more of it than they themselves consume — sometimes they consume none of it. To such a one the esteem-value of his product may be said to be rather the esteem-value of the things he believes he can get for it, and, as before said, this esteem-value is greater than its cost-value. To the consumer, on the other hand, the esteem-value of what he gets from the producer is always lower than what would be the costvalue to him (the potential cost-value, it may be called), were he to produce the thing himself; which is the rea son why he does not produce it himself, because he receives more potential cost-value than is the actual cost-value of what he gives, if he be the producer of this. Here is merely another aspect of the fact that wealth is increased by exchanges. When two producers exchange their products directly, there is no reason why they should always exchange them so that each gives and receives what costs the same amount of labor. This would mean that the exchange should be of equal actual cost-values. But this would leave out of sight, not only the potential cost-values, but also the esteem-values, which may be different; and it is precisely for the sake of the esteem-values, and of the use-values back of them, that the exchange is made. If one of the parties complains that to get the same esteem-value he has to give more cost-value, he is at liberty to produce the other thing himself — if he can. If his inability is caused by the action of the other party, he has a right to complain of that, and to join with others to correct it. But if the inability is in himself, in his want of capacity, he may complain of Nature or of Nature’s God; but FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 33 that will do him no good. That Adam Smith could have taught such a doctrine with respect to primitive peoples and that Ricardo could have extended it to civilized peoples, must be attributed to their overlooking esteemvalue. They both knew that things are not exchanged according to their general usefulness, and not knowing the difference between total and final utility, between use-value and esteem-value, the only thing left them that could serve as a common measure was labor. IX THEIR VARIABILITY B e in g relative, all value is variable. And, on compar ing them, we find that the kinds vary differently. Use-value is the most stable of the values, but it, too, varies. It varies as the utility of the thing varies; and the utility of a thing varies as its physical nature changes — for instance, as an apple ripens and rots. Apart from this, the physical nature being supposed the same, utility may vary because persons change, as, when a person is sick, or a people is afflicted with a plague, the utilities of things vary from what they were to them in a normal state of health. Or utility may vary in different situations, especially in different climates, as coal has more utility in a cold region than in a hot one, more in winter than in summer. Again, all these things being supposed the same, the utility, and consequently the use-value, still may vary, but now more slowly. In one sense, it might be said that the use-value of things always is the same, since they admit always of being put to the same uses. This means only that the potential utility of things is constant. But their actual utility, which is what their use-value follows, varies with the actual uses to which they are put. A use must first be known before advantage can be taken of it. For in stance, the greatest utility of petroleum has been a recent discovery. Also it may be dependent on the existence of something else whose utility must likewise first be known, as kerosene could not be used as an FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 35 illuminant without glass-chimneys. Thus use-value increases with applied science. In still another way actual utility, or use-value, may vary, and this variation is very different from the varia tion of the other kinds of value, use-value here standing by itself. The actual uses to which things can be put expand with the increased quantity of them in our pos session, and contract with their decreased quantity. This is the case at least with everything that has more than one use, and all staple articles are such, only some contrivances invented for a special purpose having a single use, such as mouse-traps. Thus, in the case of all the materials needed for the production of finished articles, their use-value increases or decreases directly with the increase or decrease of their quantity. Take, for example, gold. We often hear it said that gold is not a very useful metal because, besides its use as money, it is used only in jewelry, in watch-cases, for gilding, and for filling teeth. This is owing to the small quantity of it in our possession. Were gold to become as plentiful as iron, it could, and would, be used for the roofs of houses, for the plating of the sides of wooden ships, for ballast, for canning, and, with some alloys, for all the household utensils and fixtures for which copper, brass, tin, and nickel now are used. We should find it to be one of the most useful metals; and so its use-value would be much greater than it is now. Not so its esteem-value. The more gold we should possess, the less we should esteem a given portion of it, the less we should value it, the less esteem-value it would have, as would be shown by the lower uses to which it would then be put. And similarly in the case of all other things. Their esteem-value varies inversely 36 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE with their quantity. This is a simple fact of experience.1 And it varies differently with different things, and also with different persons or peoples. The esteem-values of necessaries vary most violently with inverse fluctua tions in their quantities, as was better known in the days when in regions of small extent those fluctuations were much greater than they now are in our wide mar kets; so that Gregory King was able to formulate an empirical rule for the variations of the prices of wheat, which prices, as we shall see, over short periods measure variations of esteem-value. At the opposite extreme, luxuries also vary much with slight variations of quan tity, because of the comparatively small number of their purchasers. Also, if with an increase of its quantity a thing can be put to many uses, its esteem-value may fall less than if it can be put to but few uses; for the ex tension to the new uses, by diminishing the increase of the quantity employed for the old uses, retards the fall of its esteem-value. What is here said is important: it shows that low uses are not the cause of the fall, but a support of esteem-value, preventing its further fall till continued increase of abundance overflows them. An other reason for the differences is the presence or ab sence of substitutes. If one kind of thing is easily re placeable by others, its esteem-value may vary little with its own quantity; but if it has few or no substitutes, its esteem-value, depending more on its own quantity, may vary much. A variation of a thing’s esteem-value 1 If the quantity of an ordinarily valuable thing becomes too great, so as to interfere with the enjoyment of other things, the value of that thing for the time being runs down below nothing into the opposite of value, or negative value, becoming such that we desire to get rid of the superabundance of the thing. This was found out in the case of gold by Midas. Many people have experienced it of water, in times of floods. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 37 may even be caused, without any change in its own quantity, by changes in the quantities of its substitutes. Moreover, in the case of articles that can be sub stituted for one another, habit and fashion play a part. Above, it has been said that our desire for things is ac cording to their utilities. This is not entirely correct. There is a still more subjective factor influencing our desires. This is a preferential liking, hard to account for, given to one thing rather than to another that may perhaps serve the same purpose equally well. None but scientists know whether wheat is more nutritious — that is, more potentially useful — than rice; but in occidental countries people prefer wheat, and in the orient people prefer rice. This is an instance of habit, which changes slowly. Fashion, which rests more on the ornamental aspects of things, induces our liking for different varieties of the same kind of things to change quickly. Between the two, “ crazes” change more quickly than the former, and less than the latter, such as the “ bicycle craze” of several decades past and the recent “ mahjong craze,” which cause the articles neces sary for their exercise to be held in greater esteem, and to receive greater esteem-value, while the craze lasts, than at other times.2 It might be said that this subjec tive element in esteem-value is nothing else than the subjective reflex of utility, since our preference for one 2 Comparable to such a change of habit, fashion, or “ craze,” was the demonetization of silver which took place so extensively about the year 1873. This, by legal enactment putting into effect the desire of financiers, took the use as money away from silver and put it all on gold. More recently carriages have lost their use as vehicles, which has been put upon automobiles. Car riages have hardly any other use, and so their esteem-value has dropped to almost nothing, followed by their exchange-value. But silver has many other uses, and therefore it has retained much of its esteem-value, and also much of its exchange-value. 38 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE article leads us to esteem it more, so that while we do so it has more actual utility. Still it would be our pref erence that causes the greater actual utility, and not the reverse. Now the more fully expressed law of the esteem-value of things is that it varies directly with our likes and inversely with their quantities. As for all things taken collectively, as possessed and used by a whole people, they of course have no substitutes; nor can our liking for them, our desiring them, our need of them, be said normally to vary: in them there is no change of fashion. Hence, if our esteem for all things, or the esteem-value of all things, does not vary, — and certainly it does not increase to the extent of their in crease, nor decrease to the extent of their decrease, •— then the esteem-values of them individually must vary in some inverse proportion to the variation of their total quantity. What this proportion may be, will be ex amined soon. Cost-value has been seen to be in many respects the opposite of esteem-value, along parallel lines. As a thing is differently liked by different persons, so labor is more disagreeable to some than to others. In fact, to some persons labor is pleasant, at least in some occu pations, and for a longer or shorter time after the com mencement of the day’s work, only growing irksome more and more during the remainder. Some persons are industrious, and some indolent. There are habits and fashions also with regard to labor, rendering some kinds reputable and others disreputable, differently among different peoples, and variably in the same. Cost, we have seen, is what we give up for a thing. In production what we give up is really something back of labor — our ease, or the pleasures we might be enjoy ing if we were not tied down to an arduous task. This FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 39 is what makes it difficult to wean a hunting or pastoral people from their easy and enjoyable occupations to an industrious agricultural or manufacturing life. Yet when people are once accustomed to labor, it becomes less tedious, and with the consciousness of acquired skill they come even to find pleasure in it for a time, while the more abundant products they have to con sume heighten the enjoyment of their remaining leisure. This, on the subjective side, is a reason why, as a people becomes more industrious, the disutility of labor sinks to them, the objective side being that their labor, be come more efficient, produces more. There is a double gain, more pleasure being acquired at a smaller cost of displeasure. But the subjective aspect of labor must generally be neglected in economics, except as it affects the supply of labor in the so-called labor market. It occasions no error, and it is sufficient, to speak simply of labor as the cost of the things produced. Most producers cooperate to produce one kind of article under an employer and director. The employer must consider not only his own labor, but that of his employees, about which he knows nothing of their sub jective elements, but only the objective elements of the time they devote to the work and the efficiency of their labor. A product of labor, therefore, has its cost-value estimated by the time-quantity and the efficiency-qual ity of the labor expended on it. Now, in many cases it is found that, up to a certain limit, when more labor is employed together, the quantity produced increases faster than the quantity of labor, so that the cost-value of a given amount is lowered. Thus, just as the increased quantity of the thing produced has for its consequence a fall of its esteem-value, the larger application of labor to produce it may have for effect a fall of the individual 40 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE thing’s cost-value. The fall of esteem-value will, how ever, overtake the other fall, and set a term to the process. This is the case mostly with goods manufac tured out of raw materials. The increased production of bulky articles may lead to a rise of the cost-value of their materials. For materials are mostly subject to another rule, that of diminishing returns. They are drawn from the earth, and the more that is drawn, gen erally the more difficult becomes the drawing. Mines begin on or near the surface, and have to be dug deeper and deeper. Agriculture finds lands of different fer tility, and applies itself first to those of greatest fer tility. Later, therefore, the cost-values rise. A reverse process may set in, when people find distant sources more easily worked, and enough so as to surpass the increased cost of transportation due to greater distance. Decrease in the cost of transportation also helps here. Machinery may be applied also to mines and to agri culture. Growing population thus has opposite effects, both to raise and to lower cost-values; and sometimes the one tendency has prevailed, and sometimes the other. For the last four centuries there has been cheap ening. The coming centuries may witness a change. Variations of exchange-value are of constant occur rence. Their frequency is doubled by the fact that every rise of one is a fall of another, and conversely. As they cannot all move in the same direction together, as can the preceding, our treatment of them must be very different. Two great theories have been invented to explain them, which would make them proportional to variations of cost-value or to variations of es teem-value. These theories presuppose measurement and considera tions of causation, and so must be deferred. X OUR ATTITUDE TOWARD THEIR VARIATIONS Otjr attitude toward the variations of the four kinds of value is also very different in the case of all but two. Toward use-value we have one attitude: we wish it to be as great as possible, or in the course of time to in crease. Toward esteem-value and cost-value we have another attitude, common to both, and exactly the opposite of the preceding: we wish them to be as low as possible, or in the course of time to fall. Toward exchange-value we cannot rationally hold either of these attitudes. Value may increase in two ways: extensively or laterally, and intensively or vertically. All the four kinds may increase in the first way, as when we possess more things, we may have more of all the values. It sometimes happens, however, that after one has a cer tain amount of a thing, as he acquires more of it, its esteem-value falls faster than its lateral increase, so that the total esteem-value of the thing may be to him even less than when he had less of it. This can happen even with the exchange-value of a particular article, if we are all thus enriched by its unusual abundance and are not at the same time equally blessed by a corre sponding abundance of most other things. Farmers and manufacturers sometimes find themselves impoverished by over-production. Still, this is desirable for all of us except the producers of the particular articles in the infrequent cases when their exchange-values so behave. At all events, we all wish for better things, that is, for 42 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE higher use-values. Also we all wish for more of most things, that is, for lower esteem-values as the direct consequence of their greater abundance. And we wish to get them through less labor: we wish their costvalues to fall. Certainly the producers of every article entertain this wish, and the rest of us wish the same so far as they allow us to participate in their good for tune. The opposite attitude toward use-value and esteemvalue is another clear distinction between them, which ought to keep all economists from confounding them. Unfortunately, some economists, even since Jevons expounded the distinction between total utility, which applies to use-value, and final utility, which applies to esteem-value, have thought of these two as utilityvalues, and so have renewed the old confusion. Even the Austrian economists do not keep the two concep tions as sharply distinct as they ought to be kept.1 1 The trouble occasioned by not clearly observing the distinction may be illustrated by Bohm-Bawerk’s famous ‘ ‘casuistical ” hypothesis (or ‘ ‘thoughtexperiment”) of a Robinson Crusoe with five sacks of corn. Op. cit., book in, chap. 3. Each sack is valued at 1 (the marginal utility of feeding par rots), so that the total is 5. But if he had only three sacks, each would be valued at 6 (the marginal utility of feeding chickens), so that together they would be worth 18, and it would seem to be to his advantage to throw away two sacks in order to increase the value of the corn in his possession. This reductio ad absurdum has been urged against his theory, for instance, by Cornflissen {op cit, 2d ed., p. 66), who does not distinguish between usevalue and esteem-value. Bohm-Bawerk himself, not clearly enunciating the distinction, was conscious of the trouble, and tried to obviate it by denying that the marginal values of the five sacks, each at 1, should be added. In stead, he said that the sum should be made of the marginal value of the single fifth sack at 1, plus the marginal value of the fourth sack at 4, and so on. But just as the marginal value of the fifth sack is estimated at 1 on the supposition that the five are possessed, so the marginal value of the fourth is estimated at 4 on the supposition that only four are possessed, and so on. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 43 As for exchange-value, our attitude toward this like wise stands by itself. To be sure, the extension of the exchange-values of all our possessions, the total valua tion of our property, we all wish to be increased, except in the way just described. But the heights of the ex change-values of all things — the exchange-values of the units in which their quantities are measured — must be treated differently. We have seen that the use-values of all things can rise together, and likewise the esteemvalues and the cost-values of all things can fall together, and these are the variations which we desire. But we have seen that the exchange-values of all things cannot rise or fall together. Hence we cannot rationally desire any change on the average, apart from individual ups and downs, in the exchange-values, of all things to gether. What happens is this. Every article has its special producers, and the producers of every article wish its All these are incompatible suppositions, whose consequences hardly admit of forming one sum. But with the distinction between use-value and esteemvalue there is no trouble. The use-value of the five sacks is greater than the use-value of the three, each new use, though smaller, being properly added to the preceding; and it is only the esteem-value of the three sacks, on the sup position that he had lost two, that would have been greater than the esteemvalue of the five (and would have been shown to be so by his guarding the remaining ones more carefully). But it is precisely use-value which this Crusoe desires to be as great as possible, and it is precisely esteem-value which he desires to be as low as possible. Hence it is in two ways to his ad vantage to preserve all his five sacks. But if he were surrounded by other men who produced many things but had no corn, while each of his sacks was a warehouse full, then it might actually be to his interest to destroy two fifths of his corn, as he might get in exchange for the remainder more of the other things than he could get for the whole. Many monopolists have done this very thing. The gain, however, would accrue to him alone; and to the com munity at large it would be a loss. For wealth consists in use-values. Cour not, in the first chapter of his Recherches mathématiques, made the mistake of saying that wealth can be increased by such vandalism. 44 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE exchange-value to rise (whether by a rise of its own esteem-value above those of other things, or by a fall of the esteem-values of the others below its own); but all the consumers of all articles wish their exchange-values to fall relatively to what they have to give in exchange for them. Thus especially persons with fixed moneyincomes wish the exchange-value of money to rise, but each of the producers of what these persons consume wishes the exchange-value of money with respect to his own product to fall. And land-owners are happy if people settle in their neighborhood and raise the ex change-value of their land, while those who are about to buy or to lease want its exchange-value to be low. All these conflicting desires neutralize and destroy one an other. An impartial onlooker — and such the econo mist, such the statesman ought to be — cannot share in all these special wishes, as he ought not to sympathize with either of the opposite sides alone. His only wish should be that every producer may produce equal quan tities with less labor, and especially that he may pro duce more with equal labor, and that every consumer may have more to consume — that cost-values and esteem-values of commodities may fall. Exchangevalues of commodities individually should not interest him, since that would show favoritism. And exchangevalues as a whole take care of themselves. Only the ex change-value of money needs looking after, as we shall see later on. Here, too, exchange-value differentiates itself from esteem-value and from cost-value. There are some points of contact between it and them, as we have seen and shall see; and these explain, though they do not justify, the persistent identification, or at least non FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 45 differentiation, of it with them even in the respects in which they are different, on the part of so many econo mists. But the distinction is perfectly clear, and is easy to perceive when once pointed out. It too, therefore, ought to be firmly held. XI THEIR KNOWABLENESS B e in g variable, the kinds of value should, as far as feasible, or as far as is needed, be measured. But before taking up this subject, let us pause a moment to consider one more characteristic wherein values differ, which is their knowableness. The uses of things it is the province of science to dis cover, and no one is capable of knowing them all. But as use-value follows only the known and actual uses of things, use-values are completely knowable, and any one can learn all he wishes about them on consulting experts or searching through books on the arts and applied sciences. Personal esteem-values, or the esteem-values of things to each individual person, are known to each one within the limits he cares to become conscious of them. The upper limits, however, are somewhat hazy; for every one has but an ill-defined idea as to how highly he prizes his various possessions or the things he wants. It is the lower limits of esteem-values that become clear as a person compares different objects with one another by the lower uses to which he is able to put them. Yet everyone in his bargains with others tries to keep secret the height to which his desire for the article might rise if he did not get it; and so the height of the esteemvalues of things to others is not completely knowable. They are to a certain extent, however, ascertainable in exchanges effected, especially as after an exchange people are often willing to tell their friends how good a FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 47 bargain they have made. By means of exchanges, also, to the people at large, the comparative esteem-values that things have to them become apparent, as will be shown more plainly when we examine the causes of exchange-values. Thus, on the whole, esteem-values are fairly well knowable. The least knowable are cost-values. For cost-value follows cost just as use-value follows utility and esteemvalue follows desire; but while everybody knows the utility of everything he needs and his desire for it, only the producers know the costs of the articles they pro duce, and they are by no means willing always to dis close them correctly. Thus the cost-value of each article is knowable in the first place only to a few, and these hide them. These few themselves hardly know how easily they produce some portions of their product: it is the highest cost of the whole product that interests them. And the lowness of this highest cost, or the low ness of cost-value, the producers try to conceal, or they try to make it out higher than it is. They exaggerate it for at least three reasons. The first is, in order to make better bargains in their exchanges for other things. The second is, to prevent others from learning their profits, and thereby to keep competitors out of their line of production. The third is, to get “ protection” from their government by representing that their costs are higher than the costs of the same articles in foreign countries. It is, thus, the lowness of cost-values which it is difficult for the people at large to know. Con sumers, we have just seen, try to conceal the height of their esteem-values from the producers; and now we see that the producers try to conceal the lowness of their cost-values from the consumers. But in this game the 48 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE producers have the immense advantage of being few in the case of each article, and consequently of being able to act in concert, while the consumers are many, are scattered, and are little able to combine. Producers, too, at least the managers, generally are consumers of what they produce, and can easily estimate the esteemvalue in which others are likely to hold their products; but consumers are not producers of most of the things they want, and have no means of estimating correctly their costs. Thus obscurity is one great peculiarity of cost-value, separating it off from all the other kinds. Exactly the opposite is the case with exchange-value: its amount and its variations are the most apparent of all. In fact, exchange-values exist only as they appear: they are the most phenomenal of the kinds of value. Moreover, their variations, of daily occurrence, are reported from mouth to mouth, and quoted in the newspapers. Everybody knows those in which he is interested, though he may know little or nothing about the cost-values of the articles, and may have only an unprecise knowledge of their esteem-values even to him self. Exchange-values are the most knowable of all the kinds of value. XII THE MEASUREMENT OF THE FIRST THREE We now come to the measurements of the kinds of value. Being differently variable, they must be meas ured differently. Use-value, however, the lowest of the economic values, hardly seems to be measurable with any pre cision. Being so close to mere usefulness, its measure ment, if possible in some cases, would belong rather to physics and even to physiology. The various uses of the same thing may be compared with one another roughly; and also the total utility of one thing may be compared with the total utilities of other things, and their relative importance be estimated in round figures. Nothing more than this seems to be needed. In the case of money, its use-value resides in its services as medium of exchange, as measure of comparative ex change-values at the same time and place, and as store of “ value” from one time or place to other times or places (of which kind, must be examined later) ; and all that we need say about it is that the more and the better it serves these purposes, the greater is its use-value. When the people of a country are passing from a régime of barter to a régime of commercial exchanges on a money basis, while this process is going on, money flowing in, or being produced, and gradually filling, as is said, the channels of trade, then its use-value is increas ing. But when this process is completed, its use-value may be said to be stationary. Again, however, when substitutes are being introduced, such as bills of ex- 50 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE change, bank-notes, checks (transferring deposits), and government notes promising to be received in place of money and to be redeemed in money, then the original money may be said to lose some of its use-value, which is taken over by these substitutes; but if these all to gether be regarded as money, — in Walker’s phrase, that “ money is that money does,” — then the use-value of money still is stationary (only its cost-value has sunk). A smaller supply of money at higher “ value” may, within certain limits, serve the same purpose and have the same use-value as a larger supply at lower “ value.” At the same “ value,” obviously more money is needed if the country is growing in population and prosperity. But here we are running ahead of the right order of development of our theme. Next to use-value comes esteem-value. This, we have seen, varies directly with our likes or preferences, and in some inverse proportion to the thing’s quantity, differently of different things and for different persons. Theoretically, the variations may be plotted out diagrammatically. But practically little more is known than that the lines are curves sloping in certain direc tions: they cannot be calculated individually. Luckily we have little need of precision in individual cases. What we most want to know is the variation of the esteem-value of things in general, not only to individual persons, but — and especially — to a people at large. Here the problem is simplified by the fact that an in dividual’s and a people’s liking or desire for all things in general is not affected by modes and crazes; 1 wherefore 1 Except possibly religious crazes that induce some to despise property and to seek poverty. Prospective wealth in heaven then takes the place of wealth on earth. But this is outside of economics. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 51 this factor in determining esteem-value may be elim inated, quantity alone remaining. In the case of individuals, a theory has long been entertained that the whole of everybody’s property is always of the same “ value,” -— or as Franklin put it, a poor man’s all is as dear to him as is the all of a rich man to him, —■ which can refer only to esteem-value.2 If by property be meant capital, it should obviously in clude the capitalized value of one’s earnings, or rather of one’s earning power. The theory, however, is more simply applied to a person’s consumption of goods during a given period, say a year, including the services of the permanent goods which he uses as well as those things which he uses up or destroys in using them. An emendation was suggested by Daniel Bernoulli to the effect that a certain minimum amount, just sufficient to keep one alive without supplying pleasures, should first be subtracted, and only the surplus be considered. This would make the rise or fall of esteem-value slightly greater than the decrease or increase of the whole for tune. But in wealthy countries, where fortunes are far above this minimum, the difference is small enough to be neglected. Now, the variation of a person’s consump tion of goods from one period to another can be best measured by calculating his money-expenditures during each of the periods compared, on the assumption that the exchange-value or purchasing power of money has been measured and found stable, or, if varying, that its variation is allowed for. As for the variation of the 2 This theory is not invalidated by the fact that, temperaments being different, some are content with little and others, possessing much, yearn and strive for still more. The loss of half their property would be felt more keenly by the latter than by the former. Still, the proportion to the whole would be the same in both cases. The relativity of all value allows for these differences. 52 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE esteem-value of a person’s money itself, money may be said to represent all the things it is exchanged for; and like them, money is always in fashion, so that its esteemvalue is affected only by the quantity of it one has to spend. It is important, then, to measure the variation of the esteem-value of money as well as its exchangevalue. And this is important especially in the case of the esteem-value that is put upon money by a people at large. For the theory just propounded applies to a whole people as well as to individuals. A whole people always sets the same esteem-value upon its whole an nual consumption of goods, and consequently upon its whole annual money-expenditures. As for a people’s real annual consumption, which corresponds fairly well with its annual production (plus the algebraic balance of im ports and exports), this can be estimated by averaging the ascertained variations of the amounts of all the principal goods produced and consumed during the periods compared. Professor Day and Professor Per sons have recently been showing how this can be done. In the case of money, it may be better to substitute money-income for money-expenditures. The moneyincome of an individual can differ from his expenditures during any period, on the one hand by his trenching upon his capital or by borrowing, and on the other by his paying off debts or by saving and adding to his capital. But by the law of large numbers these differ ences may be considered to be constant figures for all the individuals in a country taken collectively; and money-incomes are more easily estimated than moneyexpenditures. Now then, to measure the variation of the esteem-value of money, all that needs to be done is FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 53 to calculate during different periods the average moneyincomes of a people. The average money-income, be it said, because after the whole is calculated, allowance must be made for increase or decrease of population, and the making of this allowance is done by averaging. In this case, contrary to the usual practice, it would seem to be advisable to reckon only the adult popula tion, as money has no esteem-value to babes, and to other young children only as it is given to them. At most, only self-supporting minors should be counted. This question need not be decided here, the principal purpose of this paper being to be suggestive. The prob lem of calculating average incomes is one for statis ticians. They have thus far found many obstacles in their way, but none that are insuperable.3 This subject is now attracting more attention, and the National Bureau of Economic Research has already made some progress in this direction. When both this measure ment of the variation of the esteem-value of money and the measurement of the variation of the exchange-value of money shall have been carried out, the combination of these two, as in the case of individuals above noticed, will yield the variation of the people’s real income and consequently the variation of the esteem-value of any given amount of average goods consumed. More will be said about this later. As for cost-value, it is obviously determined by cost, and the measurement of cost is a business affair. The managers of every productive concern must needs try 3 Nothing would help them better than a strictly economic income tax, levied on total net incomes (above a small minimum), from whatever sources derived. Unfortunately our federal income tax, with its many exemptions (even excepting the salaries of government officials!), does not give this full aid. 54 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE to measure the cost, and the variations in the cost, of producing their products, and they can generally do so fairly accurately. They can calculate both moneycosts and labor-costs, their interest being chiefly in the former, while economists are more interested in the lat ter. Statisticians, by taking the results of such accounts as far as they can get them, — and get them truthfully reported, — can average their variations and thereby make an approach to a more or less veritable measure ment of the average cost of things, and so of their gen eral cost-value. For the latter purpose, it may be ques tioned whether the costs in the factories and on the lands that are kept working at the margin of profit and with out yielding rent, are the only ones to be reckoned. Ricardo, to whom “ value” meant principally costvalue, denied that there could be any measure of this value. He meant merely that no commodity could be expected to be found that would always be invariable in the cost of producing it. But this is not necessary for the purpose. If the variation of the cost of producing the usual unit (whether of weight or of volume) of any commodity were ascertained at different periods, then an inverse portion or excess of it would be known to have stable cost-value over those periods. The calcula tion of labor-costs and the averaging of them have generally attracted more attention during eras of falling prices, such as 1810-50 and 1873-96. The first of these saw in England the labors of Tooke, which were con tinued by Newmarch even beyond it; the second, the efforts of Wells and Atkinson in America. Many prac tical difficulties have been found to stand in the way, which were pointed out in Carroll D. Wright’s Sixth Annual Report of the Commissioner of Labor, 1891. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 55 But again these might not be insuperable if there were inducement enough to overcome them, although this is doomed to be the least accurate of the measurements. The examination into costs is now undertaken mostly with a view to tariff regulations, because the applicants for protection generally make out their costs to be higher here than abroad, and their statements need to be checked. In the special case of money, it may be added that, where money is identified with gold, its cost-value is of interest really only to the producers of gold. Where money consists of paper notes, its costvalue is trifling. This is said from the standpoint of the governments producing the money. To the people at large it is really the esteem-value and the exchangevalue of money that are important. What anyone at the present day has to say about the above measurements must be uttered with diffidence, as these subjects have not yet been fully discussed and examined. The measurement of the variations of ex change-value, to which we now turn, has been more fully investigated, and we can speak about it with more assurance. XIII THE MEASUREMENT OF EXCHANGE-VALUE T h e measurement of exchange-value is very different from the measurements of the other kinds of value, owing to the peculiarity of exchange-value in being interrelative. An article has exchange-value in another article according to the greater or less amount of the other article given in exchange for it in the open mar kets of the country, whether the exchange be immediate or through the intermediation of money; and the varia tion of its exchange-value is measured directly by the amounts of the other article exchanged for it. That other article has exchange-value in the first article, and the variation of the second article’s exchange-value in the first article is simply the reciprocal of the variation of the first article’s exchange-value in it. The first article, moreover, has exchange-value in still another article, and in still another, and so through the list of all articles, and in every case its exchange-value is ac cording to the amounts of the things exchangeable for it. Some of the old economists called these the article’s “ nominal values,” because each of the other things is named. But they may be better called its particular exchange-values. Now, the different particular exchangevalues of any one article may vary differently. If an article should vary in exchange-value in every other thing equally, its variation in exchange-value in all other things —•or the variation of its general exchange- FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 57 value (the term is Mill’s) 1 — would be easily measured, as its general exchange-value would vary simply as all its particular exchange-values have varied. This may happen at any time for at least a short while; for if the price of an article be marked up at some moment, we may consider it probable that for some few moments no other change of price takes place, and therefore during this interval the article has fallen in exchange-value, not only in money, but equally in all other things. But if a thing varies in exchange-value in one other thing alone, its other particular exchange-values remaining the same, which happens during that short interval when only one article other than it has changed in price, then its general exchange-value evidently is only slightly affected and, though it has varied in the same direction somewhat, it has varied to a much less extent. If, again, it rises in exchange-value in one thing and falls in exchange-value in another thing, all its other particu lar exchange-values remaining the same, — for ex ample, while its pi’ice is steady and only the prices of two articles have been changed oppositely, — then evidently its general exchange-value is affected op positely, and these opposite variations of its two particu lar exchange-values may be equal and neutralize each other, in which case its general exchange-value remains unchanged; or these opposite variations, being unequal, may not neutralize each other, and then its general ex change-value is affected more by the preponderating exchange-value, and it inclines to that side. As a rule, 1 Pol. Econ., Ill, i, § 3. The idea being new and ill-defined to him, Mill spoke of its “ necessary indefiniteness” (xv, § 1). If by this he meant that it necessarily is and always will be indefinite, he spoke hastily and with un necessary pessimism. 58 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE between two periods every one thing’s many particular exchange-values have varied variously, and the varia tion, or constancy, of its general exchange-value is a resultant of these many particular variations. Some economists have maintained that an equality of a thing’s exchange-value, by which they mean its general exchange-value, at different times is inconceiv able except only in the case that it always exchanges for the same amount of every other thing; that is, that all its particular exchange-values remain unchanged; which would require that all the particular and general exchange-values of all the other things should remain unchanged too, in what one of them has called “ a petri fied economic world,” such as does not exist. This opinion is easily refuted. These economists admit that the general exchange-value of a thing may at a later time be considerably higher or lower than it was before, and they do not require for this that all its particular exchange-values must rise or fall alike, but admit that its particular exchange-values may vary differently, demanding only that the general trend should ob viously preponderate on the one side or the other. They must admit, therefore, that the thing’s general exchangevalue may vary from a higher to a lower, or reversely, without requiring that all its particular exchangevalues vary alike. But by the principle of continuity, when anything varies from more to less, or reversely, it must pass through — or be able to pass through without being required to jump over — the point of equality. Hence it must be possible for a thing’s gen eral exchange-value at a later period to be equal to what it was at an earlier, without the requirement that all its particular exchange-values must be the same at FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 59 both. Equality at a later period must be conceivable if variation is conceivable, and of the same kind. And if conceivable, it must be admitted to be possible. And if possible, it can be measured. To measure the variation, or absence of variation, that is, constancy or stableness, of an article’s general exchange-value, it is evident that an average must be drawn of the variations of all its particular exchangevalues. In this averaging, of course, the relative quan tities of the articles that appear in the market must be taken into account; for if twice as much of, say, wheat enters into traffic as of barley (reckoned by their total valuations), the wheat should be considered as forming two classes of similarly named and equivalent articles, compared with barley as one class. This allowance for relative quantities is called “ weighting” ; and for brev ity of speech it is said that all articles should be weighted “ according to their importance.” 2 In every measure ment two different periods (or different countries) are compared, and therefore the relative quantities, or rela tive importance, of the articles at both periods (or in both countries) should be taken into account, that is, the weighting of both should be used, as neither period (or country) has better claim to consideration than the other. Now, we have no direct information about every article’s variations in exchange-value in every other article, for the simple reason that in our markets com2 There always must be weighting, right or wrong. It is common to speak of averaging as “ unweighted,” or “ without weighting,” if all the articles are counted alike. It should be obvious, however, that this is merely even or equal weighting. The difficulty of getting correct weighting is not avoided by this ostrich-like subterfuge of trying to make out that no weighting is being employed. 60 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE modities are not exchanged directly for one another. But we have such information about the variations of the particular exchange-values of money in all other things, which information is given in the prices of all the articles listed in the country’s markets; for the varia tions of prices are the reciprocals of the variations of the particular exchange-values of money. Thus in the case of money we have at hand the data necessary for the measurement of the variations of its general exchangevalue.3 The problem is now posed, and requires for its solution an inquiry into the proper kind of average to use and the proper kind of weighting. Here we need not undertake this inquiry. Mathematical economists have already worked over this subject sufficiently to have reached an adequately accurate method of meas uring the variation or constancy of the general exchange-value of money on the supposition that prices and quantities are given. These it is the office of sta tisticians to collect. The accuracy of the result is deter mined partly by the accuracy of the data collected (especially of prices), and partly by the extent of the collection; for it is beyond human capacity either to be accurate in all details or to make the collection com plete. The articles included in the research can only serve as samples. When we speak of a variation of money’s general exchange-value in all things (that is, in all things besides money), we can strictly mean by “ all” only all the things included in the collection; but 3 General exchange-value, as was pointed out in my The Measurement of General Exchange-Value, pp. 13, 39-41, may be further distinguished into general exchange-value in all other things and general exchange-value in all things, including the article itself. When we measure the variation of money’s general exchange-value by means of the opposite variations of prices, we are measuring the variation of its general exchange-value in all other things. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 61 our meaning may be inductively extended to refer to really all things with an approximation that is the greater, the greater the accuracy of the data and the greater their number; wherefore as many prices should be included as can possibly be collected with satisfactory accuracy.4 When this has been done, the mathematical theory of probabilities may be invoked to calculate what is the probability of error in the result; for it is well known that no observation, no measurement, made by man, ever is absolutely correct. Yet, notwithstand ing its deficiencies, the measurement of exchange-value has been brought to a closer approximation to truth than the measurement of any of the other kinds of value. 4 Wages, however, which with a view to greater completeness have been included by some economists, ought to be excluded, as constituting an en tirely different category of economic objects and forming an entirely different line of research. Wages may be averaged by themselves, and the result gives the variation of the esteem-value of money to the wage-earning class of the community. They belong more properly, along with salaries, profits, and even unearned incomes, as data to be averaged all together in the calculation of the variation of a whole people’s money-income, for the purpose, as we have seen, of measuring the variation of the esteem-value of money to the whole people. This is an entirely different affair. To take wages out of this combination and to put them with the prices of commodities for measuring the variation of the general exchange-value of money (which money laborers, like everybody else, use to purchase commodities with), is to make a hodge podge without meaning. It is a survival of Adam Smith’s treatment of politi cal economy from the standpoint of the employer. XIV THE QUESTION OF CAUSES H a v in g examined how the measurements of the four kinds of value are to be made, the next subject to which we should turn would properly be an inquiry as to what uses can be made of the measurements. There are several practical uses to which some of them, at least, can be put. But first there is a theoretical question to be disposed of, which, now that economists have made some progress in perfecting the measurements, we are in a position to undertake; so that, in a way, this is the first use we are to make of these measurements. This is the inquiry into the causes of the variations of the kinds of value, or simply into the causes of the kinds of value. It is, according to Whewell, “ an important maxim of inductive science, that we must first attain the meas ure and ascertain the laws of phenomena, before we endeavor to discover their causes.” 1 Economists, un fortunately, began by searching for the causes of val ues, confounded simply as “ value,” before they had correctly distinguished and measured them. In this respect, however, they proceeded as all scientists have done; for physics and the other natural sciences have run through similar courses. In antiquity the Greek physicists inquired into the causes of things first of all, before they measured and learned accurately 1 Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences (1847), ii, 241. So, of a particular case, Newton had written: “ We must learn, from the phenomena of Nature, what bodies attract one another and what are the laws and properties of at traction, before we can inquire the cause by which the attraction is per formed.” Optics, query 31, in Newton’s Opera omnia (Horsley’s ed.), ii, 243. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 63 what it was whose causes they were seeking. They stopped at metaphysics, or mental analysis, instead of using objective research. The Greek scientists at best made attempts at measurement only in astronomy and acoustics, which were the only sciences (apart from mathematics, wherein there are no causes) that they really developed, except for a small advance in me chanics. Physics in general did not become an indepen dent science until accurate measurements of forces were made in the seventeenth century of our era, and chemistry not till accurate measurements of the com binations of substances were made in the eighteenth and nineteenth. Even in physics only recently have such measurements been completed in the departments of electricity and magnetism, and only now have these departments been established on a scientific footing. In the future, when the measurements of values shall have been thoroughly carried out in economics, econo mists will probably look back at the pre-measurement economists very much as physicists nowadays look upon the ancient physicists, regarding them as having merely historical interest. XV THE CAUSES OF THE FIRST THREE W e have, then, to inquire into the causes of the different kinds of value — of all but use-value; for use-value re quires no investigation, as its cause obviously is the utility, or rather the utilities, the total utility, of the thing in question. As for the causes of utility, they are physical and physiological, and therefore lie outside of economics. With regard to the other kinds of value, I cannot go into so much detail as the subject properly calls for, since my intention is not to develop a theory of my own, but to point out the simplification effected by recognizing the distinction between the different kinds. Here, for an historical reason, the order of treatment may be changed, and cost-value be examined before esteem-value. Ricardo and his followers — they were the first in the field — assert that the comparative values of commodi ties are determined, in the case of those freely producible each at about the same cost on the part of all its pro ducers, by their comparative costs of production (or of reproduction); and in the case of those which are pro duced at various costs owing to natural limitation of the most fertile and most easily worked sources whence they are obtained, by the comparative highest costs which it is necessary to employ in order to produce all that is needed of each. If they assert this of compara tive cost-values, they have a perfect right to do so; for we know that a thing will not in the long run be pro duced unless it “ pays” to produce it — unless its cost, FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 65 or the disadvantage of laboring to produce it, does not exceed the utility or advantage we derive from consuming it. Hence “ value,” which always presup poses utility or advantage, must, in one sense at least, be as great as is the cost or disadvantage of producing the thing which bears it; and where there are several different costs, although the producers at the lowest costs get the surplus benefit, the people at large do not obtain the thing from these favored producers for less than they have to give for it to the producers at the greatest cost from whom they are willing to purchase. Thus, general usefulness being presupposed, as is cost, so is this kind of value: cost, or labor-cost, or simply labor, is a cause of cost-value. This statement is in controvertible, being nothing more than an analytical, explicative, or definitional proposition, as logicians say, the element in value which is so caused being picked out and named. Jevons, Menger, Walras,1 and their followers assert that the comparative values of things would be deter1 Gossen, who is often said to have preceded these, is not to be mentioned here because he held with Ricardo that exchange-value is determined by la bor-cost. Gossen preceded only in recognizing the decreasing enjoyment we get from using things and the increasing pain we suffer from laboring to pro duce them. He used “ value” only in the sense of use-value. He knew “ the value (= utility) of the last atom,” as he expressed the last increment; but he did not recognize this as esteem-value, to be extended over the whole class of the thing, and instead assigned a different “ value” to each portion of a class according to the use it is put to. Hence he asserted that an exchange creates “ value,” and denied that things having equal “ price” (= exchangevalue) are of equal “ value.” Accordingly he maintained that to multiply the total quantity of a thing by the prices of the portions exchanged does not give the true estimate of the thing’s total “ value” ; which of course is true of its total use-value, else water would have little use-value. In an exchange, he held, the only things equal are the pains of the last moments of the labor that produced the quantities exchanged. 66 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE mined by their comparative utilities, if anything had but one degree of utility; but as hardly anything of this sort exists, they are determined by the comparative final or marginal utility of the last and least use to which people are enabled, by the abundance of the things, to put them, and down to the last and least degree of enjoyment obtainable from that use. If they assert this of comparative esteem-values, they have a perfect right to do so; for we know that, when we pos sess a small quantity of some kind of thing, we apply it only to its greatest uses, and get enjoyment to the ex tent that we can apply it to them, since our enjoyment decreases with the extension of our using it, until it sinks to the level of another use, to which, if its abun dance suffices, we then put it, and so on with increas ing abundance, until the least use is reached, and down to its last degree of enjoyment, when satiety ensues, and if the abundance, as the thing is consumed, is main tained by Nature’s bounty, we desire no more. Only air, and in some places water, reach this ultimate degree to all people; all other good things, which we appro priate because of their lesser abundance, stop at some higher degree of the last use, and generally at some one higher than the absolutely least. And when we possess things sufficiently to put them to several uses, we do not distinguish the portions which we put to the greater or lesser uses, or from which we get greater or lesser utility, but we esteem them all according to the least utility of the least use to which we are able to put the last portion which we habitually possess. Hence value in one sense must be as low as the least possible utility of a thing according to the extent of our possessing it, and it falls or rises with the extension or contraction of our pos FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 67 sessions. Therefore we say that the esteem-value of a thing is determined and caused by the last and least utility we are able to get from it. This statement, if confined to esteem-value, is likewise a merely analytical, explicative, or definitional proposition, necessarily true, as it expresses what we mean by the term. These economists generally go one step further and say that as this final utility itself is directly according to the gen eral utility or usefulness of the thing and inversely ac cording to its abundance, or, in other words, directly according to its scarcity; and as effects increase or de crease with the increase or decrease of their causes, therefore esteem-value is caused, not only by the general usefulness of a thing, but by its scarcity. This further statement is not an analytical or definitional, but a synthetic proposition; nevertheless the proof of it is so apparent in the commonest experience, that it is almost equally incontrovertible. Thus, general usefulness being presupposed, as is scarcity, so is esteem-value: scarcity is a cause of esteem-value. Thus have been established two great truths: that, apart from general usefulness, which is presupposed in both cases, cost-value is caused by labor, and esteemvalue by scarcity. There is an important relation be tween these two propositions. As more labor is devoted to produce a thing, its abundance increases and its esteem-value falls. This may be only a horizontal ex tension of labor, the labor-cost of producing each unit of the thing remaining the same. Then, though costvalue is unchanged, esteem-value falls; but the fall of esteem-value has a limit, a thing’s esteem-value not being able to fall below its cost-value, except acci dentally, as the thing will then cease to be produced 68 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE till its esteem-value rises again. There may be another cause of the fall of esteem-value. Improved labor may in an equal time produce more units, and so reduce the labor-cost of the thing: then the cost-value falls, and esteem-value may also come down to a lower limit. Here we have spoken of production first, as if it leads the way. But production is only for consumption: consumption, as the purpose of production, really pre cedes. And it precedes in time also, both to the race and to the individual. When men were beasts, or lived in the garden of Eden, they consumed what they found. Children also consume what is given them. And chil dren discover that their marbles become less attractive as they acquire more of them, and they increase the esteem-value of their possessions by swapping their superfluous marbles for other things, and so get an idea also of exchange-value before they know anything about costs. These two kinds of value are thus learned before people apply themselves to produce things and thereby learn further their cost-value.2 Now, consumption, by diminishing the abundance of the things possessed, tends to raise their esteem-value; and it is precisely the function of labor, by restoring the abundance, to keep esteem-value from rising, and even, if possible, by in creasing the abundance, to bring esteem-value still lower. Really, then, esteem-value precedes cost-value, exist ing first, independently of cost-value. It is because we set esteem-value upon a thing that we desire to renew its supply; or in the case of a new thing, it is because 2 Therefore, in general works on economies, consumption, and also ex change, should logically be treated of before production, contrary to the usual practice, which was introduced by Say. 69 we believe in advance that it will have esteem-value, that we wish to inaugurate a supply. And continuing to produce the thing, and applying more and more labor, and more intensive labor if necessary, we give it more cost-value up, possibly, till it meets esteem-value, which meanwhile, by our producing more of the thing, has been coming down. When the two meet, they stop. It is, however, important to note that there is no neces sity that the two should meet, since Nature may not yield enough of it to our labor to bring esteem-value down sufficiently, — also the producers themselves may not desire it and may be in a position to prevent it. Esteem-value may, in some cases at least, in some places, and at some times, — and for long times, — remain higher than cost-value. Cost-value, on the other hand, can only for a short while go higher than esteem-value, doing so only by accident, the producers quickly rectify ing their mistake. Now, as it is a function of labor to lower esteemvalue, labor cannot be a cause of esteem-value. Rather it might be said that esteem-value is a cause of labor. We have seen that the esteem-value economists went one step further than the cost-value economists. They went from the analytical proposition about esteemvalue being caused by final utility, to the synthetic proposition about its being caused by scarcity. The others did not go beyond their analytical proposition, did not inquire into the cause of labor. Now, as the esteem-value of a thing is a cause of our laboring to pro duce it, it might be claimed that esteem-value is a cause of cost-value. But this is a final cause. Confining our stand to the level of efficient causes, we must admit that labor is the first and last cause of cost-value with FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE r 70 FO U R K IN D S O F E C O N O M IC VALUE which economists need be concerned, just as scarcity is the one cause of esteem-value with which they need be concerned — apart from general usefulness, be it always understood, which is a concurrent cause in both cases. XVI THE CAUSE OF EXCHANGE-VALUE — RICARDO’S THEORY T h e position has, then, been won that labor is not a cause of esteem-value, and scarcity is not a cause — not an efficient cause — of cost-value. It is evident that neither is a cause of use-value. But how about ex change-value? Both the cost-value economists and the esteem-value economists extend their doctrine to ex change-value. The former do not say that the exchangevalue of no product can be above its cost-value; they say, in order to allow for profits, that if the exchangevalue of any one commodity is above its cost, then the exchange-values of all commodities are above their costs in an equal proportion. Exchange-values, for them, are regulated by comparative costs, and so agree with cost-values. The latter do not allow that anything can have exchange-value below its lowest esteem-value; for if anything, through the bounty of Nature, has no exchange-value, its esteem-value also is nil, though its use-value may be great. They assert that exchangevalues, being essentially relative, are, in a way to be explained presently, regulated by comparative esteemvalues. These economists make their doctrine abso lutely general, because everything that has exchangevalue has utility, and therefore a final utility, and there fore again esteem-value. But the former have to admit exceptions to their doctrine. By its very wording their doctrine is confined to the products of labor. Hence 72 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE lands,1 mines, waterfalls, and other such limited and appropriable gifts of Nature, which have no cost-value, need to have their exchange-values explained in some other way, by bringing them into connection with the exchange-values of the things by labor produced from them or with their aid. Also the unique products of past labor, which cannot be reproduced, such as an tiques, and even the art works of living masters, which cannot be reproduced by others, must, it is admitted, have their exchange-values explained in still another way. Thus the only dispute is about the cause of exchangevalue. Which of these doctrines is correct? It would seem that the mere exposition of them, when carried out clearly with the aid of sufficient terminology, should easily decide between the two. The need of admitting exceptions at the very outset casts doubt upon the first theory. Consider the opening words of Ricardo on the subject, at the beginning of his Principles. “ Possessing utility, commodities derive their exchangeable value from two sources: from their scarcity, and from the quantity of labor required to produce them.” He there upon divides commodities into two classes, which have their exchange-values determined, the ones in the first way, and the others in the second. Of the first, compris ing antiques and the like (even including “ wines of a 1 In the plural, because land is not a single kind of thing with uniform value, but is composed of plots with different soils and in different situations, having different values to be accounted for. Locke and some other econo mists, among them Carey, tried to explain the exchange-value of agricultural lands by the labor bestowed upon them that has brought them into a suitable state. This is equally contrary to fact. Still more obviously labor cannot account for the exchange-value of city lots, where previous labor often stands in the way of their present value. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 73 peculiar quality”), he says “ no labor can increase the quantity of such goods, and therefore their value can not be lowered by an increased supply.” This means that with regard to the commodities in the second class labor can increase their quantity and lower their value. Certainly what reduces is not the cause (or the source) of what it reduces, since it presupposes the existence of what it reduces. Thus the cause (or the source) of ex change-value in the second class also cannot be labor; and as he has given a perfectly satisfactory explanation of the exchange-value of the commodities of the first class (which, in germ, is that of the esteem-value theo rists), and has no other, this must cover the second class as well. Still, the things in the second class, which he considers by far the most important (though the first by no means deserve to be neglected), may be exchanged according to the comparative quantities of them pro duced by the same quantity of labor. These things Ricardo treats of under two subdivisions — freely manufactured articles, and raw materials obtained from limited sources of different fertility. We may review the second first, because it is the more comprehensive, and the first differs from it, as we shall see, only in degree. Ricardo supposes a people occupying a country whose land has several degree of fertility, that of the first quality, or No. 1, yielding 100 quarters of corn, No. 2 yielding 90, No. 3 yielding 80, and so on, the same acre age being intended, and “ with an equal employment of capital and labor.” At first the people will cultivate only the best land; but as the population increases, this increase will eventually, he says, “ make it necessary to cultivate No. 2.” Then, as the same labor produces 74 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE less quantity, equal quantity is produced by more labor; hence he says, “ the exchangeable value of [the] raw produce will rise, because more labor is required to pro duce it.” And similarly, when No. 3 has to be resorted to, and so on. Here, and in most of his expositions of his theory (but not in all, as we shall see later on), the implication is conveyed that it is the cultivators of the inferior soil who first raise the price (or exchange-value) of their produce because of their higher labor-cost, and then the cultivators of the better soil follow suit. At all events, this implication is necessary for the theory that exchange-value follows, or is regulated by, cost of production. Ricardo, however, nowhere makes this implication explicit, and we need not attribute to him cleverness in hiding it: he was himself deceived into entertaining it. But the real state of the case evidently is that, as the population grows in numbers and riches, and needs more corn, com having become scarcer to them individually, they set a higher esteem-value upon it, and are willing to give, and do give, more of other things for it, so that its exchange-value rises, and rises before the next inferior soil is cultivated, its rise there fore being due to some other cause than the greater difficulty of production, which other cause is the one first assigned by Ricardo himself, namely scarcity; and it is only this prior rise, as well of exchange-value as of esteem-value, that permits the inferior soil to be culti vated and thereby gives opportunity for the rise of cost-value. Ricardo was here explaining the origin of rent (in which he had been preceded by James Anderson); for the land that will just yield the lowest acceptable profit to an agriculturist’s capital and labor cannot pay rent; FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 75 and that which yields more can pay rent because its owner, instead of cultivating it himself, may lease it to another, who will put up with the least acceptable profit and hand over to him the surplus, which is rent. This theory of rent is likewise held by the esteem-value theo rists, with the difference that they give the right se quence of cause and effect, which Ricardo inverted. When the exchange-value of corn rises through scarcity, if there is other poorer land to cultivate, the cultivation of this, by increasing the supply, keeps the exchangevalue of corn from rising as high as it would have done without this further cultivation. Thus, though greater labor is employed to produce the same amount of corn from the next poorer soils, it, instead of being a cause of the rise of the exchange-value of corn, is a cause retard ing the rise. But it retards it only for a time; for, as the population continues to grow, the cultivation of the second quality of land may not be sufficient to prevent a further rise, which will lead to the employment of more capital and labor on the third quality, and so on, the rise of the exchange-value of corn always preceding the rise of its cost of production; until at last, con ceivably, there is no more land left for cultivation, and the rise of the exchange-value of corn may then con tinue unabated (and all land will pay rent), corn now being like “ the wine of superior quality” which Ri cardo placed in the first class, because no more labor can be applied to its production, increase its quantity, and keep its exchange-value from rising further. The only absolute limit will be the stoppage of the growth of the population by an approach toward starvation. What Ricardo said of lands and of corn, he said also of mines and of minerals, since mines pay rent, and dif 76 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE ferent rent, and there are some mines that cannot pay rent. According to him, it is “ the return for capital from the poorest mine paying no rent” that regulates “ the rent of all the other more productive mines,” and it is the cost of extracting and bringing to market (“pro ducing” covers this, too) the minerals from the no rent-paying mine — the least prolific mine that it pays to work — that determines, regulates, or governs the value (the exchange-value) of the mineral. The true relation, however, is that it is the existing value (ex change-value as well as esteem-value) of the minerals, caused by their existing scarcity (in addition to their utility), that permits the working of the least produc tive mines, one or many, that are just workable, and does not permit the working of still less productive mines.2 In all this, the influence of the extension of labor to less prolific sources, in consequence of diminishing sup ply of the article, is parallel, in the opposite direction, with the influence of the extension of the employment of the article to lesser uses in consequence of an increas ing supply. The latter process, as we have seen, tends 2 One of Ricardo’s followers, A. Houston, in his Principles of Value in Ex change (London, n. d. [about 1865]), pp. 92, 93, drew a distinction between mines and agricultural lands, in that the latter are nearly continuous in their progressive fertility, while the former are much more discrete. Agricultural produce, therefore, almost always finds some land where cost-value is equal to exchange-value; but in the case of mines there may be a great gap be tween the least productive mine now worked and the next one discoverable, so that considerable latitude is left for the exchange-value to rise above costvalue till the next high-cost mine comes into operation and lifts cost-value to the level of exchange-value. This seems like a clear recognition that cost is not a cause of exchange-value. Ricardo himself, of course, did not make this distinction, since he treated, in the above example, also lands as widely discrete. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 77 to keep the thing’s esteem-value from falling, and so is not a cause of that fall; and the former, as we now see, tends to keep its esteem-value from rising, and so is not a cause of that rise. They have these contrary effects also upon the exchange-value of this thing compared with the exchange-values of other things. It would be as great a blunder to say the lower uses are a cause of the fall of exchange-value, as to say the greater costs are a cause of the rise of exchange-value. Yet the lower uses, acting to keep up the exchange-value, are much more causes of exchange-value than are the greater costs, the only action of which is to keep exchangevalue down. For what causes something to be as great as it is, is much more properly described as its cause than is something which only keeps it from being greater. As to the things in Ricardo’s first class, which com prises manufactured goods, their raw materials being assumed to be given, these in a regime of free competi tion are supposed to be produced each at one uniform cost and at one uniform rate of profit. As a matter of fact, different factories produce the same article at dif ferent costs, owing partly to differently advantageous situations, partly to different equipment, methods, and processes, themselves due to different skill on the part of the managers. Those run at less cost yield a surplus which is exactly comparable with the rent of the better lands, the only difference being that it is not generally so great or so easily perceived and recognized. With regard to different kinds of products, the theory requires that all the profits gained in their manufacture be at a uniform rate, as otherwise the relative exchange-values would not be according to the costs. This also is con trary to fact, since entrepreneurs and workmen have 78 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE different aptitudes and preferences for different kinds of work. There may also be different combinations of pro ducers of the various articles, and different legal aids and restrictions, and customary hindrances affecting them differently. Still, there may be a pure theory of production under free competition, on the assumption of perfect fluidity. On this assumption, a commodity can be produced with equal cheapness by an indefinite number of producers, and as consumers will always purchase at the lowest price, all who undertake to produce the thing will have to sell it at the lowest price yielding an acceptable profit, which will be the same to all. “ There cannot be two rates of profit in the same employment,” said Ricardo.3 Nor can profits be higher in some employments than in others, because new-comers will rush into those with greater profits, and by increasing the quantity produced will bring down the prices obtainable and consequently the profits. “ In one and the same country,” said Ri cardo, “ profits are, generally speaking, always on the same level.” 4 Wages, at least for the same kind of labor, will be uniform for a similar reason. For con tinued production, prices must always be above costs, and what keeps prices to a uniform rate above costs is the perfect fluidity supposed. On the other hand, there may also be a pure theory of monopoly, where fluidity is replaced by solidity — by a barrier somehow raised, which keeps others out. 3 Page 112; similarly, p. 37. Paginal references are to McCulloch’s edition of Ricardo’s Works, 1886. 4 Page 76. He added, however, “ They differ only as the employment of capital may be more or less secure and agreeable.” It is not so between dif ferent countries because of obstructions preventing the perfect fluidity sup posed. The pure theory does not abstract these. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 79 This theory cannot be conceived by the cost-value theorists without leaving the ground they stand on: it can, logically, be developed only by the esteem-value theorists. Ricardo, though occasionally referring to monopoly prices, knew nothing about the theory of them. The theory, developed since his day, is that, of a monopolized commodity, there is, at any one time and place, a certain price which yields a maximum profit; and this price is higher, and the quantity produced and sold is less, than what the price and the quantity are in the régime of perfectly free and fluid competition as determined by the other pure theory, which is held in common by the cost-value and the esteem-value theo rists. In practice, as the managers of a monopoly are not omniscient, it cannot be supposed that they hit upon the exactly right price that would give them the highest profit; but it is supposed that they approach more or less closely to it by trial, with a tendency per haps to keep prices too high. For of course the favored producer, or combination of producers, who have a field of production to themselves, aim at the highest profit for their own benefit, as otherwise there would be no motive for their acquiring the monopoly. Now, in the business world of to-day, and probably of all time, conditions fluctuate between those assumed in these two theories. There is no perfect fluidity as is supposed in the first, and there is no perfect solidity as is supposed in the second. The consequence is that not only profits range between a minimum acceptable to the majority up to a maximum striven after by a few, but also prices range between the lower limits determined by comparative cost-values not exceeding the corre sponding esteem-values, and the upper limits deter 80 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE mined by comparative esteem-values alone. All pro ducers strive for the highest profits, and to make them they have the two opposite means, of lowering their costs as much as possible, and of raising their prices as much as possible; which last they can do by keeping others out — hence the secrecy about their costs and profits, hence the pouncing upon new competitors, hence appeals to the legislature, hence unfair methods in general.5 All consumers of what they do not themselves produce are interested in helping the producers lower their costs and in preventing them from raising their prices, or from keeping them up when their costs are falling. Everyone wishes every other occupation to be ruled by the law of free competition, his own to be sub ject to monopoly. Between these opposing tendencies there is a perpetual seesaw. At a given time and place, some manufacturers may be nearer the condition of free competition, and the prices of their products are regu lated more closely by their labor-costs, and their exchange-values are nearer to their cost-values. At best, therefore, the cost-value theory of exchange-value is only partially carried out. And, in general, all that can be rightly said is that cost-values regulate the lowest 5 There is a peculiar way by which profits are made to appear equal. In a market at the same time the rate of interest (risk abstracted) must be fairly uniform, because interest is paid on money loaned, and there is no difference between money units. But every business enterprise pays different dividends on the original capital. If the surplus, like rent, in those with high dividends be taken by the sellers of shares, the profits to the purchasers are equalized. This, however, is a different matter, and more like interest than profits proper. Still the higher prices paid for the shares reveal the higher profits on the original capital. When through partial monopoly these become enor mous, they are generally lowered in appearance by the injection of “ water,” in order to head off legislative interference. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 81 limits of exchange-values.6 But exchange-values do not merely gravitate toward their under limits: they also levitate toward their upper limits, and in fact float variously between the two. There is therefore no pro priety in picking out cost-value, the determinant of the lower limit, as alone the regulator of exchange-value. And the impropriety is all the greater in that, even when the exchange-value of some commodity is in agreement with its cost-value, the cause of its being as high as it is is not that cost-value, and the law regulating it is the same as when it is elevated above that lower limit. 6 At this point Jevons made an unfortunate slip. His famous sorites: “ Cost of production determines supply; supply determines final degree of utility; final degree of utility determines value,” Theory, 2d ed., p. 179, merely played into the hands of Marshall, who, in his Principles of Eco nomics, 3d ed., p. 562, drew from it the natural conclusion that cost of production determines value. The mistake is in the first premiss. Cost of production alone does not determine supply. XVII THE INCONSISTENCY OF RICARDO’S THEORY I t may be objected, however, that Ricardo himself has forestalled, met, and overcome this criticism. The above exposition of his doctrine is based on his own ac count of it in the long first chapter of his Principles, on value, and in the two following chapters, on rent; and the criticism has been directed against the doctrine there expounded. But immediately after that exposi tion Ricardo inserted a fourth chapter, “ on natural and market price,” in which, besides using “price” in a wide sense, contrary to his first definition of it, treating it now as synonymous with value,1— and he later speaks of “ market” or “ natural value” in the same sense, -— he revises his doctrine and turns it into something quite different from what he first advanced. As first ad vanced, his theory was that cost, or last and greatest cost, regulates or causes 12 value, by “ value” meaning exchange-value. “ If the quantity of labor realized in commodities regulates their exchangeable value,” he there wrote, “every increase of the quantity of labor must augment the value of that commodity on which it is exercised, as every diminution must lower it” (p. 11). Again: “ If fewer fish could be obtained with the same capital and labor, fish would rise in comparative value. Fish, then, would rise or fall in exchangeable value, only because more or less labor was required to obtain a 1 He'could do so because he assumed, hypothetically, that money is invariable in value, whereupon prices become true indicators of values. 2 This word is employed on pp. 13, 20, 24, also later, p. 44. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 83 given quantity; and it never could rise or fall beyond the proportion of the increased or diminished quantity of labor required.” And of commodities in general: “ Un less more labor were required for their production, they could not rise in any degree whatever.” “ If more or less labor were required in the production” of any commod ity, “ this will immediately occasion an alteration in its relative value.” 3 All this would be perfectly true if stated of cost-value; and the criticism has been that it is, as a matter of fact, not true of “ value” in the sense of exchange-value, in which sense Ricardo here used it and in which he always professed to use it, except when he specifically speaks of “ value in use.” But now in the fourth chapter we are suddenly in formed that by value being regulated by cost, or last cost, Ricardo meant only that (borrowing a term from Petty) it is the “ natural price” or “ natural value” of things that is thus regulated, whereas what he calls their “ market price” or “ market value” may depart from it in “ accidental and temporary deviations.” Market value is the “ actual,” though only “ temporary,” value; natu ral value is the “ primary,” “ necessary,” and “ per manent” value.4 And later also he frequently speaks of price or value, though varying “ always in the market, and in the first instance, through the comparative state of supply and demand” (p. 66), yet as being “ in the market ultimately regulated by the comparative facility or difficulty of producing” the thing, or “ by its natural value” (pp. 114, 115). It is “ the natural price of com 3 Page 20; cf. later: “In all cases, commodities rise because more labor is expended on them,” p. 65; similarly, p. 165. The italics are here inserted. Kicardo never used them. 4 For “ natural value” he also uses “ real value,” pp. 171, 220, etc. 84 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE modities,” depending “ on the facility of production,” “which always ultimately governs their market price” (p. 130), or “ultimately regulates the prices at which they shall be sold” (p. 227). “ The real and ultimate regulator of the relative value of any two commodities, is the cost of their production, and not the respective quantities which may be produced, nor the competition amongst the purchasers” (p. 208). “It is the cost of production which must ultimately regulate the price of commodities, and not, as has been often said, the pro portion between the supply and demand: the propor tion between supply and demand may, indeed, for a time, affect the market value of a commodity, until it is supplied in greater or less abundance, according as the demand may have increased or diminished; but this effect will be only of temporary duration” (p. 232).5 In other words, it is only “ natural value,” which we recog nize to be what is better called cost-value, that is im mediately affected by any change of costs, and can never diverge from costs, being exactly regulated by costs; but “ market value,” which we recognize to be nothing else than exchange-value, can diverge from costs, doing6 6 Yet this revised version he had inserted in his very first statement of his theory in a pamphlet published in 1815. “ The exchangeable value of all commodities rises as the difficulties of their production increase. . . . Whereever competition can have its full effect, and the production of the commodity be not limited by nature, as is the case with some wines, the difficulty or facility of their production will ultimately regulate their exchangeable value.” And in a footnote: “ Though the price of all commodities is ultimately regu lated by, and is always tending to, the cost of their production, including the general profits of stock, they are all subject, and perhaps corn more than most others, to an accidental price proceeding from temporary causes” (p. 337). Remember we have seen that prices tend also toward a higher limit, and so it simply is not true to say that they are “ always” tending toward the lower limit. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 85 so in the first instance under another law which regu lates it and is only ultimately, in some cases, affected by costs, after some interval, the length of which Ricardo and his followers never attempt to define. So, after all, the law of costs is admitted by Ricardo himself to have only a more or less distant influence upon exchangevalue, which, whenever and while it deviates from costvalue, is regulated by the law of supply and demand. Meanwhile the cost-value itself may be varying, so that, if it was accidental for exchange-value to deviate from cost-value, it may be equally accidental for it ever to get back into agreement with it. But why is it acci dental in either case? 6 By “ accidental” we mean that we do not know the cause of what we call such. Ricardo called the deviations “ accidental” because he did not know, or at least did not have a satisfactory theory of, their causes. But that is no reason why later economists should not work out a theory satisfactorily explaining market or exchange-value as well when it deviates from as when it agrees with cost-value, the same theory ex plaining both. If the law of supply and demand (which is this theory, displeasing to Ricardo only because of its vagueness as it was entertained in his day) can regulate exchange-value while deviating from cost-value, how does this law suddenly cease to operate when exchangevalue comes into agreement with cost-value? It would 6 Ricardo seems to have had in mind the accidental variations in the price of corn arising from good and bad seasons: see another footnote on p. 877. But these are causes, through their effect on the quantity produced, of varia tions both in the cost-value (or “ natural value”) of corn and in its esteemvalue; and the fluctuations of the “ market value,” or exchange-value, of corn result from the efforts of the producers not only to recoup their costs, but to dispose of the whole crop at its proper esteem-value. After a harvest, the quantity in the hands of the producers is a monopoly, to be treated with out reference to its cost, which is a thing of the past and irretrievable. 86 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE seem to operate in all cases, and to be the only one of the two laws that does operate in all cases, whereas the law of costs, which always determines cost-value, de termines exchange-value, concurrently with the law of supply and demand, only when and where there is no natural or artificial limitation to production.7 Similarly, Ricardo later on revised his theory of rent and the value of raw produce. A greater demand for corn, he later incidentally tell us, raises its price (its mar ket price); this rise of market price or exchange-value encourages greater production (pp. 252, 253), and then, if the further supply “ be obtained from land of the same fertility as that which was last in cultivation, and with no greater cost of labor, the price will fall to its former state; if from poorer land [at greater cost], it will con tinue permanently higher” (p. 95; similarly, p. 66). Certainly there is nothing accidental in all this. And now, further, Ricardo once admits that, if land culti vable even at greater cost is lacking, then “ every portion of land in cultivation . . . will yield rent,” corn then selling “ at a monopoly price,” and doing so “ perma 7 Shortly after the publication of Jevons’s work, in a defence of it from Cairnes’s criticism from the Ricardian viewpoint, George H. Darwin, in an article on “ The Theory of Exchange-Value ” in The Fortnightly Review, Feb. 1, 1875, well showed that, on the supposition of free competition and of un limited sources, both the cost-of-production theory and the utility theory are true, but that, as the cost of production and the final utility of the last portion produced and consumed are equal, and as “ the utility theory of ex change shows that commodities exchange against one another inversely pro portionally to their final utilities; hence it appears that they also exchange inversely as their cost of production. Thus Mr. Cairnes’s datum is deducible from Mr. Jevons’s principles. I therefore hold that the utility theory is more fundamental than the other” ; which other he also calls a “ secondary law,” applicable only to special cases, while the utility theory is applicable to all cases (pp. 250, 252). FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 87 nently,” since the “produce cannot be increased.” 8 Thus Ricardo himself corrected his theory very nearly as we have done. But then this would be his theory, and not the one which he expounded in the chapters expressly devoted to it! But no, in other later passages, considerably more numerous than these few, he re lapsed into his original theory.9 Therefore really it is that wrong and correction-needing theory which is peculiarly his theory; and it is the cost-value theory proper, for those who apply the cost-value theory to exchange-value can apply it consistently only in this way, and they can correct it only by invoking the es teem-value theory of exchange-value. And in fact his correction itself was not correctly made. Purely dog matic was his assertion that the deviation of “ market value,” or exchange-value proper, from “ natural value,” or cost-value, is only accidental and temporary. 8 Pages 150, 151. In a later work he reverts to saying “ the only perma nent cause of rise in the value of corn is an increased charge on its production, caused by the necessity of cultivating poorer lands ” (p. 460). But above, for the higher value, he has noticed a different permanent cause, so that this is not the only one. In another passage he says the supply may not be deficient, and yet the price will be permanently higher “ because there has been an in creased cost in producing it ” (p. 96); for he conceived the people as needing just so much corn and getting it at any cost. This is true, as a matter of fact, only in the first stages, when the population is small and lavishly supplied from the lands of greater fertility. In the later stages supposed by the pas sage above in the text, the people simply do have to put up with a smaller supply, and to make the best use of it. 9 Thus on p. 05 he speaks of certain commodities rising in price “in con sequence of more labor being expended on them.” “ In another part of this work [the first chapter], I have endeavored to show, that the real value of a commodity is regulated, not by the accidental advantages which may be enjoyed by some of its producers, but by the real difficulties encountered by that producer who is least favored ” (p. 220). The original theory first ap peared on p. 373, and is repeated on pp. 60, 70, 91, 104, 135, 150, 151, 171, 198, 200, 220, 221, 246, 251, 460, 475. 88 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE We have seen that it is just as natural to bull prices up toward their upper limit as it is to bear them down to ward their lower limit. If there are accidental and tem porary causes affecting exchange-values, there also are accidental and temporary causes affecting cost-values. Moreover, Ricardo never corrected his erroneous state ments about labor being the cause of exchange-value, as far as labor went. He merely sought for a new cause when exchange-value rose above what he could account for by labor. Also his use of terms continues wrong; for just as by “ market value” he meant “ market ex changeable value,” so by “ natural value” he meant “natural exchangeable value.” He tried to treat them both as varieties of exchange-value; " whereas they are coordinate species, and his “ natural value,” being costvalue, is not exchange-value at all, although it may sometimes agree with it. ' The later acknowledgment of error in the first ex position is, after all, only a repetition of the admission momentarily made at the outset. There one class of objects were allowed not to have their exchange-value regulated by cost, for the very good reasons that some of them have no cost, others have no present cost, and others again, by natural (or artificial) restriction, e. (/., the “ wines of peculiar quality,” have a monopoly price. Of monopolized goods, he later tells us, “ the price has no necessary connection with their natural value” (p. 234); wherefore, as he had no clear idea how it is regu lated, he called it “ a fanciful price” (p. 150). Thus of the things in the first class it was only the market value that Ricardo momentarily considered, and then dis missed on the ground that “ these commodities form a very small part of the mass of commodities daily ex FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 89 changed in the market ” — in spite of the fact that the paper money which, when he wrote, appeared in every transaction in the market, belonged to that class. We were there given to understand that nothing more was to be said about these things with their unaccountable values; yet now they, or others behaving like them, constantly reappear, like Nature, pitched out with a fork, always recurring, or, better, like the evil spirit which, when driven forth, returned with seven others. There we were told that he would pay attention only, to the things in the second class — “ such commodities as can be increased in quantity by the exertion of human industry, and on the production of which competition operates without restraint.” It was of these he there maintained that their value (= exchange-value = market value) always agrees with their natural value. But in their case also he admitted, in the later revision, that their market value, or exchange-value, can deviate, though only more or less temporarily, from their natural value, or cost-value. And we find that this deviation of their exchange-value from their cost-value is due to the same cause which regulates the exchange-value of the things in the first class, namely, scarcity in addition to utility, or the amount of existing goods in relation to the people’s desire for them — in short, supply and de mand. Thus Ricardo really entertained two theories of exchange-value: the one, that it is due to supply and demand (the esteem-value theory of exchange-value), the other, that it is due to cost (the cost-value theory of exchange-value). He used the first, really, of all com modities, though of some only temporarily. He used the second of as many commodities as he could, and as often and as long as he could, and when he could not, 90 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE he fell back on the first. Evidently the first is the more important; and yet he tried to make out that the second is the only important one. The first he had abundant facts to prove; the second he never even attempted to prove. It was an a -priori theory. At the end of the fourth chapter he says: “ In speaking, then, of the exchangeable valu^ of commodities, or the power of purchasing possessed by any one commodity, I mean always that power which it would possess, if not dis,tur.bsd^b-y~*ny temporary or accidental cause, and which is its natural price.” What does this mean but that by exchange-value he meant the value which a thing would have if it were determined by its cost-value, — if, in fact, it behaved as his theory demanded? And this after admitting that actually it does ROt so behave! He simply did not mean always what he here tells us he always meant. His theory is merely the analytical one about cost-value, and it is true of exchange-value only when exchange-value happens to agree with cost-value. This absence of any attempt at proof of his theory applied to exchange-value is serious. We have seen that Ricardo denied the possibility of a measure of value, that is, of cost-value (as well as of exchange-value), and we have perceived the mistake in his denial (above, in XII). If cdst-value exists, it should be measurable, since it depends on costs, and costs are measurable. This provides a means of testing the cost-value theory of exchange-value. We have seen that if the variation of the cost-value of the unit of something were deter mined over several periods, the inverse portion or excess of this unit would have a stable cost-value. Now, if Ricardo’s theory that exchange-value is regulated by cost-value were true, the variations of the units of all FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 91 other things could be found by comparing their prices with the prices of these portions of the standard thing that have stable cost-value. But the cost-values of several other things over the same periods could equally well be ascertained directly, in the same manner as were the cost-values of that first thing, and these other things could equally well serve as standards. Then it would be seen whether they agreed or not. Yet if they did not agree, Ricardo’s followers could say it was because the prices used were only market prices. This merely shows the hopelessness of the tangle in which they have wound themselves. No practical use of the cost-value theory of exchange-value can ever be made, because of the possi bility, always existing, that, after all, exchange-value, now disparagingly called mere “ market value,” may deviate from it. The best his followers can do is to fall in behind that most ardent admirer of his, DeQuincey, who wrote: “ A measure of value which cannot be prac tically applied is worthless; as a measure of value, there fore, Mr. Ricardo’s law of value is worthless.” But no blame was to be settled on Mr. Ricardo on that account, “ for Mr. Ricardo never dreamed of offering a standard or fixed measure of value.” 10 Ricardo, in fact, was a broker, and knew nothing about the costs of producing things, and apparently had no desire to know anything about them.11 His followers may defend him by going on with DeQuincey, who challenged “ any man to show that the great interests of Political Economy have at all suffered from want of such a measure, which at best would end in answering a few questions of unprofitable 10 The Templars’ Dialogues, V. 11 DeQuincey somewhere tells of a Manchester merchant who dealt in wheat for forty years, and never once saw a wheat field. 92 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE curiosity; whilst, on the other hand, without a know ledge of the ground [ = source, cause] on which value depends, or without some approximation to it, Political Economy could not exist at all, except as a heap of base less opinions.” 12 The uses of this knowledge are stated to be its influence on all the derivative laws, and its simplification of the science. DeQuincey could not fore see that one of the uses of Ricardo’s theory would be to establish Marxism and Bolshevism. Indeed, it may be said that of all false theories Ricardo’s has proved itself the most pernicious. Ricardo himself made no such deduction. He used his own theory when he could, and he used the other when it suited him. His own theory is at the bottom of his mistakes. The other is what led him to truth. One of his mistakes was to maintain that wages and profits can vary only inversely to each other, or at each other’s expense. This is an obvious deduction from the prin ciple that exchange-value always is exactly bound down to, and is identical with, cost-value. But it is vitiated by the fact that exchange-value, or market value, is not so bound and is not identical with cost-value.13 The por12 Ibid. Cf. his later Logic of Political Economy, 1844, pp. 45, 49 (chap. 3, section 3). There he admits one use of measurement*, to determine “ varia tions in the stages of a paper money ” — not a matter of mere idle curiosity! 13 Even leaving the deviation of market value out of the question, this proposition, though true in one sense, is false in another. Even if exchangevalue always were identical with cost-value at the same time and place, we shall presently see that they are not identical in the course of time. If under better management labor becomes more productive, there will be more to distribute, so that the purchasing power (or exchange-value) of both wages and profits may increase together. But Ricardo held that this greater prod uct has only the same “ value” as before, because produced by the same amount of capital and labor —■ it has the same cost-value, which he still identifies with exchange-value. Now, of course, the invariable cost-value of the variable product can be shared only by the laborer getting more as the 93 tion of Ricardo’s political economy that has been of the greatest value is his discussion of monetary prob lems, in which his profession made him well versed. Of his treatment of money, nine tenths was an application to it of the quantity theory (the esteem-value theory of its exchange-value).14 And his one great error in the theory of money was due to his cost-value theory of exchange-value. He said the ratio of gold to silver, then hovering between 15 and 16 to 1, was owing “ solely” to the fact that “fifteen times the quantity of labor is necessary to produce a given quantity” of gold than of silver (p. 213). Thirty years later DeQuincey was able to repeat the same assertion.15 That ratio had existed already for many years, and it continued until 1873, when it suddenly began to change and has been variable ever since. It is the “ market value” ratio, and here was a remarkable instance of the market values not de viating from the alleged natural values for a very long run. Ricardo and DeQuincey never examined whether FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE capitalist gets less, and conversely. This again is a worthless (except for being a misleading) analytical proposition. Because of it, Ricardo maintained that “ a real rise of wages is necessarily followed by a real fall of profits,” p. 534, “real” here having reference to labor-cost, whereas it ought to refer to the product, or to what the product can obtain in exchange — to the exchangevalue proper of the product, concerning which the statement is absolutely false. It led him into the terrible blunder of saying “ there is no other way of keeping profits up but by keeping wages down ” (p. 476). 14 He began with this in 1809 and 1811, before he distinctly developed his cost-value theory; and he did not give it up afterwards. At the beginning he said that, if a gold mine were discovered in some country, its currency “ would be lowered in consequence of the increased quantity” (p. 264). Cf. above, in n. 9 on p. 87. 16 In his alarmist essay on the gold discoveries in California. A few years later Jevons, who was in Australia during the gold fever there, believed that gold was being extracted at a cost greater than it was worth (Investigations, pp. 70-71). 94 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE the mines were producing just fifteen times as much silver as gold at the same cost: they never conceived that to be necessary. And in fact it was not necessary; for it is perfectly possible that some gold mine some where and some silver mine somewhere else were yield ing gold and silver at that ratio to the same amount of labor, and no good would be accomplished by finding just what mines were doing so. But to assert that these two sets of mines caused gold to be so many times more valuable than silver was to assign a most inadequate cause, in view of the quantities of the two metals already accumulated at all sorts of costs. With equal likelihood there were other mines that could have been worked, but were not because it did not pay to work them; and after 1873 some gold mines were opened which could not be profitably worked before, and some silver mines were closed because they could no longer be worked except at a loss. Obviously it was the existing exchange-values of gold and silver, due to the existing supplies and to the monetary and other demands for them, that per mitted some mines to be worked and others not. Ri cardo reversed the order of cause and effect. And the principal reason why gold and silver had the ratio they had was before his eyes, staring him in the face; but he could not see it, being blinded by his false theory. Yet, with regard to paper money, Ricardo always said that its value — its market value, its exchange-value — depends entirely on its quantity (relatively to the de mand for it), and that its exchange-value could be kept in agreement with that of gold by regulating its quantity (pp. 214, 265, 346, 398) — and not only temporarily, but apparently forever. In fact, he considered paper money, so regulated, the most perfect form of money FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 95 (pp. 218, 301, 397, 404^05). But the cost of producing paper money has nothing to do with its exchange-value. Then why is it that the cost of producing gold should necessarily be the regulator, temporary or permanent, of its exchange-value? Ricardo himself said of money in general, “ The demand for money is regulated entirely by its value, and its value by its quantity” (p. 114).16 Here, of gold money in particular, he added: “ From its durable nature, and from the difficulty of reducing its quantity, it does not readily bend to variations in its market value.” This seems to be a misstatement for say ing that, for these reasons, its market value, or exchangevalue, does not readily bend to its natural value, or cost-value. This, however, would be inconsistent with the notion that its market value and that of silver did bend to their natural values for so long a time. Rather, these reasons account for their natural values, or costvalues, not readily affecting their exchange-values. That was why Ricardo was at liberty to apply the quan tity theory to explain the variations of their exchangevalue. But in doing so he was not using his own costvalue theory.17 16 And (p.337 n.) lie spoke of “ an alteration in the value of the precious metals, arising from their abundance or scarcity.” 17 Ricardo said that throughout his reasonings about the exchange-values of commodities he would assume that the “ value” of gold, or of money, was invariable (pp. 29, 60 n.). What could he mean by that? Suppose the costvalue of gold were invariable: still its market value could be variable. Perhaps, then, he meant that the market value as well as the natural value of gold should be invariable. But if the market value of gold were invariable, that would be enough, and everybody (except gold miners)would be indifferent to variations of its cost-value, about which they would know nothing. We may take a hint from a passage already quoted. He meant that the exchangevalue of money should be what it would be if it remained in agreement with an invariable cost-value of gold, whether gold happened to be invariable in cost-value or not. This, of course, does not mean that the exchange-value of money should be invariable. XVIII ON LABOR-COST ic a r d o , however, was justified in objecting to Adam Smith’s doctrine that rent is a component part of price. But he should have objected likewise to Adam Smith’s doctrine that wages and profit are component parts of price. To the capitalist-employer producers two of these, wages to all, and rent to those who pay rent, and also interest (wrongly confounded with profit), are com ponent parts of costs. Prices are what the producers can get and what the consumers will give. They have no component parts. They must, in the long run, be above the costs, and the difference is profit. Profit is not a component part, or cause, of price, but an effect from the existent cost and price, which have different, though interacting, causes. Here we have unavoidably run over from exchangevalues to prices, and from labor to wages. Prices, at any one time and place, correctly measure exchangevalues, and different wages indicate different kinds or qualities of labor. To expound the labor-cost theory of exchange-value entirely in terms of labor is an even more impossible task, and involves a vicious circle. The money-cost of the labor that has gone into the pro duction of a commodity is composed of all the various wages and salaries paid to the employees, including the managers, all the different kinds of labor receiving dif ferent pay, but all measurable in the money-unit.1 If R 1 The subject of wages has at the beginning been excluded from the range of this paper. Labor has no value, and there is no need of speaking of the “ value of labor,” the term “ wages” being sufficient. Wages, however, have FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 97 the labor-cost simply — the mere expenditure of labor, so many hours of so many laborers be considered, we shall have to assign different “ values” to the different labor of the different laborers without possessing any labor-unit to measure them in. “ Value must here be taken in an extra-economic and mathematical sense. an hour of one man’s labor is to be considered as a quantity of labor equivalent to two hours of another man’s labor, when the former ordinarily, because of its greater efficiency, at the same time and place receives double the wages (or salary) of the latter. The costvalue theorists have generally slurred over this point. They have generally taken for their unit the labor of the worst paid large class of laborers they were familiar with, and have then treated it as an easy matter to re duce all the other superior labor to this unit. But the only way they have of making this reduction is by means of the wages or salaries the superior kinds of laborers ordinarily command and receive. Thus if any one kind of a commodity is produced by one hour of all the kinds of labor required for its production, and an equally valuable commodity of another kind is produced by two hours of all the kinds of labor required for producing it, the fact of the equal value of the two commodities is taken as showing that really the same quantity of labor has been employed to produce them, and therefore the some analogy with value; which accounts for the practice of identifying them. Similar theories have been invented to explain them: a cost-ofproduction theory, applied to the upkeep of the labor supply, and the scar city theory, as the scarcity of competent laborers in different branches affects their comparative remuneration. But the “ value” of the product is always at the bottom of the question of wages. Hence the subject of wages, which belongs under production, should be treated after the subject of “ value,” which belongs under consumption. Cf., above, note on p, 68. 98 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE one hour of labor producing the former is the same quantity of labor as the two hours of labor producing the latter. Evidently the quantity of labor going into the production of the two articles is now being deter mined by the exchange-value of the articles, and not the exchange-value of the articles by the quantity of labor. There is no beginning or end to this method of reasoning. At best, the cost-value theorists can hold that labor is according to the laborer. This was main tained by Aristotle, who said that as the agriculturist is superior to the shoe-maker, so the product (and its value) of the agriculturist’s labor is superior to that of the shoe-maker’s. But this evidently inverts the se quence of cause and effect. A great artist earns more than, and is superior to, a shoe-maker, because his prod ucts have greater “ value,” including greater exchangevalue.2 Thus, altogether, labor, though it creates wealth, does not create value, except in the single sense of “ value” meaning cost-value. Labor produces things that have value, but it does not produce any value ex cept cost-value. Neither use-value nor esteem-value nor exchange-value is produced or caused by labor. These values come to the products of labor, as to the things not produced by labor, from elsewhere. The three come to an object that has value from its utility, and the later two both come to it from its scarcity. 2 A poor picture by a great painter may have greater exchange-value than a better picture by an inferior artist, because, through association with his other better pictures, the former acquires greater esteem-value than the latter. The anomaly is to be explained under the theory of esteem-value. Exchange-value here, as always (so the esteem-value theorists of exchangevalue maintain), is determined by esteem-value. But economists need not pursue desire into all its vagaries. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 99 People produce things only for the sake of these values in the things. They expend labor upon them, if neces sary, up to their value. Things have cost-value only because they have the other values. Condillac was right. XIX GENERAL EXCHANGE-VALUES ACCORDING TO COMPARATIVE SOCIAL ESTEEM-VALUES T h is leads us to the esteem-value theory of exchangevalue. The full explanation of exchange-value could not be given till the theory of esteem-value was developed. From of old people have held the rough-and-ready, ruleof-thumb theory of “ supply and demand,” as it is called, which says that the “ value” of a thing varies directly with the demand for it and inversely with the supply of it. If by “ demand” be meant desire and by “ supply” the quantity possessed, this is merely a statement of the law of esteem-value. But “ demand” and “ supply” mean more than that. “ Demand” for a certain kind of things means the quantity of other things offered in ex change for it by the persons desiring it, while the quan tity of the thing offered by persons desiring the other things is its “ supply.” All exchanges are between pos sessors, however they came to possess the things they exchange. They need not be the producers of them. In regard to the things now possessed which were pro duced by past labor and whose exact copies cannot be reproduced, we have seen that the cost-value theorists agree with the esteem-value theorists, having really aban doned the field to them. We are concerned, therefore, not only with exchanges between contemporary pro ducers and consumers, but with all possible exchanges. The same person qua consumer is very different from himself qua producer. Of any given article the con sumers are much more numerous than the producers: FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 101 of some articles the whole people are consumers. Con sumers are concerned only with the esteem-value to themselves of what they give and get in an exchange. How this value is determined, we have already seen; and the cost of production of articles had nothing to do with it. Producers, however, generally produce their own article in such excessive quantities that its esteemvalue to them as an article of consumption, after the production, is practically nil; but as an article of ex change, and useful to them for this purpose, its esteemvalue to them was, in anticipation, at least somewhat greater than its cost-value, or else they would have had no motive to produce it. In the open markets of a country, people are able to compare the esteem-values they set upon things by each one learning how much others are desirous of getting and are willing to give; whereas the cost-value of every article is known only to its producers, and these generally conceal it, and even try to deceive others about it. Moreover, even if it could be found out, people are more interested with the esteem-value to themselves of the things they exchange than they are with the cost-value of every article to its particular producers, about which they care so little that they rarely make inquiries, and if told, pay little attention. But as esteem-value is determined by quan tity, which is variable, general utility being almost a constant, everybody is interested in the quantities in the market, whether recently produced and reproduc ible, or produced only in the past. This is the reason why the esteem-value theory accounts for monopolized goods as well as for those freely produced. The proper meaning of the terms “ production” and “ producer” is the act, or agent, not only of making but also of bring 102 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE ing to market. In this broad sense there are producers of antiques as well as of ordinary things. Now, in every exchange each party receives an article of higher esteem-value to himself than the article has which he gives, because otherwise there would be no motive for making the exchange. Each party wishes the excess to be as great as possible. The consumer wishes to purchase as far as possible below his esteemvalue, and the producer wishes to sell as far as possible above his cost-value. When the exchange is of a single commodity for money, the two parties set upon it dif ferent estimates of its esteem-value to themselves, that of the purchaser being the higher; and the price at which the sale is effected will range between these esti mates. In the open markets of a country, where many producers come with various quantities of all commodi ties, and many consumers (often the same persons) come with variously intensive desires for various quan tities of all the commodities, the estimates on both sides in regard to every commodity will have a wide range, crossing one another variously. Ordinarily, the higher the price first set, the greater the offer and the less the demand; the lower the price, the less the offer and the greater the demand. So in the case of each commodity individually,1each in turn when sold giving its producers 1 Of each article the supply and the demand may be represented diagrammatically by two curves, generally crossing each other. These curves represent the conditions on one particular occasion, and they change per haps every day. Sometimes, when the production of an article is exceeding its consumption, prices fall, consumers (and the middlemen near to them) stock up, and a day comes when “ the bottom falls out of prices” and there is a “glut.” At other times, when consumption is exceeding production, prices rising, there comes a day when producers (including the middlemen nearest them) have no stock and are almost indifferent about sales. On the former day the supply curve is so high as hardly to meet the demand curve. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 103 opportunity to appear as purchasers of other things, and all forming one great system of interactions. The price at which the supply and the demand equal each other is the price which will prevail. It may not be im mediately hit, and meanwhile conditions may change: the actual prices will trail the theoretical or normal prices. The normal prices, on assumed conditions, can be calculated mathematically. The best mathematical treatment of the subject has been made by Walras; the best in common language, by Bohm-Bawerk.2 Mill On the latter, the demand curve is so high as hardly to meet the supply curve. Between these there are many gradations. This remark is necessary because these curves are often taken to represent the course, instead of the state, of things. 3 Bohm-Bawerk, however, in one small detail has made a mathematical mistake. He says, op. cit., pp. 267-270, that in an isolated bargain between the seller and the purchaser of a single article, if the former estimates it at 100 florins and the latter at 300, and if they are both equally good bargainers so that neither gets the better of the other, the price will be about 200, each gaining a hundred. He here argues as Nozzolini did in a certain seventeenthcentury controversy reviewed by me in The Problem of Estimation, since he lights immediately on the arithmetical mean as the proper one to draw be tween the two estimates. But Galileo, as shown by his argumentation in that controversy, would have argued that this was wrong, in that the seller would gain the double of his estimate, but the purchaser only two thirds of his, or, in other words, the seller has after the transaction 100 per cent more than his estimate, but the purchaser has an article which he estimates only 50 per cent more than he paid. Galileo would therefore have said that the equal bargain, showing equal skill in both parties, would have been at a price which is the geometric mean between 100 and 300, viz., a trifle over 173, which would give the seller 73 per cent more than his estimate, and the pur chaser an article which he estimates 73 per cent above what he paid. We may even suppose that the estimates were actual exchange-values, — that the seller had paid 100 for the article, and the purchaser later sells it for 300. Or, with allowance for expenses, we may suppose the seller had bought the article for 90 and after spending 10 on it estimates it at 100, and the buyer after spending 10 on it sells it for 300. The equalizing price would then be represented by x in the proportion 100 : x = (x + 10) : 300, which yields x = 168j, giving to both the same profit of 68j per cent on each one’s outlay. 104 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE came very near to correctly stating the theory, in his doctrine of the equation of supply and demand; but missed it because of not clearly recognizing the distinc tion between esteem-value and use-value. The theory involves that every purchaser of a com modity sets an esteem-value upon it at least as high as the price, and has something to give which he does not esteem so high, those to whom its esteem-value is not so high being shut out, even though they have plenty of other things to give for it. It involves also that every producer who continues to produce the thing can pro duce it at a cost at least as low as, or, rather, lower than, the price. The highest cost required to produce the amount demanded sets the lowest limit to the price while the demand at that price continues; but, as we have seen, nothing hinders the price, when the demand increases, from rising above the highest cost, and above the cost-value, if this be held fixed by natural or artificial restriction. Not so with the relationship between the price and esteem-value. The price cannot go above the esteem-value which at least some one sets upon the thing — that is, if it be an effective price, a sale taking place; and it will not fall below the esteem-value repre sented by the figure at which some one will purchase the last increment offered. Exchange-value necessarily is tied to some esteem-value; and it is determined by the esteem-value which equalizes the demand to the supply or the supply to the demand. The theory is, obviously, the same for monopolized as for freely produced goods, the difference coming in only on the side of produc tion. The prices of all articles, so determined, may be said to indicate the comparative general esteem-values that FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 105 the people as a whole sets upon the articles in the mar kets. These general esteem-values may be called the social esteem-values of the articles, in distinction from the various personal esteem-values in which they are held by individuals. If the cost-value theory of ex change-values were true, the same distinction would have to be made in cost-values. There are, as we have seen, various personal cost-values, every producer having his own; but the idea of a social cost-value is a mere fiction, since the people at large do not produce every single thing, and the cost of a thing to its non-producing consumer can only be transferred to it from the cost of what he gives in exchange, and to some persons what they give has cost them nothing. In exchange-value, however, the same distinction reappears; for the prices prevailing in the open markets indicate the social exchange-values of the articles, while particular exchanges sometimes take place at other rates, which may be called personal exchange-values, and, when differing from the social, are not considered fair indications of the thing’s true exchange-value.3 The term “ social” applied to two kinds of value must not be taken to imply that all value is social — far from it. Every purchaser who keeps what he gets, does so because his personal esteem-value set upon it is higher than its social esteemvalue; and any one whose esteem-value for a thing is lower than its social esteem-value, must go without it, or if he happens to have it, he is likely to sell it. Now, 3 General exchange-value is only social exchange-value, since personal exchange-values, when different from the social, are only infrequent, not repeated, and cannot be averaged. These are not a subject of interest. The term “ social exchange-value” is not needed, since “ general exchange-value” is better and is sufficient. 106 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE in the money régime, at any one time and place, prices indicate exchange-values; for in every exchange in open markets the articles exchanged have, by definition, equal exchange-values. Hence exchange-values are ac cording to comparative social esteem-values. XX THE DIVERGENCE OF EXCHANGE-VALUES FROM ESTEEM-VALUES IN THE COURSE OF TIME I t needs to be emphasized that exchange-values are according to, or are determined by, comparative social esteem-values; for they are not simply equal to, or identical with, social esteem-values. Most of our treat ment of the subject so far has been conducted on the supposition that we are dealing with things in the same place and at about the same time. It is necessary now to deal with the values of things at different times,— dif ferent places being mostly neglected for simplicity, — that is, with things as they are valued by a people in the same country through the course of time. Exchangevalues may, as time advances, cease to agree with social esteem-values — or simply with esteem-values, as we shall again generally omit the epithet, since our atten tion is principally centered upon social values.1 For we have seen that in the course of time all things can rise or fall in esteem-value, whereas all things cannot rise or fall in exchange-value. Exchange-values are in terrelative, while esteem-values (along with cost-values) have something absolute about them, since they vary independently of one another; but every variation of one exchange-value involves an opposite variation of 1 Naturally, in the course of time, personal esteem-values vary on the whole with social esteem-values — in fact, leading the way. The personal esteem-values of any one thing vary manifoldly, and the variation of its social esteem-value, or simply of its esteem-value, is a middle term between the extreme variations. 108 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE some other exchange-value.2 It is this companionship at one time, or for a short time, and this eventual part ing of company in the course of time, of esteem-value and exchange-value, that has caused the confusion. For while they are together, the same term is applicable to both; but when they diverge in their variations, only one term being still employed, inconsistency arises. If all things fell exactly alike in esteem-value, their exchange-values would remain entirely unchanged. Also if all things fell exactly alike in cost-value, and if it fur ther happened that their exchange-values were regulated accordingly, and if the things that have no cost-value behaved as if they had, then too their exchange-values would remain unchanged. If things fell on the whole in these values, but differently, there would be variations of their exchange-values corresponding to the differences in these falls, but exchange-values on the whole would still be constant. In this respect esteem-value and cost-value are alike, and form one category, over against exchange-value as forming another. For generally esteem-values and cost-values vary in the course of time more or less closely together, since either the dis covery or utilization of new sources that are worked more cheaply, or the application of better machinery or processes producing more than before by the same labor, or both together, increases supplies and thereby per mits a fall of esteem-values along with the fall of cost-values; or conversely, with the increase of costs, the scarcity which is either its cause or its effect, causes a 2 The exchange-values of all things can, of course, fall successively, just as all the molecules of water in a pond can sink one after another, though they cannot all do so at the same time. And the reason is the same in both eases, in that the sinking of one thing shoves others up. It is a very simple fallacy to think that all exchange-values can fall together. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 109 rise of esteem-values along with the rise of cost-values. The ulterior causes of these changes — whether they be expansion and new inventions, or the impossibility of further expansion, the exhaustion of sources, and de generacy of the people — need not here concern us. Mankind is now, and has been for several centuries, and is likely to be for some time to come, in an era of improvement and of expansion greater than the growth of population, and both the cost-values and the esteemvalues of most, if not of all, things, have been, are, and are likely to be, falling. But the exchange-values of all things are not falling. Only the prices of all things may fall — not necessarily do fall. For all prices can vary together, like esteemvalues; but they do not necessarily do so. They may, on the whole, remain stable, like exchange-values; they may even, on the whole, rise, though esteem-values (and cost-values) on the whole are falling. At a given time and place prices correctly indicate exchangevalues, so that the terms may be interchanged. Con sequently some economists have confounded them, and have habitually used “ price” for “ exchange-value.” This is unobjectionable for contemporary and coregional prices and exchange-values. It is, however, no longer correct when prices and exchange-values are compared at different times and places. This identifica tion of prices with exchange-values (always so far mean ing general exchange-values) and through them with esteem-values (and less closely with cost-values) at the same time and place, along with the possibility (though not the necessity) of prices accompanying esteem-values (and approximately cost-values) through the course of time, is what has permitted economists to make the mis 110 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE take of thinking also of general exchange-values as accompanying esteem-values (and cost-values) through the course of time. But it is only the particular ex change-values of things in money that are always iden tical, in magnitude, with prices, by definition;3 and it is only these particular exchange-values of things in money that can accompany their esteem-values (and cost-values) as they fall all together, or on the whole. Then the particular exchange-values of money in the things, the reciprocals of the prices, all rise together, or on the average, which means that the general exchangevalue of money rises. In other words, the general ex change-value of money rises if prices accompany the falling esteem-values (or cost-values) of things. If money is to remain stable in general exchange-value, the average of prices must remain stable, some prices rising and others falling as esteem-values vary among themselves in their general fall. Then prices keep com pany with the general exchange-values of things, varying as they do; but part company with their esteem-values (or cost-values), varying only as these do relatively to one another, but not as they do absolutely. Ricardo knew nothing about the compensatory action of oppositely varying particular exchange-values and the consequent possibility of measuring the variation of the general exchange-value of a thing (especially of money) by averaging the variations of its particular exchange-values (or, inversely, of prices).4 He had 3 For the definition of price is the amount of money that can be obtained in exchange for the thing, and this is also the definition of the particular ex change-value of the thing in money, with the only difference that the latter is, not the amount of money itself, but the power to obtain it. 4 “ Even this comparison [with the value of many other commodities] does not afford a certain test [of the value of gold or money], because one FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 111 heard of the proposal to judge of the value of money “ by its relation to the mass of commodities” (p. 400), as it had been made in England in his day by G. Shuckburgh Evelyn, Arthur Young, and J. P. Smith, al though the first serious effort to measure the general exchange-value of money in this way and to reduce con tracts to a stable value of this kind was made by Joseph Lowe a year after the last edition in his lifetime of his Principles. But because of his ignorance of the method of executing this proposal, and because of his identifica tion of exchange-value with cost-value at the same time and place, Ricardo not unnaturally fell into the way of identifying these two kinds of value at all times and places. As all commodities can rise or fall in costvalue, “ why,” he asked, “ should all commodities to gether be the standard, when such a standard is itself subject to fluctuations in value?” (p. 166). This can be true of “ value” only in the sense of cost-value (or esteem-value), but Ricardo applied it to exchangevalue: “ the exchangeable value of all commodities rises as the difficulties of their production increase” (p. 377). Still, he did dimly perceive that all commodities cannot rise or fall together in exchange-value;5 which precisely fits them for being a standard, wherefore if any one thing, say money, preserved all its particular exchange-values constant on the average, money would half of the commodities to which they are compared may have varied in one direction, while the other half may have varied in another: by which half shall the variation of gold be tried? If by one, it appears to have risen; if by the other, to have fallen” (p. 470). Similarly p. 228. The confusion is caused by the idea of cost-value being implicitly present, as it is explicitly on pp. 400-401. 6 “Corn rises because it is more difficult to produce, and its cost is in creased; it would be no rise at all if all other things rose with it” (p. 463). 112 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE be stable in “ value” in the sense of general exchangevalue. Only this dim perception never rose to clear conscious recognition, and therefore he had to deny that all commodities together can serve for such a standard,6 and to fall back on his position that “ that commodity is alone invariable [in value] which at all times requires the same sacrifice of toil and trouble to produce it.” 7 Now, Ricardo had a right to the opinion, perfectly ob vious and merely analytical, that only what is stable in cost of production is stable in “ value,” provided he al ways recognized, and proclaimed, that by “ value” he meant only a kind of value, namely cost-value, which by definition is tied to cost; but this opinion could then exert no influence on the views about exchange-value of those who clearly recognize the distinction, at least through the course of time, if not at the same time, be tween cost-value and exchange-value. When the theory of esteem-value and its application to exchange-value was worked out, its discoverers might have made a similar mistake of inferring that because 6 “I cannot agree with M. Say in estimating the value of a commodity by the abundance of other commodities for which it will exchange ” (p. 171). Yet this contradicts the following: “ The only proof which we possess of the relative value of money in two places, is by comparing it with commodities. Commodities measure the value of money in the same manner as money measures the value of commodities. If, then, commodities will purchase more money [ = if money will purchase less commodities] in England than in France, we may justly say that money is cheaper in England ” (p. 293; cf. p. 266). The solution of the contradiction is, of course, that the latter passage refers to “ market value” and the former to “ natural value” ; yet the con tradiction still exists when we remember that Ricardo subsumed both these values under exchange-value. 7 Page 166. Because all commodities are produced by labor, “ labor is a common measure by which their real as well as their relative value may be estimated” (p. 171). Their “ real value” in the sense of cost-value, yes; but their “ relative value” in the sense of exchange-value, no. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 113 all exchange-values are in agreement with comparative esteem-values at the same time and place, therefore they all rise or fall through the course of time with the rise or fall of all esteem-values. Jevons, who had already himself devoted attention to the measurement of gen eral exchange-value, and Walras, who afterwards did the same, escaped making this mistake. Menger also did not make it so baldly as Ricardo had done; but he bordered upon it. Because of certain difficulties in measuring variations of the general exchange-value of anything, he concluded that this measurement is im possible. And then, without showing how the measure ment of variation of esteem-value is any more easily and accurately attainable, he centered his attention upon esteem-value. As Ricardo, merely because of his theory explaining exchange-values by comparative costvalues, conceived only of money remaining stable in cost-value as its one way of remaining stable in “ value,” and desired it to remain stable in “ value” in this sense, so Menger, simply because of his theory explaining exchange-values by comparative esteem-values, like wise desiring money to remain stable in “ value,” ap proved of its remaining stable in esteem-value. Menger would also have been perfectly justified in saying that only in case money is stable in esteem-value is it stable in “ value,” provided he clearly stated that by “ value” he meant only esteem-value. Then this likewise merely analytical proposition would have no influence on the views about exchange-value of those who recognize the distinction, through the course of time, between esteemvalue and exchange-value. Similarly any one else who says that by “ value” he means always exchange-value, would be equally justi 114 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE fied in maintaining that only in case money is stable in exchange-value is it stable in “ value.” And this further merely analytical proposition need have no more in fluence on the views of those who distinguish cost-value and esteem-value from exchange-value and who desire money to be stable in the one or the other of these kinds of value. The merely arbitrary restriction of the term “ value” to one of its kinds cannot properly serve as the basis of argument. Some amplification of what is here advanced is needed. This leads to two more subjects. XXI PRACTICAL USES OF THE MEASUREMENTS F ir st , w e m u st exam in e som e o f th e p ractical uses to w h ich th e m easurem ents o f th e kin d s o f v a lu e can be pu t. The practical use of a measurement of the use-value of things, and in particular of money, would seem to be small. In economics, beyond recognizing that use-value increases in some proportion with quantity (except in the case of money, when fully introduced, although in a growing and progressing population more of it may be needed for it to serve certain of its purposes well), we have little need for further information on the subject. The measurement of cost-value also seems of little im portance, except to the producers, or from a technical viewpoint. The variation of the average of all costs of production may show the variation of the general costvalues of all commodities to their producers, but not necessarily, as we have seen, to the people at large. The people at large are affected only as lowered costs are permitted, by the producers, to increase the quantities of goods supplied to them — that is, to increase their real income. When, or to the extent that, this is not permitted, the measurement of the variation of costvalues is of no use at all in political economy; and when it is permitted, then it agrees with, and is no better than, the measurement of the variation of real income. This latter measurement, which, inverted, is a measure ment of the esteem-value of all things in general, may not only satisfy our curiosity as to whether progress has 116 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE been made or not, and how great; but it may aid us to experiment with different régimes — as, for instance, whether more progress is made under free trade or un der protection. Now, this information can be obtained by a combination of two measurements: of the varia tion of the social esteem-value of money, and of the variation of the social or general exchange-value of money, in the following way. It is especially facilitated if the one or the other of these values of money be found to have no variation, or to be constant or stable, al though this is not necessary. These, then, are the two measurements it is important for statisticians to de velop. Let us suppose that these two measurements have been performed. We may consider two hypothetical cases. The first is that over a long tract of time the esteemvalue of money is found (or has been made) to be stable, that is, the average of money-incomes has been constant. If, then, the general exchange-value of money, which is the more or less accurately weighted average of its particular exchange-values, or inversely of prices, is found to have risen or fallen to a certain extent, such a rise (or fall of prices) indicates that the constant aver age money-income purchases more commodities, on an average, in the same proportion with the variation of the general exchange-value of money (or with the inverse variation of prices) ; and such a fall (or rise of prices) indicates that the constant average money-income pur chases less commodities proportionally with that fall (or inversely with the rise of prices). The quantities of the different kinds of commodities have had, of course, to be collected as data for weighting the average of FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 117 prices. But only relative, not absolute, quantities need to be used here, and a rough accuracy is sufficient, so that this double method virtually accomplishes the averaging of the variations of quantities with avoidance of the new and difficult problem of properly weighting them. Now then, a variation of the average real income means an inverse variation of the esteem-value of things in general; and the price of every particular thing at a later year, compared with its price at an earlier, in dicates how the social esteem-value of that thing has varied, while the variation of its general exchangevalue is indicated by a comparison of its price-variation with the average variation of all prices. All people desire their real incomes to increase, and the esteemvalues of things to fall. Therefore, if their money-in comes on the average are stable, which means that money is stable in esteem-value, they must wish prices to fall, and the general exchange-value of money to rise. The second case is that over such a tract of time the general exchange-value of money is found (or has been made) to be stable, that is, the weighted average of the particular exchange-values of money, as also of prices, is constant. If, then, the esteem-value of money, which varies inversely with the average variation of moneyincomes, is found to have risen or fallen to a certain extent, such a rise (or fall of average money-income) indicates a proportional fall of the average real income, and such a fall (or rise of average money-income) indi cates a rise of the average real income; for moneyincome and real income now vary together, since prices have not changed on the average. The quantities of goods purchased by the varying money-incomes, and which constitute the real incomes, have had, as before, 118 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE to be collected more or less roughly at all the periods compared; but the advantages of this double method are the same as in the preceding case. Thus, in the present case, while a variation of average money-in come indicates the variation of average real income, the general exchange-values of commodities, taken all together, have necessarily remaine'd stable, and in dividually, in agreement with their particular exchangevalues in money, have varied inversely with their prices, some rising and others falling, and their average esteem-value on the whole has varied inversely with the variation of the average money- or real income. We may get the variation of the social esteem-value of any one thing between two periods by multiplying the variation of its price (the ratio of its later to its earlier price) by the variation of the esteem-value of money (the ratio of its later to its earlier esteem-value). Our desire with regard to real incomes and to the esteemvalues of things is the same as in the preceding case. Therefore, if money is stable in exchange-value, people must wish their average money-income to increase, and the esteem-value of money to fall. In these two cases it is not necessary that the general esteem-value or the general exchange-value of money shall be stable, since an allowance may be made for any variation in the one which is taken for the standard. Here for simplicity we may deal principally with moneyincomes and prices. Numerical examples will also be more convenient. In the first case let us suppose that between one year and another the average of money-incomes is found to have risen 10 per cent, and the average of prices to have fallen 5 per cent. Now, if the money-unit were reduced FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 119 inversely, so that the new unit was equivalent to 1.10 of the old, the money-incomes would be constant in this new unit. The later prices would then have to be reduced at the same rate, by dividing them by 1.10; and also the average of prices. This last operation is 0.95/1.10 — 0.8636, indicating a fall of average price in the new unit of 13.64 per cent. Real incomes, therefore, have risen to the reciprocal of this: 1.00/0.8636 = 1.1579, a rise of 15.79 per cent. Thus the reciprocal of the reduced average price-variation indicates the varia tion of the average real income; or, again, the reduced average price-variation itself indicates the variation of the social esteem-value of things in general. Of every commodity also the price-variation being so reduced, its reduced price compared with its original price will show the variation of its social esteem-value. Such re duced individual prices, compared with the prices at the first year as unities, may be called esteem-value prices, because they are reckoned in a money-unit correctly serving as a measure of esteem-value. In the second case, let us suppose the same actual variations as before, the only difference being in our use of them, our intention now being to reduce things on the supposition that the average of prices had re mained constant. This can be done by raising the money-unit from 0.95 to 1.00, so that the new unit equals 1.00/0.95 or 1.0526 of the old, in which new unit the average of prices would be constant. Then all in comes, and the average income, would have to be raised in the same proportion, being multiplied by 1.0526. The average money-income, so multiplied, becomes 1.1579, a rise of 15.79 per cent. This is the height to which the average of money-incomes has risen in a 120 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE money-unit stable in exchange-value, and so it indi cates the rise of the average of real incomes, giving of course the same figure as before. When the later price of any one commodity is altered in this way, the recipro cal of its ratio to the price at the first period indicates the variation of this commodity in general exchangevalue.1 Individual prices corrected in this way, com pared with those of the first year, may be called exchange-value prices, because they are reckoned in a money-unit correctly serving as a measure of exchangevalue.12 As a mere matter of calculation, therefore, it is in different how money behaves, since the actual figures may be corrected in either way we prefer to alter them. But in practice there may be a great difference. In the 1 To be exact, the general exchange-value of a commodity so obtained is its exchange-value in all things (including itself): see note on p. 60. It is this general exchange-value of all things in all things that remains constant. See chapter xiii of The Measurement of General Exchange-Value. The dif ference between general exchange-value in all things and general exchangevalue in all other things is practically so small as to be negligible. It has only theoretical interest. 2 In The Measurement of General Exchange-Value, pp. 466-468, 473—474, these were called “ true prices,” on the assumption that the true function of money as a measure of value is to serve as measure of exchange-value. There —pp. 474-477—prices of this sort were worked out in the case of petroleum for the years from 1863 to 1891; and it was noted that Laspeyres had worked out some, and Sauerbeck and D ’Avenel had touched upon the subject. It may be added that Jevons in his The Coal Question (1865, p. 62), remarked that general prices between 1794 and 1860 had fallen from 100 to 62, and the price of coal had risen from 100 to 120, so that, compared to general prices, the price of coal had risen from 62 to 120, or had nearly doubled. This means that coal, rising 20 per cent in actual price, had risen 93 per cent in general exchange-value. More recently Professor Irving Fisher has worked out such prices on several commodities, calling them prices “ in terms of general pur chasing power” or, more simply, “in terms of commodities.” Stabilizing the Dollar, pp. 41, 218. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 121 above hypothetical cases we have altered only the static relations of things after any dynamic influences affect ing them have already had their effect, and we have taken into consideration only the function of money as a measure of value. But money, in its functions as a medium of exchange and a store of value, has dynamic influences upon the course of things. In the two later modifications of our first suppositions, we might have supposed that, instead of average money-incomes rising 10 per cent and average prices falling 5 per cent, money had been made stable first in esteem-value, and secondly in exchange-value. The first change could be brought about by diminishing the volume of money (including the quantity not only of legal-tender money, but of credit substitutes, with allowance also for changes in the rapidity of their circulation) so that average moneyincomes should be reduced by one eleventh; and in the second, by increasing the volume of money so that average prices should be raised by one nineteenth. But if these changes in the money conditions had actually been made, the resultant individual incomes and prices would have been different, with an effect upon their averages. A mere change in our idea of the money-unit at the later period does not alter the relative values and quantities of things, since we are merely correcting the inferences we draw from the way money has functioned as a measure of value. But actually to make the moneyunit stable in either of the two kinds of value, this operation, by altering the volume of money, affects the functioning of money as a medium of exchange and as a store of value, and so has effect upon actual exchanges, upon the distribution of products, and even upon the quantities produced. In an era of industrial progress, 122 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE for money to remain constant in esteem-value or in exchange-value, the volume of money must change differently; and these different changes in the volume of money have influence, and different influence, upon the progress itself. This difference of influence becomes apparent from the following considerations. We may assume the con tinuance of industrial progress, with falling costs and increasing quantities of products per capita — in other words, increasing real incomes and falling esteem-values of commodities. This being presupposed, if money were stable in esteem-value, money-incomes being constant on the average and prices falling, this would benefit all receivers of fixed money-incomes, including creditors, bond-holders, holders of long leases, persons whose salaries or fees are fixed by custom or by law, e. g., office holders, who would resist reductions, and, to a less ex tent, wage-earners, who would have the advantage of position. Among these are idle rich men and women, and the passive elements in production, who would be favored, their real incomes automatically rising without effort on their part; while the active factors in produc tion, entrepreneurs and their partners (share-holders) would be discriminated against, they having to give up some of their gains, produced by their own efforts, to the others. On the other hand, if money were stable in exchange-value, average prices remaining constant and money-incomes rising, all this would be reversed. Now borrowers, share-holders, entrepreneurs would get the increased real income, while the others would not have their incomes increased, except as they might get a slight rise of the interest rate, and might succeed in getting some raise of salaries, wages,' and fees. These FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 123 latter, however, — certainly all creditors qua creditors, — are not discriminated against. The active agents of progress are merely getting the gains they have them selves made, while the passive recipients are stationary, except as they may turn to and become active agents, whereupon they may make the gains that the others do. Of course rising prices may intensify these effects, only they now do discriminate in favor of the active elements and against the others, with injurious effects; and fall ing prices, as the fall approaches stability of money in esteem-value, change the effects into the former, and if the fall goes still further, intensify their injuriousness. These contrary influences, arising from a difference in the distribution of gains, must affect differently the production itself, hindering or promoting its progress, since the one favors idleness more than does the other. Even wage-earners can only receive less in the former case, since they get their wages from the entrepreneurs, but if these have to give up more and more to their creditors, there will be less for them to distribute in wages. It is obvious that progress cannot be the same under these two different behaviors of the monetary system. The question before us is somewhat like the question between the Ptolemaic and the Copernican systems of astronomy. Before Galileo and Newton discovered the laws of motion and of force, it was, from the purely geometric or static standpoint, a matter of indifference whether the sun were viewed as revolving round the earth, or the earth were viewed as revolving round the sun. But since the discovery of those dynamic laws, it has been necessary to adopt the latter view. Similarly, although statically it is indifferent whether money be 124 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE stable in esteem-value or in exchange-value, it may be, dynamically, very important that it should be stable in the one way rather than in the other. In the Middle Ages, when the supply of gold and silver was not suffi cient to furnish all countries with a satisfactory cur rency, and paper-money substitutes were impossible, peoples struggled to get as much of the precious metals as they could and set great importance upon them as instruments of wealth. Later, when these metals be came abundant, and especially when they were supple mented by paper notes, ideas changed and a tendency set in to disparage the importance of money. Money, it was said, is a mere go-between, and economists tried to leave it out of sight as much as possible. All that was necessary, they said, was to keep the money-unit a fixed quantity of metal. A large or a small quantity of money was indifferent, as people could get along as well on a high level of prices as on a low level, or conversely. A change of level also seemed to many of them of little importance. This latter view could be entertained only because during the last two centuries, during which economics was studied as a science, money was actually varying not very much in its values, and mostly in the less harmful of the two directions. Also there were periods of a score or so of years when it gradually fell in exchange-value, and then again rose in exchange-value, so that those who were injuriously affected and who argued for a change in any one of these periods, hardly had time to get a hearing before conditions changed, they were pleased, others were injured, and the argu ments had to be done over from the opposite side. Dur ing these times, most (though not all) economists held the static view, and ignored the dynamic influences of FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 125 rising, falling, or stationary average prices upon the different classes of society, or minimized it. The acci dental fact that during these times these influences were weak enough to permit their being overlooked, ought not to have determined opinions. It is unworthy of economists, if they pretend to be scientists, not to take a broad and comprehensive view of all possibilities. This brings us to our final subject. XXII IN WHICH KIND OF VALUE OUGHT MONEY TO BE STABLE ? A lmost all economists have maintained that money ought to be stable in “ value.” But in which kind of value ought money to be stable? Obviously this ques tion could not come into consciousness until the distinc tion between the different kinds was recognized. And when this distinction is clearly recognized, it becomes an important question, calling for decision. Between the non-recognition and the clear recognition there are many grades, and during this interval confusion of thought was inevitable. At first a distinction was drawn only between use-value and exchange-value. Then there could be no doubt. It may be said that any currency which fills the channels of trade is equally useful, or is stable in use-value, however the “ value” of the moneyunit may otherwise vary. Or it may be said that that is the most useful currency which behaves in the best way, and therefore money must be variable in usevalue until it becomes stable in some other value. In either case constancy in use-value is not enough. Then it was necessary to say — and the economists who made only this division, all said — that money ought to be stable in exchange-value. But we have seen that, be cause of the insufficiency of this dichotomy, the term “ exchange-value” was made to cover also esteem-value, or cost-value, or both. For a time cost-value was erected into the principal claimant. But esteem-value was de veloped out of the idea of use-value, and then became FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 127 a serious rival. Meanwhile exchange-value in its true sense was always held by some economists to be the right kind of value for money to be stable in. There have even been other extraneous kinds of “ value” set up as the proper kinds. In the old monetary science a distinction was made between “ intrinsic” and “ extrinsic” value of coin. The former was its metallic content, the latter the estimation in the money of ac count set upon it, both regulated by government. When the metallic content was altered in the coin represent ing the money-unit, or (which amounted to the same thing) when the estimation set upon the existing coins was altered, — to-day when gold has a variable agio in the current paper-money, — should debts be paid in the same “ intrinsic” or in the same “ extrinsic” value — in the same amount of metal or in the same number of money-units? The answer to this question is unde terminable, since the question does not involve any of the real economic kinds of value. Those who answer that debts should be paid in the same “ intrinsic” value are the holders of the bullionist theory of money, which pretends that the money-unit is a certain weight of a certain metal, to which it must be kept through thick and thin, always. But we all know that if alchemy were successful, these bullionists would be among the first to clamor for a change. On the other hand, those who would allow the government to alter the weight of the metal in the coins at random, and maintain that always a dollar is a dollar and so is the same thing, are equally foolish. It may be added that there have been advo cates even of the opinion that money should be stable in “ value” as expressed “ in the street,” that is, it should be supplied in such quantities as to keep constant 128 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE the rate of interest. This needs only to be mentioned, to be rejected. What is ultimately, fundamentally, though often con fusedly, wanted by every sensible person is that money should be stable in “ value” in one of the four kinds of economic value. Use-value being set aside, there remain three kinds. We have seen that in the course of time cost-value and esteem-value keep pretty close com pany, although they do part company when monopolies become common. Hence these two have often been com bined into one as a labor-standard, over against which is set up a commodity standard, advocated by those who wish money to be stable in exchange-value. Be tween these two camps most clearly lies the bone of contention. If the victory should be won by the laborstandard, it would then remain a fine question whether money should be stable in cost-value or in esteem-value; and the decision could hardly fail to be in favor of es teem-value. If the commodity standard wins, there will be no need of bothering about the distinction be tween the other two. One great error that has run through much of the argumentation on this subject, due to indistinct and in complete recognition of the different kinds of value, has been to use the explanation of exchange-value as settling the question. Those who hold with Ricardo that ex change-value is regulated by cost-value, have generally held that cost-value is “ real value,” as they express it, and have immediately concluded that money ought to be stable in cost-value. Ricardo himself did this because he had only a vague conception of esteem-value, and had no knowledge how exchange-value could be meas ured. Some, but fewer, of the followers of Jevons, Wal FOUR E3NDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 129 ras, and Menger, led by Menger himself, have held that because exchange-value is regulated by esteem-value, therefore esteem-value is “ real value,” and money ought to be stable in esteem-value. The latter have less justi fication than the former for arguing in this way, as they know the other kinds of value, and they know, or ought to know, how exchange-value can be measured. But the explanation about the cause of exchange-value, and in particular about the exchange-value of money, is one thing, and the opinion about the proper behavior of money, or of prices, through the course of time, is an other, and there is no proper connection between the two. Exchange-value exists, however it be explained; and money may be stable in exchange-value just as well as it may be stable in cost-value or esteem-value. If all commodities are falling in cost-value or esteem-value, and money falls in these values equally with their aver age fall, then money is stable in exchange-value. We desire all commodities to fall in these values; then why should we not desire money also to fall in these values, and thereby to remain stable in exchange-value? On the other hand, we might desire it to remain stable in one of these values, and therefore to rise in exchangevalue. The question is: which of these desires is the more reasonable one? Evidently the explanation why money behaves in one or the other of these ways should have nothing to do with settling this question. And to call one of the kinds “ real value” is merely to express a preference, and does not constitute an argument. Another great cause of error of argumentation on this subject has been the desire of the bullionists, especially of the gold bullionists, to defend their standard by any argument that comes readily to hand. Ricardo and his 130 FOUR E3NDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE immediate adherents wrote in a period when prices reckoned in gold were falling, and the idea that they might be falling in agreement, more or less exact, with the fall of costs, also known to be going on, no doubt helped to make them satisfied with a money-unit at tached to a weight-unit of gold. This satisfaction was more consciously expressed in the later period of falling prices from 1873 to 1896. Then the bimetallic contro versy raged. The advocates of bimetallism wished, by injecting silver into the circulation, to make money more stable in “ value,” meaning exchange-value. Their opponents maintained that money was stable in “ value,” some of them meaning cost-value and some of them esteem-value. Between these opposing parties the terms “ appreciation” and “ depreciation” were much bandied about. These terms, of course, contain the same ambiguities as the term “ value.” They may mean a rise and a fall respectively of esteem-value, cost-value, or exchange-value.1 We might be captious and claim that as the root-word in both the terms is pretium or “ price,” they refer properly to rise and fall of exchange-value. But nothing would be gained by this preciosity. Now, many of the gold-advocates of that period tried to make out that the average fall of the cost of production of commodities had been about the same as the average fall of prices, and then they said 1 There is still another common meaning of these terms. If a metallic currency be recognized as the standard (without regard to the fluctuations of its values), then a paper-money pretending to agree with it, if it does not, but has a lower value relatively to that primary money, is “ depreciated.” Such paper-money rarely is “ appreciated,” rising above the value of the other, though this has happened. This is depreciation or appreciation within money itself, between two kinds of money; and so is something entirely dif ferent from the question before us. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 131 that commodities had “ depreciated,” but gold had re mained stable in “ value” ; and this they thought enough. But if their contention was correct, it meant only that commodities had fallen in cost-value, and that money had remained, as they roughly estimated, stable in cost-value. Others were content that wages had re mained fairly stable, since, by Adam Smith’s and Malthus’s laborers’ income standard, they too thought this indicated stability of money in “ value,” though it was but a very imperfect measure of esteem-value. Over against these many of the bimetallists merely asserted that a fall of prices ipso facto was an “ apprecia tion” of money. This is true of “ appreciation” in the sense of a rise in exchange-value. The two sets of op ponents, while seeming to be arguing with each other, were merely describing the same facts in terms with different meanings. Their amplifications of these specious arguments generally came but little closer to reality. The gold advocates urged that since science and industry were lowering costs, and because every article, as it was cheapened, fell in price, therefore everything was as it should be; or, in other words again, that the greater abundance of goods, the greater supply, and the con sequent lower prices of all things were a sign of advanc ing civilization.2 The reply made by the bimetallists was that if gold, too, had been cheapened by science and industry, and become more abundant under the impetus of advancing civilization, the prices of com 2 In the preceding period of rising prices before 1873, some of the gold advocates had even held that it is the function of civilization to increase the demand for goods, and therefore to raise prices! In our present period some faint echoes of this have been heard. 132 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE modities on the average would have been restored, and gold, being carried down the stream of progress on the same level with the commodities, would have remained stable in “ value,” that is, in exchange-value; and as this was not the case, things were not as they should be. To counter this, the other party asserted that gold ought not to be cheapened, and its abundance ought not to be increased, for the very reason that it was used as the standard of “ value” and should remain stable in “ value,” meaning cost-value or esteem-value. Still, however, each side was only adducing its own prefer ences for stability in the one or the other kind of value. Nor could anything decisive result from each side trying to cry down the other by asseverating that value is its kind. Value is any of the four kinds, any one being as good as any other. As a matter of fact, most of those writers and speakers on the opposite sides did not use these specific terms, and did not even recognize clearly either their own or their opponents’ meanings. Their arguments were mostly at cross purposes, and fell on deaf ears. Nothing better than that futile debate shows the need of the different terms for the different kinds of value. It surely is not sufficient to inquire whether during any tract of time our money has been stable in one or another of the kinds of value, and to pronounce it good if only it has been stable in one of them, no matter which one. Yet this is frequently done. At the present day there can be little doubt that one reason why so many economists are slow in supporting Professor Irv ing Fisher’s project for stabilizing the dollar, is that they have a notion at the back of their heads that when prices begin to fall again, there are other kinds of value FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 133 in which money may be stable just as well as in ex change-value. Then why bother specially about stabiliz ing it in only one kind of value? It is this distraction of ideas that needs to be overcome. The real question calling for decision, we may repeat, is as to which kind of value money ought to be stable in, — which kind ought we to desire it, and, if possible, make it, stable in? This involves the inquiry, in which kind of value is the stability of money the best for all concerned, for the whole people? This inquiry is partly one of morality, and partly one of expediency. In the bimetallic contro versy some of the disputants, especially on the propo nent side, did raise their arguments to this higher plane. But no conclusion was reached. Must inconclusiveness reign for ever on this subject? Surely economists will not be doing their duty if they allow it. Let us briefly review some of the arguments. Morality requires that parties to a contract carry it out: the debtor must pay what he promises to pay. In a contract to pay money what is it the debtor promises to pay? On the face of it he generally promises to pay so many money-units. Can he then honestly solve his debt by paying the money-units that the government happens to make current? No, say the bullionists: the money-unit is so many grains of gold, and these he must pay. But as a matter of fact, not one debtor in ten thousand knows how many grains of gold he is contract ing to pay. He regards money as a means to get other things, and to everyone a dollar is a composite idea re presenting so many things he can purchase with it: it is a purchasing power, an exchange-value, or simply a “ value” as it is usually most indefinitely called. A debt, then, must be repaid in the same value that was 134 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE lent, plus interest.3 This is what morality calls for. Had people always used the definite term “exchange-value” there would probably have never been any question but that money ought to be stable in exchange-value. But as “ value” has other senses, the bullionists who want the gold standard at all hazards have been able to claim that a repayment in the given number of grains of gold having an equal value of some other kind is proper. Then, too, the idea that labor is a subject of exchange has come in to aggravate the confusion. Granted that money ought to be stable in exchangevalue or purchasing power, it is said that it ought to be stable in its power to purchase labor, which means that wages ought to be stable. Adam Smith and Malthus, as we know, have asserted that this is sufficient: the monetary system is behaving properly as long as wages are stable, no matter how the prices of commodities may be changing. This, of course, taking as it does only the standpoint of the employer, is absurd. Less absurd, and therefore more likely to be accepted, is the notion that the purchasing power of money ought to be stable over both commodities and labor. Suppose this were so — suppose prices fell and wages rose in such a way as to compensate each other. This could generally hap pen only in case labor were becoming more efficient. 3 It not infrequently happens that creditors stipulate for repayment in a unit of so many grains of gold. Here every idea of value seems to be ex pressly excluded. But the creditors do this because they think gold more likely to be stable in some kind of value than a possible paper substitute. If a government really provided a paper-money stable in the proper kind of value, it might be advisable to forbid such contracts in order to prevent creditors, expecting gold to rise in this value, from taking advantage of the need and ignorance of the debtor to impose a harder bargain than the debtor himself thinks he is getting. FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 135 Then a debtor would repay in money able to purchase more commodities but less labor of greater efficiency. Certainly this money would have risen in purchasing power, all told. The commodity element alone has to do with exchange-value,4and labor is a factor in esteemvalue; and such a standard would be a mixture of two kinds of value. As for esteem-value itself, is it expected that debts should be repaid in equal esteem-value? Take the case of individuals: a poor young man may borrow, and may make repayment after growing rich, his creditor, too, perhaps having advanced in the same way. Nobody expects that he should augment the quantity of money he repays so as to keep the sum of the same esteem-value to himself and to his creditor. But if this is not expected of individuals, how can it be expected, and demanded, of all the individuals who compose a people which is growing richer and whose money, though stable in exchange-value, is falling in esteem-value? Nor is there any good reason for taking a half-way stand between the two standards. Suppose a person loaned money to another in 1800 and their descendants settle the debt in 1900, and that between these dates commodities have become twice as abundant on the whole, per capita, so that their average esteem-value (and probably their average cost-value) has fallen by half, or by 50 per cent. If money-incomes had remained stable and prices had fallen by half, the debt would be paid in the same esteem-value, the creditor receiving twice as great purchasing power as his ancestor loaned. If money-incomes had doubled and prices remained stable, the debt would be paid in the same exchange4 See the footnote on p. 61. 136 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE value, the debtor expending half the labor-cost of the original loan. To let the two parties share the gain equally, money-incomes should rise, not half way, but to the geometric mean between 1 and 2, or from 1.00 to about 1.41J, and prices should fall (on the average, of course) from 2 to 1.41§, or from 1.00 to 0.70f. Then both the average of prices and the esteem-value of money would have fallen by about per cent. (A certain change in the volume of money would have both these effects.) Then, as the debtor’s productive power presumably has increased by 100 per cent, and as the money-capital repaid purchases 41| per cent more than it did, the real capital is produced by him at a laborcost equal to 70| per cent of the labor it cost the credi tor’s ancestor to produce it. Thus the creditor gains as from 1.00 to 1.41J, and the debtor gains as from 0.70f to 100, which is the same as from 1.00 to 1.41 J, and the gain of both is the same. But, as it was not the passive side of the loan that created the improvements, why should the creditor gain at all? Moreover, money in this case would not be stable in any kind of value, and economists would have to revise their almost unani mous declaration that money ought to be stable in value. The arguments from expediency are either a priori or a posteriori. The former go back to the considerations reviewed near the end of the preceding article. In an era of advancing prosperity money stable in exchangevalue does not discriminate in favor of debtors, but money stable in esteem-value (or in cost-value), and rising in exchange-value, does discriminate in favor of creditors. Money falling in exchange-value, on the other hand, discriminates in favor of debtors. Now, an FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE 137 impartial observer should not desire to favor either creditors or debtors, although, if the choice be neces sary, it would be wiser to incline toward the latter. He should not prefer, therefore, a monetary system which takes the gains properly belonging to debtors and gives them, either entirely or in part, to the creditors. This is not a question between social classes, as debtors and creditors do not fall into such, many persons being both at once. But creditors qua creditors are passive and merely wait to have their loans paid back in interest and principal. Debtors qua debtors have to hustle to pro duce the wherewithall to meet their obligations. Indus trial debts are incurred to be used as productive capital, and it is the borrowing capitalists that are interested to make or adopt improvements, while lending capitalists are not concerned how the money is obtained which re pays their loans. Therefore a money stable in esteemvalue (or in cost-value), which gives the gains accruing from improvements to idle lenders without effort on their part, will induce many persons to retire fromactive enterprise, who, under a money stable in exchangevalue, which leaves to the workers all the gains they have produced, would be encouraged to become work ers. Therefore the former system tends to retard, the latter to further, industrial progress. Hence the opinion has been more or less prevalent, ever since it was pro pounded by Hume nearly two centuries ago, that rising prices are better than equally falling prices. If that is so, a fo rtio ri stable prices, which favor neither of the parties to a loan, are better still, besides being more just. And experience — this is the a posteriori argu ment — seems to bear out this opinion. Unfoi’tunately experiments cannot be made in this subject. History 138 FOUR KINDS OF ECONOMIC VALUE alone can be appealed to. History offers few eras of long continuance in which money has been stable in any kind of value. But it offers many eras in which money has fallen in exchange-value (and still more in the other values), and others in which it has risen in exchangevalue (and been more nearly stable in esteem- or costvalue, as we have seen claimed by the gold-advocates). And history shows that even the former eras have been eras of greater prosperity and contentment than the latter. No more details need be gone into here. Only one warning may be added. Malthus argued for his wagesstandard (or a partial esteem-value), that it should be adopted because it was the only workable one. An argument of the same sort has now been advanced by some economists that the commodity-standard (of ex change-value, by means of index-numbers) should be adopted because it is the only workable one. This is not right. If the income-standard (of esteem-value proper) were the correct one, it should be adopted in spite of its difficulty of operation, and the endeavor of economists and statisticians should be turned to make it workable by obtaining a good method of measuring esteem-value and of collecting the necessary data. It is perhaps not so much a piece of good luck that the measurement of exchange-value is now the easiest, as it is a result of the endeavors to make it so, themselves inspired by the belief that this is the kind of value in which money ought to be stable. At all events, the proper purpose of meas uring the exchange-value of money is to prepare the way for somehow rendering money stable in this value. But first of all, this value must be cleared of confusion with the other kinds of value.